A Puzzle for Egoists


In debating the merits of ethical egoism, one thing that should be agreed on all sides is that, in understanding what is in our interests, we need to be referring to long-term interests. No remotely plausible ethical theory holds that what we ought to act on is our short-term interests.

This, however, raises some interesting questions about the weight or importance to be attached to future harms and benefits. It is something economists deal with under the label of “time-preference.” It is a pervasive fact about human motivation that, in general, we would rather have a good thing now instead of later (and a bad thing later instead of now). Part of the explanation for this can be given in “ordinary” terms: there are considerations of risk, uncertainty, opportunity costs and the like that make it reasonable to prefer present benefits to future benefits, to prefer $100 today to $100 next week. However, there’s also considerable reason to think that such “ordinary explanations” do not account for all the phenomena of time-preference. I shall not discuss those arguments because they are not germane here. All that needs to be pointed out for the sake of the argument to come is that people differ in their time-preference: some weigh future costs and benefits heavily in deciding what to do, while others do not.

Now, suppose that you have a person who has a high time-discount-rate. That is, he places a relatively low weight on future harms and benefits compared to current harms and benefits. In everyday language, he is short-sighted.

Suppose also that he is an egoist. What reasons can be given to him for taking the more distant effects of his actions into account? I hope the problem is obvious. It won’t do to say that it is in his interests to take the more distant consequences into account – because his short-term focus partially defines what he takes to be in his interests. A cost that doesn’t show up in the short term isn’t, as far as he can tell, a cost at all. A gain that doesn’t show up in the short-term isn’t, as far as he can tell, a gain at all. The rate of time-preference with which he operates determines what he takes to be in his interests or not.

Now, broaden the scope a little bit. Different egoists can have the same conception of what counts as a benefit (money, health, friendship, longevity, etc.) and operate with the same information, yet reach different conclusions about what they have self-interested reason to do if they have different rates of time-preference.

Where does this lead? Egoism, it seems, even for fully informed and rational persons, yields indeterminate advice about what to do unless you also make some assumption about what the “correct” rate of time-preference is.

And interestingly, there can be no argument that a particular rate of time preference is in your interests, because some assumption about the time-preference rate is needed to derive any conclusions about what is in your interests.

How might this problem be dealt with? I can think of two possibilities, one “clean” (but hard to argue) and one “messy” – neither of which fits comfortably with egoism.

First, the “clean” possibility: One could argue that there is some rational principle requiring one to adopt a particular rate of time preference – perhaps one that counts all benefits and harms equally apart from what were called above “ordinary explanations” of time-preference (one could discount for risk, etc., but not for anything else).

The problem with this for an egoist, of course, is that it cannot be defended in terms of self-interest because it partially defines what self-interest is. If it really is a rational requirement on our deliberation and decision-making, there is at least one rational requirement on action that does not flow from self-interest.

Second, the “messy” possibility: A person, even a short-sighted person, could come to care about the welfare of another for its own sake. But if that other has a lower rate of time-preference, then caring about how that other is doing may involve partially incorporating the other’s rate of time-preference in deciding about what are the likely outcomes of actions. A person’s rate of time-preference may be adjusted in the direction of taking greater account of long-term consequences because of others he cares about.

This is messy because there’s no guarantee that the short-sighted person will run into and end up caring about people who are more far-sighted than he – but it does provide a route along which the short-sighted person’s consideration for the consequences of his action may be adjusted – provided that he is not an egoist.

Either way, it appears that there is no reason that can be given to a pure egoist to adjust the weight he attaches to future costs and benefits. Hence, though ethical egoists constantly insist that they are talking about long-term self-interest, that must, on their theory, either be an arbitrary choice or lead them beyond egoism.

 

 

Comments? I'd love to hear!