Gender, Sexuality and Law:

Thou Shalt Not Forbid Adultery

or

The Application of Democracy to Love

(Part I)

Harper Jean Tobin

Contributing Writer

Having recently married, and also started law school, it was only natural that I should become curious about the legality of adultery. It came as a surprise to me that adultery is still a crime in almost half the states in the Union. But surely, I thought, no one ever gets arrested for adultery anymore. While there has been a long tradition in our country of criminally punishing adultery (did anyone read The Scarlet Letter in school?), enforcement of adultery (and other “morals” offense) laws has waned almost to insignificance since mid-century. The only clear exception to this trend is the military, where court-martials for adultery are still a regular occurrence.

It therefore came as a surprise to many when John Bushey of Lurey, Virginia was convicted and fined in August for having an extramarital affair. While Bushey had at one point vowed to fight the case all the way up to the Supreme Court, he later changed his mind and pled guilty. Though he turned back from challenging the constitutionality of adultery laws, some analysts think he might well have had a case.

Multiple federal courts have ruled that adultery is not protected by the Constitution. Marcum v. McWhorter (2002) is but the most recent of a series of cases, generally concerning employees who were disciplined or fired because of adulterous relationships (interestingly, nearly all of them were police officers). In all of these cases the plaintiffs argued that their sexual relationships were protected by the First and Fourteenth Amendment rights of intimate association and privacy. In all of these cases the courts relied heavily on the landmark Bowers v. Hardwick (1986) - which upheld state sodomy laws - in holding that adulterous relations were not constitutionally protected because they violated long-standing moral and legal traditions.

Bowers, of course, is history - overturned by the even-more-landmark Lawrence v. Texas (2003). In essence, Lawrence stands for the principle that the state must stay out of our bedrooms. In his scathing dissent in Lawrence, Justice Scalia warned that “[s]tate laws against bigamy, same-sex marriage, adult incest, prostitution, masturbation, adultery, fornication, bestiality, and obscenity are … sustainable only in light of Bowers' validation of laws based on moral choices. Every single one of these laws is called into question by today's decision.”

While there has been no end of speculation about the accuracy of Scalia’s prediction, no court since then has ruled on the status of adultery. Earlier this year a Kentucky district court declined to take a stab at it in a case called Cawood v. Haggard. Cawood, an attorney, alleged that local law enforcement invaded his constitutional rights when it investigated his extramarital affair with a client. The court found the case distinguishable from Lawrence because while the latter involved “two adults who [acted with] full and mutual consent,” Cawood’s lover had been the one to complain to the police, suggesting that “her continued participation in sexual activities with Cawood was no longer completely consensual.” Because sexual intimacy that is not fully consensual is clearly not protected, the court saw no need to determine whether Lawrence meant that adultery was constitutionally protected.

Only time will tell what the courts will decide. As is often the case, minority opinions in past cases point the way toward possible resolutions. If Scalia is right - much to his chagrin - adultery laws and discrimination on the basis of adulterous behavior will soon be history. However, the late Justice Blackmun noted in his dissent of Bowers that adultery can be distinguished from sodomy because it involves a breach of promise which society can rightly seek to deter. According to this view, fornication and other “morals” laws, perhaps, must go, but adultery can stay.

The concurring opinion in Marcum suggests a sort of middle ground. While relevant in determining whether it falls within the right of association, it says, “the adulterous nature of [an intimate] relationship alone should not be dispositive.” In addition, courts should consider the purpose, selectivity, longevity, and exclusivity of a relationship. A complex formula, to be sure, but it does jibe nicely with Lawrence’s logic that sodomy is protected because it may be an essential component of a deeper relationship. In essence, the idea is that serious affairs may be protected, but not mere flings.

One thing we can be fairly sure of is that the national trend of repealing adultery laws - as the District of Columbia did this year - will continue. The European Union no longer looks kindly on these laws, either: Turkey recently dropped a proposal to reintroduce adultery into its criminal code amid fears it would harm their application for EU membership.

Less clear is how it might be possible to reconcile an expanded notion of personal liberty and sexual privacy with the realities of deceit, betrayal, and damaged relationships that often attend adultery. Is this properly a matter for the law at all? And if so, how might the law better address adultery in a post-Lawrence world? Further consideration of these issues will continue in the next edition of this column.

Back to Publications