Gender, Sexuality and the Law: Adultery Part II

Harper Jean Tobin

Contributing Writer

            Previously in this column I discussed whether adultery is protected by the constitutional rights of association and privacy. As I mentioned in the prior column, jurists and legal scholars have distinguished adultery from "morals" offenses such as sodomy and fornication on the grounds that adultery involves betrayal and causes real emotional and other harms. Nevertheless, it is private, consensual behavior. How to square the "keep the government out of our bedrooms" approach to privacy rights exemplified in Lawrence v. Texas with legitimate concerns about the harms caused by adultery? In order to begin to answer this question, I think it is necessary to define what adultery is and why it is harmful.

            Adultery, put simply, is extramarital sex. While many feel that extramarital sex is wrong because it violates the Seventh Commandment and society's predominant sexual norms, it is clear that the law is moving away from enforcing private sexual mores and religious beliefs.

            Why else, then, do we find extramarital sex objectionable? Simply put, it must be because it is a violation of the expectation -- often made explicit in wedding vows ("forsaking all others") -- that lasting monogamy is an important component of marriage. To many, perhaps most spouses, this expectation has great emotional import, and violations of it can be tremendously painful.

            There are, however, many ways to hurt or disappoint one's spouse. Other than adultery, those things which the law has generally concerned itself with, such as physical or verbal abuse, are more or less inherently harmful behaviors that do not fall within protected spheres of personal liberty. If someone is upset by a spouse's hobbies, friendships, political activities, visits with family, or taste in books, they can hardly take these matters to court. Marriages are legal relationships, and they are social contracts, yet they are not legal contracts; we cannot sue for breach if we feel we are not being loved, honored and cherished pursuant to our matrimonial vows.

            But, arguably, sex is different. While what two consenting adults do behind closed doors may not be any of the neighbors' business, some feminist scholars have argued that in the context of marriage, an exclusive focus on the consent of participating parties is misleading. After all,  the right to choose one's own sexual relationships arguably involves the right to decide whether or not they will be monogamous, and secret affairs deprive spouses of that right.

Extramarital sex, then, is harmful and unethical because it is deceptive, promise-breaking, and deprives spouses of an important aspect of sexual self-determination. Most of the time, that is. Some social scientific evidence suggests that a substantial minority of married couples have some form of mutual agreement allowing for extramarital sex. (While estimates are contested, there are probably at least as many heterosexual couples in some form of "open" marriage as there are gay and lesbian couples, period.) For these couples, adulterous behavior is arguably neither a personal betrayal nor any of society’s business. On the other hand, the harm of outside sex which is furtive and contrary to a partner's expectations is probably just as great for members of long-term, unmarried couples as it is for cuckolded spouses.

            Having defined the harm of adultery in this way, how should the law treat it? Criminal law seems an ill-suited and probably unconstitutional mechanism for controlling what is essentially a personal slight. We used to recognize torts such as "criminal conversation" and "alienation of affections," but these applied only to the paramour and have largely been abolished anyway. Traditionally, adultery has played a large role in divorce law, both as a grounds for divorce and a factor in dividing up marital property. But nowadays most jurisdictions don't consider non-economic bad behavior in dealing with marital property, and the number of states that require grounds for divorce is shrinking.

            Arguably, adultery is a private matter best left out of the courts; but if we insist on legal remedies, they should focus not on the fact of extramarital sex itself, but on the real harms involved. If one exposes a spouse to a sexually transmitted infection because of unprotected adulterous sex, the exposure and not the adultery should be the cause of action. Similarly, some states allow claims of intentional infliction of emotional distress (IIED) in cases of adultery. Under this tort, the wrongful conduct has to be "outrageous," the distress severe, and the infliction of distress intentional, knowing or reckless. This remedy would not apply when there has been an open marriage, and the high standard of proof ought to deter all but the most serious claims.

            A modest proposal, then: repeal criminal sanctions and prohibit discrimination on the basis of adultery (and any other private, legal sexual behavior); and if (ex-)spouses are harmed enough (or simply craven enough) to drag one another into court over adultery, let it be on a tort claim narrowly tailored to the harm caused.

            Comments? Topic ideas? Write to me at hjt3@case.edu.

Back to Publications