Navigation
Papers by Melberg
Elster Page
Ph.D work

About this web
Why?
Who am I?
Recommended
Statistics
Mail me
Subscribe
Search papers
List of titles only
Categorised titles

General Themes
Ph.D. in progress
Economics
Russia
Political Theory
Statistics/Econometrics
Various papers

The Questions
Ph.D Work
Introduction
Cost-Benefit
Statistical Problems
Social Interaction
Centralization vs. Decentralization

Economics
Define economics!
Models, Formalism
Fluctuations, Crisis
Psychology

Statistics
Econometrics

Review of textbooks

Belief formation
Inifinite regress
Rationality

Russia
Collapse of Communism
Political Culture
Reviews

Political Science
State Intervention
Justice/Rights/Paternalism
Nationalism/Ethnic Violence

Various
Yearly reviews

Philosophy
Explanation=?
Methodology

 


[Note for bibliographic reference: Melberg, Hans O. (1996), Social engineering and rational choice theory, http://www.oocities.org/hmelberg/papers/960509.htm]

[Comment: This observation assumes some familiarity with game theory. I also have to acknowledge that the main ideas in this observation are now my own, but from various works by Jon Elster.]



Social engineering and rational choice theory

by Hans O. Melberg


The starting point for this observation is the thought that a change in the environment (rules, institutions, incentives) will cause individuals to change behaviour - in a predictable way - as they adapt to the new system. An example of this is the belief of many economists that freeing prices and introducing market institutions (private property, bankruptcy laws) automatically will make people adapt their behaviour so that the economy Soviet Union becomes more like the West (more efficient). It is this belief which I believe is closely connected to a rational choice conception of man. If people do not behave rationally, then a change in the environment will not lead to predictable changes in peoples' behaviour.

The driving motor behind rational choice theory is maximization. If people choose their actions in order to maximize a function (such as their utility function), then it is relatively easy to predict how they will behave under a new system with a new set of incentives. The problem is that rational choice theory is both incomplete and inadequate. A theory is incomplete when it fails to tell us what we should do. It is inadequate when people behave according to the predictions of the theory (Elster (1993), p. 181). Thus, my critique of rational choice theory is not only that people sometimes behave irrationally, it is also the fact that sometimes it is impossible to behave rationally because rational choice theory cannot prescribe an action.

That people sometimes are irrational is beyond doubt. Numerous experiments, and everyday experience, gives evidence that we are weak-willed, imperfectly calculating, and norm inspired creatures. The question is, of course, to what extent we behave irrationally compared to rational behaviour. However, in this observation I only want to give one example of norm-guided behaviour which created (creates) problems for the economists' social engineering experiment in Russia and Eastern Europe.

Judy Batt in an article entitled "The "Politics of Economic Transition. (in Developments in Eastern European Politics edited by Stephen White, Judy Batt and Paul Lewis - London, 1993), mentions that cultural attitudes may prevent a reform from having the expected result (p. 223). One example of this could be that Russian enterprise directors view themselves more as "fathers" of their labourforce than profit maximizers on behalf of their owners. This attitude may be traced back to the old Russian commune, in which the head of the village was responsible for all the villagers. However it may also be traced back to the times under communism in which the enterprise director was responsible for sending their labourforce on holidays, for their housing, for social benefits etc.. Hence, traditionally the role of an Russian enterprise director has been very different from the more aggressive profit maximizers of the West. In which way is this difference relevant today?

Today the enterprise directors face a new environment - they are supposed to maximize profit by selling their own products in the free market. One would then expect that they do what seems rational - to cut costs as much as possible - to become more effective. However, empirically we have witnessed that enterprise directors are unwilling to make cuts in their labour force in order to become more effective. Instead they send people on paid (and unpaid) holidays, they reduce the working week, they continue to produce goods even when they cannot sell their products. One must then ask why they did not behave as predicted. One answer could then be that they are motivated by the old norms - by their old culture of protecting the social benefits of the workers in their factory.

One may ask how this is possible since one would expect firms behaving in this way to go bankrupt. The answer is that in an economy where many enterprise directors are motivated in the way explained above, they can avoid the "hard budget constraint" by giving each other credit (or simply by resorting to bartering). This inter-enterprise credit has increasingly become how factory directors keep their factory in business even when it is not really profitable. In addition it was possible to get substantial credits from the central bank. In this way culture has overcome the "hard budget constraint".

One might argue that the it is only a question of time before the enterprise directors are forced to behave rationally. Thus, in the long-run the experiment in social engineering (the big bang!) is going to be successful, as predicted. This may be true, but I have yet to see a good theory of how long time the transition is going to take. Maybe, as Keynes once said, the long run is so far away that we are all going to be "dead." when the experiment becomes successful.

Although the proponents of social engineering might rescue their argument by arguing that people will become rational in the long run, they cannot use this argument if we can prove that in some situations it is impossible to behave rationally. Following Elster I shall discuss two reasons why it sometimes is impossible to behave rationally: Strategic uncertainty and brute uncertainty.

First there is the problem of forming expectations in strategic situations. The problem is this: What I want to do depends on what I think you will do and vice versa. In game theory these situations are solved by backward induction. But the backward induction technique rests on a fallacy. In short backward induction is a fancy name for the following chain of thought "If I do A, he will do B and we end up in X. If I don't do B, he will do C and we'll end up in situation Y. Because the situation in Y is worse than X, I'll do A". The fallacy is to assume that the other person will do C if you do not do A. The reason is that if you do not do A the other person can no longer believe that you are rational, hence the best action for the other person need no longer be C. But, knowing this it may become rational to appear irrational. Then again - none of the players know if the other player really is mad/irrational or is simply faking. because of these problems backward induction may fail. And, if backward induction fails, there is no rational solution to the game.

(One possible solution could be to argue that people assume it is more likely that the player is faking, than really being irrational, since they fear the humiliation of being outsmarted.)

The second source of indeterminacy, is brute uncertainty. In many situations we simply do not know enough to make rational decisions. For example we can never know the optimal level of information about how much information we should collect before we make a decisions (because this leads to an endless chain and because the marginal value of information is not constantly decreasing). We do not know enough about the future to make rational investment decisions (although we pretend). In these, and many more, situations we simply do not know enough to make a rational decision - We might as well use a random decision-maker (although this option is often prevented by our (irrational) addiction to reason - the need to always justify our choices by reasons even when this is impossible).

Now, the reader may ask, how is this related to social engineering. Social engineering relies on being able to predict the outcomes of a new system. This ability rests on the assumption that people are rational maximizers. In this short article I have showed how it sometimes is impossible to be rational. This leaves room for norm-guided and other non-rational (as opposed to irrational) behaviour. We do not know how this kind of behaviour will change in response to a changed environment. This in turn means that social engineering even in theory cannot be predictable. The question is then to what degree predictable social engineering is possible. This leads us to ask to what extent behaviour is, and can be, guided by rational considerations as opposed to irrational and non-rational motivations. Since I do not yet feel confident enough to give an answer to this question, I shall have wait until a later occasion.



Sources
The main source of this article is Jon Elster's article "Some Unresolved Problems in the Theory of Rational Behaviour" (Acta Sociologica (1993) 36:179-190). The main ideas and examples in this observation are from this article and not my own.
Two other sources are:
J. Elster (1979), Ulysses and the Sirens (Chapter 3), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
J. Elster (1996), Doing our level best, The Times Literary Supplement, 29. March 1996, pp. 12-13.

[Note for bibliographic reference: Melberg, Hans O. (1996), Social engineering and rational choice theory, http://www.oocities.org/hmelberg/papers/960509.htm]