Navigation
Papers by Melberg
Elster Page
Ph.D work

About this web
Why?
Who am I?
Recommended
Statistics
Mail me
Subscribe
Search papers
List of titles only
Categorised titles

General Themes
Ph.D. in progress
Economics
Russia
Political Theory
Statistics/Econometrics
Various papers

The Questions
Ph.D Work
Introduction
Cost-Benefit
Statistical Problems
Social Interaction
Centralization vs. Decentralization

Economics
Define economics!
Models, Formalism
Fluctuations, Crisis
Psychology

Statistics
Econometrics

Review of textbooks

Belief formation
Inifinite regress
Rationality

Russia
Collapse of Communism
Political Culture
Reviews

Political Science
State Intervention
Justice/Rights/Paternalism
Nationalism/Ethnic Violence

Various
Yearly reviews

Philosophy
Explanation=?
Methodology

 


[Note for bibliographic reference: Melberg, Hans O. (1996), Rational Irrationality? - Describing and explaining the extreme right in Russia , http://www.oocities.org/hmelberg/papers/961025.htm]




Rational Irrationality?
Describing and explaining the extreme right in Russia

by Hans O. Melberg

Walter Laqueur
Black Hundred - The Rise of the Extreme Right in Russia
Harper Collins, New York, 1993
ISBN: 0-06-018336-5, 317 pages

Introduction
It is important to study the extreme right in Russia because, as Laqueur shows, it was and is one of several players determining the course of Russian history. The question then arises as to how the phenomenon should be studied. Laqueur's answer, as it emerges through his book, can be divided in two. First, Laqueur, being a traditional historian, favours a largely descriptive approach above the more analytic approach used by social scientists. Second, it is clear that Laqueur's approach is passionate in the sense that he does not pretend to be neutral in his description of the ideas of the extreme right. As he writes, "the ideas of the extreme right are not only mad but evil." (p. 296). In this review I shall discuss both of these approaches. In the first section I shall argue that the descriptive approach is justified, but not complete. Moreover, I shall make extensive comments on Laqueur's explanation of irrational beliefs. In the second section I shall argue that Laqueur is right in using the passionate approach as opposed to the detached style of some historians.

1. The descriptive approach
Laqueur's book is mainly, but not exclusively, descriptive. He organises and presents a factual overview of the extreme right in Russia - its historical background, organizations, leading personalities, its doctrines and its influence - without going too much into why the extreme right enjoys a level of support or what factors determine the doctrines of the right. For some, especially social scientists like me, this is often unsatisfying since welike books which try to explain a phenomenon, not simply to describe it. However, lately I have becomed convinced that pure description is also worthwhile because it satisfies an intellectual need - the desire simply to know facts. For example, if I visit a church and I am told that its was built around the year 1000 (ad.) by Olav the Sacred (a Norwegian Viking) this piece of knowledge is in itself pleasing. I know something I did not know before and this satisfies my inborn curiosity. Hence, there is no need to justify the study of history by arguing that we can discover laws or draw lessons which can be applied to today's situation.

Pure description may be boring but good historians, like Laqueur, always make an effort to make the story interesting by providing fascinating details. For example, consider the following sentence which occurs when Laqueur discusses one of the personalities of the extreme right: "Emelyanov's work was interrupted for a number of years after he murdered his wife and dismembered her body. (We shall deal with this part of his career later on.)" (p. 115). The reader is then kept in suspense for about one hundred pages until Laqueur reveals more about the career of Emelyanov (p. 210-11). Admittedly, this may be to create suspense by appealing to the lower instincts of humans (fascination with death and violence). However, in the name of fairness, it is only one of many devices used by Laqueur to make a descriptive account interesting and it starkly exemplify the point that descriptive accounts need not be boring.

Even if the descriptive approach is interesting and intellectually acceptable, we need not restrict ourselves to purely descriptive accounts of history. The already mentioned inborn curiosity of humans is not fully satisfied by knowing the properties of objects (the house is red; the church was built in 1000 ad.), we also want to know how phenomena are related (why is the house red; what determines the doctrines of the extreme right in Russia). Of course, Laqueur's does not avoid these questions altogether. For example, in two places he tries to answer why the extreme right got any support at all. (p. 19 and p. 258). In both cases he ends up explaining the support for the extreme right in terms of people who have experienced rapid social change which in turn trigger psychological fears which fuel right wing extremism. Thus, the Black Hundred (the extreme right in old Russia) is explained by the rootlessness of the first generation of urbanized peasants. Similarly, the appeal of the extreme right today is explained by the changes in the economic (worsening economy), political (chaotic) and national (loss of an empire) situation after the collapse of communism. Both yesterday and today these changes makes people call for a strong hand and a return what is believed to be a more glorious past. Laqueur's story in this respect is plausible and I do not intent to quarrel with him here.

On one point, however, is there reason to examine Laqueur's explanations more closely. This is when he tries to explain the specific content of the doctrines of the extreme right. Why, for example, did the extreme right place so much emphasis on anti-Semitism. Why did some nationalists favour small Russia (to end what they considered was Russian subsidies for the other Republics), while others favoured a large Russian empire (Others, in turn, seems to favour both!). Why were conspiracy theories a prominent belief among the Russian right? The problem in explaining the content and the differences in the doctrines (over time and persons) is interesting because it, to a large extent, is an attempt to explain irrationality. Some of the beliefs of the right were clearly inconsistent and/or without basis in evidence, yet the right continued to hold some of these beliefs. How should one explain this?

In some places, Laqueur argues that the beliefs of the extreme right cannot be explained rationally. As he writes: "Anti-Semitism is not a rational phenomenon, and the endeavour to look for rational explanations has seldom been altogether satisfactory." (p. 109). However, in other places he uses considerations about the rationality of beliefs to explain why a certain doctrine is rejected or advanced. For example, Laqueur argues that the anti-Semitism can be partly explained by the large number of Jews who figured prominently in the revolution (but not later). He also writes that the right did not attack glasnost because it was glasnost which permitted them to express their opinions (p. 159). Yet, I fail to see why irrational people should be prevented by logical considerations of this sort. Clearly, people who believe that the Jews were behind both the Russian Revolution, the collapse of the USSR, the Hitler regime and that Gorbachev was the son of a Turkish woman(!) need not be restrained by rational reasoning when they determine who and what to attack.

The examples could be multiplied. Laqueur sometimes explains the non-existence (or reduced degree of emphasis) of doctrines by arguing that it stretched and strained credulity too much. But this argument relies on the assumption that there was at least a certain level or irrationality which even the extreme right wing could not accept. In short, there is a tension between Laqueur's argument that the phenomena cannot be explained rationally and his actual arguments which sometimes tries to do precisely that.

The tension is interesting because it is important to understand the causes of irrational behaviour. It is important because we may hope to reduce irrationality if we understand its causes (either by institutional design, personal precommitment or simply by being aware of its causes). One prominent theorists in this field is Jon Elster who has done much research on why we have irrational beliefs and, more controversially, irrational desires. This is not the place to go deeper into these theories (the interested reader is referred to Jon Elster (1983) Sour Grapes - Studies in the Subversion of Rationality, See The Jon Elster Page .), however one mechanism mentioned by Laqueur should be discussed. He writes that "It is a well known fact, in the life of individuals as of nations, that facing a clear and present danger may have a sobering effect, curing (at least temporarily) manias of this kind. A person in danger of drowning will understand, one would assume, that the real danger facing him is not being chased by lions in the desert." (p. 177). This seems to me both partly wrong and inconsistent with Laqueur's earlier claims.

Except for the false and misleading analogy between individual persons and nations, the theory is wrong because a crisis may be precisely the time in which irrational beliefs are created. In a crisis the need for a scapegoat is more acute than in calm times. In a crisis the rapid changes make it difficult to form correct beliefs. In a crisis various irrational mechanisms, such as wishful thinking, have greater effects on our beliefs than in clam times. Hence, I do not agree with Laqueur's "well known fact."

Moreover, Laqueur himself cannot agree with the theory. Firstly, he goes on to argue that the crisis did not have the expected effect on the Russians, thus falsifying his original claim. Secondly, and more importantly, the quote is inconsistent with his explanation of why the extreme right enjoyed and enjoys the support it does in Russia. As previously explained this theory rested on the argument that rapid changes create psychological tensions which resulted in right wing support. In other words, crisis produce irrationality, not rationality.

2. The passionate approach
In a previous observation I made some comments on the passionate approach of R. Pipes as opposed to the detached style of E. H. Carr (See, Should historians make ethical judgements?) . The arguments for the passionate approach are the same as before.

First, a spade should be called a spade. Of course, this is not as simple as it sounds because we are using essentially contestable concepts such as "evil." What one author calls evil, another may call good. Nevertheless, I believe we should use these terms. Why should we force the reader to read in between the lines to learn our moral position on the issue? Is it not better to state it openly? Furthermore, historians should not leave the definition of terms such as evil, to philosophers. Instead they should actively enter the debate with historical examples - a feature lacking in many philosophical accounts. By allowing historians to use contestable terms the debates about the precise meaning of terms is enriched.

Second, this is not a question about the evaluation of evidence. When we interpret the degree to which a document proves or undermines an argument we should not attempt to exaggerate its importance even if we want to prove a thesis. This is, of course, elementary. It is also equally obvious that historians and social scientists constantly engage in this king of mistaken belief formation. However, those who argue for the passionate approach do not argue that passionate belief-formation is a good thing.

Third, we are forced to use normative concepts when we want to describe a state of affairs since we need (given time and space limitations) to invent terms which denote a number of features. It is simply impossible to mention all the features of the Soviet system. We may then use the term Totalitarianism as a shorthand. This term, in turn necessarily has normative connotations because it focuses on some features (not all i.e. the selection must be done on a criteria which is normative(?)) and because in the course of a debate what was detached terms gain emotional content (witness the attempt to change the term "handicapped" to get rid of the emotional connotations. The result, of course, is simply, that the new term after some time gets the same negative emotional connotations because the connotations are not inherent to the word, but to the subject it describes).

Fourth, it is desirable to use passionate terms because this is at least one part of what history is about: to investigate which systems created good societies and which created bad societies; which actions were good and which should not be repeated.

These were some arguments in favour of the passionate approach. This does not mean that I favour an inflationary use of contestable terms. There is no point in attaching an emotional adjective to every noun. That would only weaken their effect and reduce its usefulness. Lastly, I should add that I am open to counterarguments against the passionate approach (mail me ).

A disagreement
Before concluding I would like to comment on Laqueur's argument that "The balkanization of the former Soviet Union is a tragedy; it will certainly make democratization infinitely more difficult" (p. 275). This may be the case, but I have heard Zbingniew Brzezinski making the opposite argument: That a continued existence of the empire would make it impossible to create a democratic Russia. In fact, there are mechanisms which could justify both conclusions. The first argument could be supported by the argument that the collapse of the empire stimulated a form of nationalism - the desire for a strong man - which makes democracy less likely. The second argument, as Brzezinski presented it, is that to keep the empire united (especially forcing Ukraine to remain a part of Russia) would require a great strengthening of those institutions which oppose democracy (the army, the security organs, the whole military-industrial complex). Both effects are possible and the net effect is ambiguous and time dependent. In the short run the anti-democratic forces may be strengthened, but in the long run the disintegration may be good for democracy. Thus, I believe it is wrong to be as categorical as Laqueur is.

Conclusion
I have used Laqueur's book as a launching pad for some of my own reflections. Judged by this the book was successful in creating intellectual tension, at least in my mind. As a descriptive book I also found that Laqueur was good. There were not too many surprising facts or analyses, but if one wants an overview of the extreme right in Russia Laqueur is a good place to start.

[Note for bibliographic reference: Melberg, Hans O. (1996), Rational Irrationality? - Describing and explaining the extreme right in Russia , http://www.oocities.org/hmelberg/papers/961025.htm]