Navigation
Papers by Melberg
Elster Page
Ph.D work

About this web
Why?
Who am I?
Recommended
Statistics
Mail me
Subscribe
Search papers
List of titles only
Categorised titles

General Themes
Ph.D. in progress
Economics
Russia
Political Theory
Statistics/Econometrics
Various papers

The Questions
Ph.D Work
Introduction
Cost-Benefit
Statistical Problems
Social Interaction
Centralization vs. Decentralization

Economics
Define economics!
Models, Formalism
Fluctuations, Crisis
Psychology

Statistics
Econometrics

Review of textbooks

Belief formation
Inifinite regress
Rationality

Russia
Collapse of Communism
Political Culture
Reviews

Political Science
State Intervention
Justice/Rights/Paternalism
Nationalism/Ethnic Violence

Various
Yearly reviews

Philosophy
Explanation=?
Methodology

 

[Note for bibliographic reference: Melberg, Hans O. (1997), The pros and cons of state intervention, http://www.oocities.org/hmelberg/papers/970630.htm]

 

The pros and cons of state intervention
A review of Skidelsky's The World After Communism


by Hans O. Melberg

Robert Skidelsky
The World After Communism: A Polemic for Our Times
London, Macmillan, 1995
ISBN: 0 333 62274 x
212 pages


Introduction
To what extent should the state intervene in society? In The World After Communism Robert Skidelsky tries to answer this question. The organizing principle for his answer, is the idea of collectivism which is discussed from different angels in eleven chapters. The main argument is simple:

"Collectivism - the belief that the state knows better than the market, and can improve on the spontaneous tendencies of civil society, if necessary by suppressing them - has been the most egregious error of the twentieth century ... My contention is that this belief in the superior wisdom of the state breeds pathologies which deform, and at the limit destroy, the political economies based on it." (preface, xiii )

I shall argue that the book succeeds quite well in explaining why the idea of collectivism managed (manages?) to grip people's minds. The book is less good at developing a systematic overview of the consequences of collectivist thinking, although there are many scattered ideas.

The causes of collectivism
Collectivism has already been defined as the belief that "scientific" state intervention can improve the "blind forces" of the market. One result of this belief is that "In a collectivist society the state enlists the law to serve its aims; in a liberal society the law sets limits to what a state can do" (p. 19). An example could be laws about smoking. In Norway the state uses laws regulating smoking (e.g. taxes and prohibiting smoking from public buildings) in order to change people's behaviour - to make people smoke less. Another example could be laws against discrimination. Once again, the law is used to discourage certain forms of behaviour which would otherwise have taken place if people were left to regulate themselves. A third example is the use of the State to redistribute income - a form of intervention disliked by liberals (in the Europeans sense of the word) and favoured by the collectivists. These examples illustrate the difference between the collectivist and the liberal use of the State and the law.

The degree of collectivism in different countries can, Skidelsky argues, be measured by four important variables: The fraction of output spent by the government; The fraction of output produced by the state; The amount of interference with cross-border trade (tariff, quotas, subsidies, exchange controls, restrictions on migration); And, the progressiveness of the tax system (p. 24). Admittedly, these are rough and imperfect measures, but I shall not argue about these details.

What are the causes of collectivism? In other words, why and how did people start to believe that we could and should use the state to improve on the outcome of the free market? Skidelsky provides a long list of causes, some obvious, some interesting and some dubious.

One obvious and often cited cause of larger government intervention, is war. In the words of Skidelsky:

"The war seemingly disclosed a world of reality which corresponded to the world of the collectivist imagination; it showed that collectivist organizations worked, and it created revolutionary situations which enabled collectivists to seize power ... War has thus been a powerful agent of collectivism." (p. 45)

Another cause of the ideas of collectivism, was the rise in large corporations. Much in the same way that wars demonstrated the practical feasibility of large scale state intervention, the large corporations showed the feasibility of large scale planning of production. Later people discovered that the seemingly innocent inference from "private planning works" to "state planning works" was flawed.

A third factor making intervention feasible, was the growth of science. New forms of communication, increased power of calculation, and new knowledge in general made the impression that the administration of society was a mere question of accountancy on a large scale. Not only did science make intervention look feasible, it also made it look desirable. Intervention in the natural sciences were successful (breeding etc.), and vulgar social-Darwinism made it look like a country had to have active intervention to survive international competition. In short science appeared to make collectivism more feasible and desirable.

As mentioned, showing that collectivism became more feasible is not enough; we must also show why people thought that intervention was desirable. An important contributor to this idea, was depression (1873-96 and the 1930s). On the surface it appeared that the free market did not produce optimal results - large scale unemployment being the most obvious sign of this failure. This was clearly an important factor making people believe that planning could improve things: The market was bad, so planning must be better. One might argue that the inference was incorrect - that the depression was cause by intervention (the Hawley-Smoot tariffs), and not by the free market. Regardless of the truth of this argument, it is still correct that the depression was perceived as a free-market phenomena, and as such it contributed to the belief that intervention was desirable.

A second cause of the rise of the perceived desirability of collectivism, was modernization. In short, "'Modernization' enlarged, exposed or created 'gaps' in inherited systems of social self-regulation which the state was bound to fill ..." (p. 33). Examples include the increased need for education, health insurance, and regulation as a consequence of industrialization and urbanization. A second, and related, feature of modernization was the growth of international trade (p. 34). Increasing possibilities for trade gave rise to collectivism, since it was believed that intervention in trade could improve a country's international ranking. This kind of economic nationalism led to protectionism (tariffs, quotas) and intervention in home production (subsidies and state ownership of factories).

Another powerful force making people believe that intervention was desirable, was ideology. Specifically, Marx's concept of exploitation served, in the words of Skidelsky, as the "charter myth" used to justify intervention. The argument being that it was only fair to tax the rich and give the money to the poor since the tax represented "the unpaid portion of working-class toil" (p. 30). In brief, the workers were underpaid, the capitalists overpaid, and intervention could improve this imbalance [note: see Jon Elster's Making Sense of Marx for an interesting argument that the workers really were underpaid; Paying each worker according to marginal revenue means treating each worker as if he were the last to be hired, but all workers cannot be the last to be hired]. Later, the ideas of Keynes was used to justify state intervention, although Skidelsky often points out that Keynes himself was a liberal who would not have accepted everything that later was done in his name. In any case, ideas and ideologies contributed to the belief that intervention was desirable.

Skidelsky does not only discuss the factors explaining the rise of collectivism. The popularity of collectivism changed over time, and to explain the reduced popularity one must focus on factors working against-collectivism. Once again they conveniently come in a pack of three: The defeat of fascism in World War II; The success of the German and the Japanese economy; And, a number of leading intellectuals who exposed the logical and empirical weaknesses of collectivism.

The defeat of Germany, Italy and Japan in World War II greatly reduced the prestige of the fascist version of collectivism. However, the war also served to enhance another version of collectivism - Communism. Being on the winning side of the war gave Stalin and Communism international prestige and sympathy. The more unsympathetic features of the regime - like the Stalinist terror and GULAG - was partly unknown, partly ignored. One reason for this, Skidelsky suggests, was that there were no visual images of Stalin's concentration camps. In contrast, there was overwhelming visual evidence from Germany's concentration camps. In this case pictures spoke louder than words, and maintained the illusion that the left wing version of collectivism was different than its right wing brother.

After the war, the US greatly contributed to the building of liberal societies in Japan and Western-Europe though its direct involvement in Japan, and more indirectly through the Marshall aid. Without this aid, the chances of a collectivist parties (Communism) coming to power would have been much higher. Also, the very success of these countries - the German wirtschaftwunder and the remarkable recovery in Japan - contributed to the belief that liberalism worked. In contrast, the fact that East Germany had to build the Berlin wall to keep its citizens from fleeing, contributed to the belief that collectivism did not work.

The third factor working against collectivism, was several new and important intellectual contributions. Popper exposed the unscientific basis for "scientific-Marxism" in his The Poverty of Historicism. The argument was simple - a theory is scientific if there is evidence which can be used to falsify it. Parts of Marxism can certainly be falsified (like the theory of the falling rate of profit), can be falsified, but as a body of theory it was unfalsifiable. Whatever evidence one threw at the Marxist, they could come up with a theoretically possible (but often empirically implausible) way of fitting the observation to confirm their own world view. For some illustrations, consider first Marx prediction that the workers would experiences growing immiseration - a prediction which soon was proved wrong. To explain away this problematic piece of evidence against Marxism, Lenin invented the theory of Imperialism as the highest state of capitalism (p. 36 in Skidelsky). Briefly, the argument was that immiseration was not taking place because the capitalists had bribed the workers with profit from their colonies [note: This is empirically wrong since the costs of having colonies often exceeded the monetary benefits for countries as a whole]. These examples can be multiplied: When social mobility increased, this was not a real advance, rather it was a plot by the capitalist class to deprive the workers of their best and brightest leaders; When the state introduced legislation which favoured the workers, the theory that the State was a tool for the capitalists had to be amended by a theory of the relative autonomy of the state. In this way Marxists continually found refuge in more and more implausible arguments against evidence that Marx was wrong. An ideology with these self-confirming qualities could never be scientific - it could not be logically proved or disproved, as Popper pointed out.

Another important intellectual development, was Hayek's Collectivist Economic Planning (1935) and The Road to Serfdom (1944). Once again the argument was relatively simple: It was practically and theoretically impossible to make efficient plans without free-market prices. The practical problems should be obvious - imagine trying to decide how much should be produced of thousands of goods when the production of each good also depend on the other (if you want more refrigerators you also have to produce more steel). Theoretically, without information about prices there is simply no way of determining whether some investments are more profitable than others. The theory is that those investments with the highest net benefit (benefit minus cost) should be chosen. However since there are no real prices there is no way good way of estimating the costs of a project. Hence, central planning could not solve what has been called the problem of economic calculation.

Based on Skidelsky I have so far presented nine factors which made the idea of collectivism more or less appealing. Three focused on the increase in the perception that state planning was feasible (war, large corporations, science), another three centered on the idea that intervention was desirable (depressions, modernization, ideology), and the last three factors emphasised forces working against both the feasibility and desirability of collectivism (defeat of Fascism, success of Germany and Japan, intellectual developments). I shall now go on to discuss the more interesting question of the pros and cons of intervention - as opposed to the sociological history of the idea of intervention.

The pros and cons of state intervention
Whether intervention is good or bad - or more importantly whether the net effect of intervention is positive or negative - should be determined by examining the consequences of the intervention. Sometimes Skidelsky seems to disagree with this, as when he writes that:

"The issue here is not whether state taxation and spending policies, or public ownership of industry, or regulation, create a society more of less efficient or just than it would have been in the absence of such features. It is that they create a society which is different from what it would have been. Herein lies the chief flaw of collectivism. It is that, outside exceptional circumstances, the degree of consent for the reshaping of the economy and society is always more limited than the ambitions of the collectivists." (p. 26).

At least the first part of this quotations suggests that state intervention is inherently an evil thing, much the same was as murder is inherently an evil thing. If this is true we need not examine the consequences of intervention, However, I think most people take a more pragmatic view: State intervention is more acceptable when it has consequences which we on balance find desirable, such as promoting material well being or justice.

Even if we agree to focus on the consequences of state intervention, we need to distinguish between the static and the dynamic consequences of intervention. For example, a monopoly may be statically inefficient in the sense that it charges too high prices compared to the competitive outcome. However, one might argue that monopolies nevertheless are good since they are dynamically more efficient than competitive firms. Precisely because they can charge high prices they earn more profit, which means that they can invest more in research and development. This, in turn, means that they might develop more efficient production techniques which ultimately will benefit the consumers. One may doubt the empirical validity of this argument, but at least it illustrates the difference between static and dynamic efficiency. The question is then: What are the static and the dynamic benefits and costs of state-intervention?

Skidelsky presents four arguments which he thinks are valid reasons for the state to intervene, or as he puts it "state activity which supports a liberal society ..." (p. 20). First, the state should use the law to protect people from harms - for example food standards and licensing laws. Second, the state should provide public goods, such as defense and street-lightening. Third, the state may provide a social safety-net since the market fails to provide this kind of insurance. Fourth, the state may help to promote self-regulation - for example creating professional standards. A unifying concept for all four arguments is that of market failures - intervention is justified when the market fails (and the intervention is no worse than the disease itself). Hence, Skidelsky's view is that "States may be regarded as existing to fill the inevitable gaps in the protective and regulatory mechanisms of civil society... " (p. 20).

All of the arguments above, Skidelsky thinks, can be abused. The concept of harm can become too wide, thus the first argument - to protect people from harm - can be used to create a 'nanny' state. The existence of mixed goods and externalities can be used to justify almost any intervention - such as strict laws against smoking. The argument based on a social safety net can easily spill over into an argument for using the state to redistribute income from the rich to the poor. Finally, state intervention to help intermediary organization can develop into corporatism - a situation in which the organizations function as an extended arm of the state i.e. they loose their independence.

There is little new in these arguments, and the warning against the abuse of the arguments for intervention is not too enlightening. The problem is that Skidelsky's arguments are too general to be helpful to determine the exact limit between acceptable and unacceptable interventions. Most people accept that the government has to provide some regulation to protect people from harm. It is equally obvious that the concept of harm can become too wide, thereby producing too much bureaucracy and regulation. The difficulty, however, lies in deciding exactly when we use a too wide definition of harm. Exactly when does state intervention turn from being supportive of liberal order into undermining this order? Have we gone too far when we have laws prescribing seat-belts? Are laws restricting smoking in public buildings collectivist, or a justifiable intervention to protect the non-smokers from unwanted pollution? To say that the concept of harm, or the concept of externalities, can be abused is thus not very enlightening since an argument which you think is too wide, may be perfectly acceptable for another person.

Against the four mainly static argument for state intervention, Skidelsky presents several dynamic arguments against intervention. These all deal with "the logic of collectivist creep" (p. 65), meaning that what appears to be a good intervention is bad if we consider its consequences over time. In effect, one intervention leads to another and so on. We may call this the "the slippery slope argument."

One such slippery slope, results from intervention in international trade. Initially one may (mistakenly) believe that this is a good intervention - enabling the country to become more self-sufficient, competitive and wealthy. However, Skidelsky argues that if we want to manage international trade (tariffs, quotas), we are also forced to engage in some planning on the national level (p. 65). This in turn, leads to more planning and eventually nationalization and restrictions on emigration and immigration. I must admit I failed to see the necessity of this logic, though I concede the that it is a possible tendency.

A more interesting "slippery-slope-argument" is Hayek's statement that except in a war there is not enough voluntary consent to support government intervention. Thus the attempt to change people's behaviour fails, leading to calls for even stronger and more intervention (coercion) in order to fulfil the aim. This kind of logic leads to an "inexorable tendency for democratic planning to become totalitarian planning." (p. 80). For example, assume the government prohibited all smoking tomorrow. It seems likely that this would require quite a lot of coercion. Now, assume instead that the state puts a tax on cigarettes. Unless one counts the tax as coercion, this measure seems quite likely to succeed reasonable well. The tax might, however, increase smuggling which in turn leads to new laws and increased intervention in civil life (to prevent smuggling). Despite this tendency, I think it is exaggerated to argue that it necessarily will lead to totalitarianism.

More generally, I think it is possible to maintain a mixed system. The logic of the slippery slope argument is that we have to end up in one extreme solution: a very small state or a very large state. I think the choice is more a question of degrees - more of less state intervention. Maybe the most important mechanism making this balance possible, is the existence of democracy. As Skidelsky shows, when people think there is too much regulation, they simply elect a party which promises to reduce the amount of intervention. True, this mechanism is imperfect, for example even in a democracy a majorty might ignore state-interference with minority groups (e.g. religion). However, these faults are also reducible, for instance through constitutional rights. Thus, I do not think the choice is between extreme versions of liberalism or collectivism, but between degrees of state intervention.

Lastly, I am unconvinced about the argument that redistribute policies are inherently evil. Progressive taxation - to tax the rich more than the poor - is attacked by the liberals as theft from the rich. What we earn, the argument goes, we should be free to spend as we want. Thus, it is a question of rights: We are entitled to the fruits of our own labour. I do not disagree with this, but the problem is that we should also consider a number of other rights that people have. For example, one might claim that people have the right to equal opportunities to make money (which implies equal access to a good education). Or, more basically, that people have the right to food and medical care. The problem, then, is that some rights might clash (at least in a world of scarce resources), and to focus exclusively on the right to keep everything you receive is to ignore the other rights people also have.

Overall, I was not too impressed by Skidelsky's discussion of the costs and benefits of state intervention. It is not novel, it is not systematic, complete or rigorous, and it relies more on general arguments than concrete examples. Most importantly, we cannot use his arguments to determine the degree to which the state should intervene since he relies on inherently subjective notions like "too wide definition of harm" to dismiss some interventions. As I have argued, there is no agreement on when the definition of harm becomes too wide. Indeed, this is precisely the disagreement which we would want to discuss.

Recommendations and interpretations
The sub-title of the book, A Polemic for Our Times, indicates that there should be some lessons for current policy formation. In addition to the main focus of this review - state intervention - I would like to discuss a two of Skidelsky's other recommendations. First, the warnings about expanding NATO. Second, the advice not to give large-scale financial aid to Russia.

NATO should not be expanded eastwards, Skidelsky thinks, since this would weaken the position of the progressive forces in Russia (p. 185). Instead we should develop a new all-European security system which includes Russia. I have no firm opinion on this issue. However, it seems like the possibility of gaining membership in NATO has positive effects on some policies in many Eastern European countries. For example, countries are more eager to conclude old border disputes, to respect the right of minorities, and to implement market reforms since this increases their chances of NATO membership. In this way NATO membership is a good way of promoting what I think are right policies for these countries. Whether this beneficial effects should be scarified in order to please Russia is a question I cannot answer.

On the question of financial aid to Russia, I agree with Skidelsky. The Marshall aid worked because the institutional structure of these countries was already geared towards a market economy. Russia is totally different (see p. 69). Much of the aid would end up in the hands of the wrong people. Moreover, foreign intervention like this breeds hostility and rent-seeking. It feeds the paranoid belief that the West governs Russia (with the aim of turning it into a colony which only produces raw-materials), and it will focus the attention of the elite on getting a share of the aid instead of focusing on productive activities. No, Russians must put the Russian house in order. (Incidentally, there seems to be a small contradiction between the recommendation not to give financial aid on p. 70, and the recommendation to "gamble" "generously" on the new Russia which includes the argument that "Western investment in the Russian state is deemed by hard-headed self-interest [to prevent collapse]" (p. 185))

Conclusion
I am uncertain whether to recommend this book. One the one hand, it is highly readable, the scope is very large. and many of the arguments are important. On the other hand, it is not novel, systematic or rigorous. In sum, this is a good book if you want a relatively short, easy and good overview of some of the issues in modern political economy. However, if you want a complete academic treatment of state intervention your desire is better served by other books.



Afternote:
1. I believe there is a small mistake on page 113. The article giving the communist the leading role in Soviet Union, was not article 16, but article 6.
2. The following quotation deserves space:

"The trend of political economy in the twentieth century may be summed up as follows. The tremendous increase in the political, administrative, and organizational capacity of the state, together with its power of economic calculation, has tempted it to do too much. As the performance of states worsened, so the resistance to their pretensions grew, forcing a retreat freom collectivism back to the market economy. This is the meaning of the transistion through which we are living." (p. 26)

[Note for bibliographic reference: Melberg, Hans O. (1997), The pros and cons of state intervention, http://www.oocities.org/hmelberg/papers/970630.htm]