Navigation
Papers by Melberg
Elster Page
Ph.D work

About this web
Why?
Who am I?
Recommended
Statistics
Mail me
Subscribe
Search papers
List of titles only
Categorised titles

General Themes
Ph.D. in progress
Economics
Russia
Political Theory
Statistics/Econometrics
Various papers

The Questions
Ph.D Work
Introduction
Cost-Benefit
Statistical Problems
Social Interaction
Centralization vs. Decentralization

Economics
Define economics!
Models, Formalism
Fluctuations, Crisis
Psychology

Statistics
Econometrics

Review of textbooks

Belief formation
Inifinite regress
Rationality

Russia
Collapse of Communism
Political Culture
Reviews

Political Science
State Intervention
Justice/Rights/Paternalism
Nationalism/Ethnic Violence

Various
Yearly reviews

Philosophy
Explanation=?
Methodology

 

[Note for bibliographic reference: Melberg, Hans O. (1997), Why culture should not be treated as a residual, www.oocities.org/hmelberg/papers/971025.htm]

 

Why culture should not be treated as a residual
Positive proofs vs. Proofs by default

by Hans O. Melberg


Introduction
In his book How Russia Became a Market Economy Anders Aaslund writes:

"Many Russian peculiarities have been inferred as objections to reform. One objection is the backwardness of Russian political, economic, or legal culture. With my strong belief in modern institutional economics, I treat culture as a residuum that can explain what cannot be explained with other means" (p. 10).

I interpret this to imply that explanations based on rational self-interest are always better than explanations based on culture. Hence, if he had to choose between two explanations of the same phenomena, Aaaslund would always choose the "rational" explanation, not the "cultural explanation" (a lexicographic preference). Only if he cannot find a rational explanation is he willing to consider a cultural explanation.

The quotation from Aaslund is not isolated. In fact, most economists and many political scientists argue that culture should be treated as a residual (see for instance Elkins and Simeon's article. Culture as a residual cited in the bibliography of my "The Cultural Approach to Russian Politics" at www.oocities.org/hmelberg/papers/papers.htm). I disagree with this, and in this short essay I want to explain why.

The arguments
I have three arguments. First, rational choice does not win by default: I want concrete evidence of the mechanisms involved, the linkages and the assumptions in the rational explanation. This can be used to judge the reliability of the rational explanation, for instance by examining the empirical plausibility of the assumptions and the empirical strength of the links. Second, culture does not win by default i.e. the fact that you cannot find a rational explanation does not imply that a cultural explanation is true. Once again you need positive evidence; a demonstration of the mechanisms involved. And, once again the plausibility of this explanation can be judged from empirical examination of these links. Third, and finally, it is perfectly possible that the probability of a rational explanation being true is less than the probability of a cultural explanation being true. Hence, when faced with two phenomena it is wrong to always choose the rational explanation no matter how implausible and outlandish it is. In short, sometimes a cultural explanation, or some other explanation, is more plausible and should be given preference.

Before I go on to illustrate these three arguments (and I mean illustrate, all my major points have already been made, the rest is only examples!), I want to make one qualification: I am not against explanations based on rationality. People usually try to do what they think is best for themselves (rational selfishness). However, my point is that I want positive evidence for this in every specific case (to avoid the fallacy of composition), and this evidence takes the form of tracing and empirically testing each step in the chain, each mechanism in the explanation. This testing gives rise to a probability of an explanation being true, and this probability determines which explanations is the best. One cannot, and should not, give lexicographic preference to the rational explanation.

With this qualification in mind, I shall give some examples to explain what I mean, starting with the third claim that even if we can find a rational choice explanation it is not always superior to alternative explanations.

Are explanations based on rational choice always superior to other explanations?
Consider the claim that religion can be explained by parents wanting to reduce the rate of discounting in their children (in other words, make them more patient). One "rational" strategy for doing so, might be to make your children religious (suggested by Gary Becker). The continued existence or religion, the continued upbringing of children by parents in a religious way, is explained by a rational choice: The parents want their children to be better off, to be better off they have to be patient, being religious makes them more patient - so parents give their children a religion. And, this is only one way of explaining religion rationally. One might also argue, as Becker does (according to Jon Elster) that the upper-classes use religion to pacify the lower classes - to protect themselves from revolutions. In short, religion can be explained by rational choice.

My immediate feeling is well captured by Jon Elster who writes that:

I find this analysis intrinsically implausible and devoid of empirical support. Had Becker looked at the historical literature, such as the chapter on "The Transforming Power of the Cross "in E.P. Thompson's The Making of the English Working Class,6 he would have found that for religious indoctrination to work the indoctrinators have to believe in the religion themselves.7 Self-consciously manipulative attempts to inculcate religious and political ideologies invariably fail.
(from Elster's review - "More than Enough" - of Becker's Accounting for tastes, available at the Jon Elster Page: www.oocities.org/hmelberg/elster.htm)

To claim that an explanation based on rational choice is always superior to alternative explanations, is to ignore that the plausibility or an argument depends on many factors. Of course, the theoretical possibility that religion is simply a tool of the oppressor to keep the oppressed down, or a tool used by parent to induce more patience, does exist. However, the mere possibility that religion can be explained in this way, does not make me believe it: I want positive evidence that this is actually the way religion is used.

When faced with two explanations for religion, the correct approach is then not to ask "which is based on rational choice" and "which is based on a non-rational conception of man" (for example, a psychological explanation based on the need for meaning). Nor is it correct to always prefer the explanation based on rational choice. The correct procedure is to test various explanations, to examine the links empirically (and logically) and decide which explanation is most plausible.

Rational choice does not win by default
In his book Rational Expectations Steven Sheffrin repeatedly reports tests which could not reject the theory of rational expectations (which is the null hypothesis in this case), and this is interpreted to support the theory of rational expectations (see p.17, 21, 52-54, 142-3, 156). In my opinion, and I think Sheffrin would agree, this is not a very convincing or powerful argument in favour of rational expectations. By convention the null hypothesis is very difficult to reject (at the 5% significance level), and the failure to reject it does not constitute strong evidence in favour of it.

There are, in fact, quite a lot of micro evidence that people often do not have rational expectations. (See, for instance, Kahneman & Tversky & Slovic: Judgement under uncertainty , H. Simon (bounded rationality) and D. Hausmann on preference reversal in The Inexact and separate science of economics). Now, I do not want to turn this into an essay about the truth of rational expectations in general. My point is only this: To believe in rational expectations we need positive evidence, not simply the failure to establish an alternative (and equally general) expectations model. This fallacy, I believe is exemplified by some of the articles considered in Sheffrin's book.

One might say that you cannot beat something by nothing - that you should believe in rational expectations as long as you do not have an alternative. I disagree. It is perfectly possible to be agnostic - do admit that we do not know. The choice is not between the extremes - yes or no. rather it is a question of more and less faith, as well as the intellectually respectable option of "uncertainty": I do not know!

Culture does not win by default
Faced with a puzzling phenomena that apparently cannot be explained by rational choice, it is no necessarily true that a cultural explanation is most plausible. Once again, only positive evidence can convince me of the plausibility of the cultural explanation. By way of illustration, consider the following: Some might argue that employees are guided by norms about fairness when they do not reduce the wage to the lowest possible given the market: In other words, the "irrational" and high wage level is interpreted as a failure of rationality, and as evidence in favour of a norm-based explanation.

However, the same phenomena, it turns out, can be explained by rational choice. Given that the employees are humans with emotions - so they might work less hard if they feel their pay is too low (and they are more likely to shirk if the potential penalty is lower i.e. the efficiency wages argument) - it becomes rational for employers to keep a wage above the market clearing level. The cut in wages is not worth the gain since productivity will also fall if you cut wages.

The lesson is this: The apparent failure of simple and rational profit maximization, does not constitute good proof in favour of a cultural explanation. It only teaches us to look further for better explanations of whatever type that the data tell us is most plausible - rational, cultural or some other explanation.

One should also note that there are many alternatives to a rational explanations, and culture is only one of these alternative. We could use psychology (cognitive failures) to explain irrationality, we could use norms to explain irrationality, we could use ideology to explain irrationally and so on. This implies that the rejection of on, does not constitute good evidence in favour of another approach - since we do not know which alternative is the most likely to be true. If there had been only two mutually exclusive alternatives the inference (rejection implies confirmation of alternative) would be correct. For instance, if I reject the hypothesis that you are pregnant, then it is safe to infer that you are not pregnant. However, in our case a cultural explanation is only one of several alternative to a rational explanation.

Conclusion
The arguments made in this essay may seem obvious (and repetitive). However, the points are continually being ignored by many social scientists, as I have tried to show with some examples. Aaslund wants to treat culture as a residual (as does Elkins and Simeon), Becker and many other economists (e.g. Steven Landsburg: See the first pages of his book

The Armchair Economist seem to give rational choice not only a favourable position (as a first working assumption), but a lexicographic preference: Explanations based on rational choice are by assumption superior to other explanation, no matter how implausible they are empirically. In real life, imperfect calculative abilities, emotions, culture and norms also do play a role. Even Aaslund, for instance, admits that the outcome of reforms in Russian (under Gorbachev) was different from reforms in China because, amongst other reasons, there were many "entrepreneurial" Chinese people - a factor which might be viewed as cultural (p. 15). (It implies that the market economy requires more than rational selfishness to work, it also seems to require some kind of entrepreneurial spirit). Now, as for the degree to which people are rational, emotional, selfish, guided by tradition and so on, I remain agnostic. All I know is that the only way to find out is to do empirical studies, as opposed to assuming that one alternative is true or false.


[Note for bibliographic reference: Melberg, Hans O. (1997), Why culture should not be treated as a residual, www.oocities.org/hmelberg/papers/971025.htm]