Navigation
Papers by Melberg
Elster Page
Ph.D work

About this web
Why?
Who am I?
Recommended
Statistics
Mail me
Subscribe
Search papers
List of titles only
Categorised titles

General Themes
Ph.D. in progress
Economics
Russia
Political Theory
Statistics/Econometrics
Various papers

The Questions
Ph.D Work
Introduction
Cost-Benefit
Statistical Problems
Social Interaction
Centralization vs. Decentralization

Economics
Define economics!
Models, Formalism
Fluctuations, Crisis
Psychology

Statistics
Econometrics

Review of textbooks

Belief formation
Inifinite regress
Rationality

Russia
Collapse of Communism
Political Culture
Reviews

Political Science
State Intervention
Justice/Rights/Paternalism
Nationalism/Ethnic Violence

Various
Yearly reviews

Philosophy
Explanation=?
Methodology

 

[Note for bibliographic reference: Melberg, Hans O. (1997), Nationalism: Is it definable, important and worthy of attention?, www.oocities.org/hmelberg/papers/971210.htm]

 

Nationalism
Is it definable, important and worthy of attention?

by Hans O. Melberg


Ethnonationalism: The Quest for Understanding
Walker Connor
Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey, 1994
234 pages, ISBN: 0-691-02563-0

Introduction
Why should social scientists be interested in nationalism? First of all, there has to be a minimum of agreement on the definition of a nation and nationalism. Second, it must be shown that nationalism has important behavioural consequences. However, agreement on the definition and demonstration of consequences are not enough. Sometimes a phenomenon is both well defined and important, and yet beyond our understanding. Hence, a third pre-condition for our interest in nationalism, must be that it is susceptible to scientific investigation.

I cannot pretend to give good answers to the three questions above. My weak knowledge of the theoretical literature, and my less than certain grasp of the relevant historical details, combine to make this impossible. Instead, I want to use the collection of articles in Walker Connor's book Ethnonationalism: The Quest for Understanding as a launching pad for some reflections relevant to the three questions above. Moreover, to make these reflection as interesting as possible, I have chosen to focus on topics which I feel I know something about, such as rational choice theory and methodology.

Is it important?
The second question - that of importance - is seemingly the easiest question to answer. Nationalism has been used to explain earth-shattering events such as the break-up of the Ottoman Empire, Austria-Hungary, and most recently the Soviet Union - just to mention a few examples. Moreover, it is not just a force of the past; the Kurds, the Basques, the Palestinians, and many other groups and conflicts testify to the continued importance of nationalism. In sum, nationalism has behavioural consequences which makes it well worth closer examination.

Still, it is possible to argue that factors other than nationalism was, and is, the driving force behind the events ascribed to nationalism in the paragraph above. Maybe economic variables best explain the collapse of the Soviet Union? Maybe religious factors were more important than nationalism in the break-up of the Ottoman empire? Maybe the Palestinian movement is best understood in term of the personal interests of an elite?

Connor disagrees:

Explanation of behaviour in terms of pressure groups, elite ambitions, and rational choice theory hint not at all the passions that motivate Kurdish, Tamil, and Tigre guerrillas or Basque, Corsican, Irish, and Palestinian terrorists. Nor at the passions leading to the massacre of Bengalis by Assamesc or Punjabis by Sikhs. In short, these explanations are a poor guide to ethnonationally inspired behaviour (p. 74)

Thus, Connor argument is that explanations in terms of relative economic deprivation, elite theory, and rational choice are falsified by historical experience. History shows that nations demand independence regardless of their economic situation compared to the rest of the state. The Basque are better off than the rest of Spain; the Irish were worse off than the rest of the United Kingdom. History, Connor claims, also shows that religious and class bonds are weaker than ethnic ties. Witness, for instance, the failure of Lenin's call to the working class not to participate in World War I, and the failure of religious leaders to prevent Christians from fighting Christians in the same war (p. 156). Finally, focusing on the elite cannot explain why the masses so readily accept the message of nationalism. True, the elite may exploit, and manipulate nationalist feelings, but surely there must be something to be exploited in the first place. In short, alternative factors are not powerful enough - we need to examine nationalism in order to explain important historic events.

If the importance of nationalism is beyond doubt, its precise nature, its relationship to other concepts (such as the state), its causes, its consequences, and its future are more debated. Moreover, in order to say that nationalism was, and is, an important facto in shaping history we must at the very least have a rough idea about what nationalism is. This is the topic to which I now turn.

What is nationalism?
According to Connor, a "nation consists of a group of people who believe they are ancestrally related" (preface, xiv). Nationalism, in turn, is defined as "loyalty to the ethnic group" (p. 40). Loyalty in this context implies willingness to sacrifice, for instance being willing to give your life to defend the group in a war. This definition of nationalism should be sharply distinguished from patriotism (loyalty to the state). In relatively homogeneous societies - like Germany, Japan and Norway - the two are easily confused, but in multi-ethnic societies there are many examples of conflicts between loyalty to your ethnic group and loyalty to the state.

Having defined a nation and nationalism, Connor goes on to examine the causes and the nature of these concepts. Why, for instance, do we believe that we are ancesterally related to the members of our nation. The cause of this belief cannot be rational evaluation of evidence, since the factual basis for arguing that, say, all Germans descend from a common German Eve is clearly empirically false (p. 217). How, then, do we explain why people believe in the myth of the nation and are nationalists?

One possible explanation is evolution. To explain this allow me to recall an observation from Richard Dawkins' book The Selfish Gene (I here rely on my fallible memory). Lengthy observation of a bird colony established the following facts: A bird-mother would almost always risk her life defending her children against an intruder. A uncle, however, was less frequently willing to risk his life to protect a single child, although he was more inclined to do so when the lives of two or three children were at stake. Finally, even more distant relatives would only defend the children if more than four lives were threatened. In short, the closer the DNA resemblance, the more the bird were willing to sacrifice. Why should this be so? The obvious answer is evolution. A species with a DNA code that told it to sacrifice its life defending everybody - even other species - would become extinct. In the same way, one might speculate whether human willingness to make sacrifices for your relatives (real or imagined) can be explained by evolution.

Connor does not speculate on the evolutionary causes of nationalism. He simply notes that "its well-spring remain shadowy and elusive" (p. 92). Moreover, the precise nature of the bond is also elusive, although in general Connor argues that "the national bond is subconscious and emotional rather than conscious and rational in its inspiration" (preface, xiii).

I have so far presented Connor's definition of nationalism and his discussion of its nature and its causes. This leaves maybe the most important topic: The link between nationalism and the events claimed to be caused by nationalism (like the collapse of Empires). Exactly how did the ethnic bonds between people lead to, for example, the collapse of Austria-Hungary?

Being a strong believer in methodological individualism, I want to explain events by reference to the individuals who were involved. The key question is thus what forces make an individual behave as he does. The most parsimonious answer to this question - that employed by economists - is rational selfishness. In short, people do what they think is best for themselves. In this perspective, only two main variables explain behaviour: aims and beliefs. Of course, one might go further - as sociologists often do - to try to explain the aims and beliefs we have. For instance, there are hot and cold mechanisms that shape our beliefs, and our preferences are also shaped by various mechanisms. Wishful-thinking is an example of hot belief-formation (beliefs influenced by what we want to be true); Incorrect beliefs about the distance to an object when the weather is good is an examples of cold belief-formation (beliefs influenced by systematic cognitive mistakes); and sour-grapes is an example of preference formation (that we do not want what we cannot get). Regardless of whether we try to explain preferences and beliefs, the key to the economist approach is the prediction that of all the possible actions an individual faces, he will choose the one that he believes is best at satisfying his aims. Using this frame, rational choice theorists have lately invaded political science. My question is then: Where nationalism fit into this picture (if at all).

Being loyal to your ethnic group, Connor's definition of nationalism, is not a belief - nor is it an aim. Instead, it seems to be an action inspired by emotions (the bond we feel to those we believe are our relatives). And emotions are not the only factor causing problem for the narrow economic view of man. Another factor is norms which influence behaviour without being an aim or a belief. For instance, rational-choice theory cannot explain why people vote (the effort is simply not worth the small amount of influence from one vote), while norms of duty ("it is my duty to vote") may explain voting. In sum, to the question of what drives human beings we can give three main forces: Interests, passions and reason. [For more on this distinction see Jon Elster (1996): Doing our level best, The Times Literary Supplement, 29. March, pp. 12-13. Also available from The Jon Elster Page at URL: www.oocities.org/hmelberg/elster.htm]

Interests are our selfish desires, and it is relatively obvious that our behaviour is motivated by this factor - for instance, consumer behaviour. That we are motivated by passions, should also be relatively obvious. For example, revenge and hate are rarely rational, although often a powerful motivator for behaviour. Lastly, reason can be associated with impartial rules: We want to have good reasons for our actions and we feel that these reasons should go beyond pure self-interests. The reason we vote is neither interests, nor passions, but that we think it is the right think to do.

What is the proper role of nationalism in this extended frame? As mentioned, Connor believes nationalism is an action associated with an emotion. Emotions, in general, have what one might call 'action tendencies'. As Jon Elster writes: " The first urge of the envious person is to destroy the object of his envy or, if that is impossible, to destroy its owner. The action tendency of shame is to hide or disappear; that of guilt, to make atonements and repairs; that of anger, to strike: that of fear, to run; that of joy, to dance." [Elster (1996), Rationality and the emotions, Economic Journal (September 1996), vol. 106 (438), pp.1386-1397. Also available from the Jon Elster Page.] The 'action tendency' of feeling related to a person, then, must be to protect and advance that person; or more generally, to advance and protect the group.

Let me now return to the original question: What is the link - the causal connections - between nationalism and the events ascribed to nationalism? Building a new state can, in part, be viewed as facing a series of prisoner dilemma's problems. As an example of this problem, consider the defence of a community. Could the community be defended without a central authority with the power to coerce people? Without a central authority, each individual would have to face the following question when a potential danger loomed on the horizon: Should I leave my family and defend the community? (Or, should I leave my family to fight for a new state?) Assume the payoffs can be visualised in the following figure:

					Pal
				Fight		Not fight
		Fight		7, 7		1, 10
Igor
		Not fight	10, 1		3, 3

The motivation behind these payoffs is that if none of us fight, we will end up in a relatively bad situation (occupied, but alive; everybody gets 3). If only Igor fights there is a high probability that he will die, but he will also defend the country so Pal can live in freedom (so, Igor's expected payoff is 1, while Pal gets 10: freedom and no fighting). If both fight, they greatly reduce the probability of dying, and the expected payoff to each is 7 (fighting is costly, but liberty is good).

What will Pal and Igor choose? A rational and selfish person, say Igor, would reason as follows: If Pal fights, it is best for me not to fight (I get 10 instead of 7). Now, if Pal chooses not to fight, it is also best for me not to fight (I get 3 instead of 1). So, whatever Pal chooses it is best for Igor not to fight, and this is what he will choose. But the same reasoning applies to Pal, whatever Igor does, it is most profitable for him not to fight, so this is what he will do. The end result is that both choose not to fight and they both get 3 in payoff. The paradox, of course, is that they could have done much better if they both had fought (get 7 each). But this solution is not available, if one person chooses to fight the other has an incentive to cheat - to avoid fighting, to make the other person carry the burden while you free ride. This shows how individual rationality can create collectively disastrous results.

What is the solution to this problem? If a state is created with the power to punish those who cheat, this will change the payoffs so as to make it profitable to fight. In this way the state can solve the problem of the prisoner's dilemma (as it is called). Moreover, defence is not the only example of a how individual rationality may create collectively disastrous results. To mention a few examples: Individually fishermen have an incentive to fish too much; factories an incentive to over-pollute; and people an incentive to under-invest in prevention of epidemics. Faced with these problems most countries have opted for some kind of state intervention.

In what way does nationalism affect the story above? Recall that Connor defines nationalism in terms of willingness to make sacrifices for the group. Within my frame, there are at least two ways of visualising this. First, to say that people will choose to fight even when it is not in their material interests. Second, to argue that being a nationalist changes that payoffs, so that it makes fighting more profitable - for instance by including psychic gains from fighting on behalf of your group. In any case, the point is that ethnic bonds between people can make the co-operative solution more likely since it makes individuals more willing to make sacrifices on behalf of the group. This shows a more detailed picture of how nationalism can explain the collapse of empires: As nationalism grows in new nations, more and more people become willing to make the sacrifices necessary to fight for nationhood - scarifies that are individually not profitable but because of nationalism people are no longer propelled solely by selfish and material cost-benefit considerations.

Can nationalism be studied scientifically?
A person can accept that nationalism is both important and roughly definable, but still doubt the utility from studying nationalism. This, of course, depends on the aim of our study. Three such aims are: to explain (historical events), to predict (future events) and to recommend (finding policies to deal with nationalism).

One reason why focusing on nationalism may run into problems on all three accounts, is that explanations based on emotions are very hard to quantify. Consider the following competing arguments:
1. "Person X did Y since his aim was to become rich and action Y was believed to earn him $1000"
2 "Person X did Y because his emotions made this the most profitable actions" (Or, "because his emotions made him do Y")

The first argument can be tested, since it is possible to examine what the person would do if he received less than $1000 to do Y (e.g. give less blood the less you are paid). The second argument has a circular quality (everything can be explained by saying that "he felt like doing it"), and it is much more difficult to test. The monetary payoffs are observable, the emotional payoffs are not. This is one reason why explanations based on emotions may be less reliable than rational choice explanations.

Lack of quantifiability, and lack of a formal mathematical model, also makes predictions difficult. Rational choice supporters, on the other hand, have the advantage that they can make predictions based on the "as-if" assumption. That is, when they make predictions they need not assume that people actually are rational, only that they behave "as-if" they were rational. For instance, if we were to predict the shot and angle of a pool-player, we might find that a quite complicated mathematical model accurately predicts the strength and angle of his shot, but we need not claim that the pool player actually goes through these calculations in his head before he makes the shot. There is, I think, no similar argument available to make predictions based on emotional behaviour.

Finally, policy recommendations may also be best when we use a framework based on the belief that people respond to material incentives. For example, assume that you want to reduce the crime rates in a country. Two alternative proposals are then put forth:
1. To try to change people's norms and attitudes
2. To increase the sanctions (e.g. increase tickets for speeding)

The effect of these measures do not only depend on whether people are motivated by norms or rational cost/benefit calculations when they commit crimes, but also on the ease, predictability and relative efficiency of changing norms vs. incentives. One may even admit that emotions are very important in certain kinds of crime, but as long as there is some element of cost-benefit considerations the net payoff from focusing on changing the incentives may be much larger than the net payoff from trying to change attitudes. The simple reason is that it is hard to change attitudes (since the causal mechanisms are relatively uncertain, and - moreover - it may take a long time and be very costly), while it is easy to change the sanctions.

Return now to the original question: To what extent can nationalism be studied scientifically? I have so far made general arguments to the effect that the lack of quantifiability and precise models makes this study difficult - whether your aim is to explain, to predict or to recommend. In the following I want to make this argument a bit more precise, as well as discussing Connor's arguments on the possibility of scientific study of nationalism.

On several occasions Connor seems very sympathetic to the argument that nationalism cannot be studied scientifically. For instance, he discusses an article by Ladis Kristof to the effect that: "Dissection and logic, even in concert, may prove not only inadequate but misleading when applied to the study of sensory loyalties" (p. 112). Similarly, he quoted Freud who writes about "many obscure and emotional forces, which were the more powerful the less they could be expressed in words" (p. 203). Finally, Connor himself writes that "... nations, national identity, and nationalism are 'the stuff that dreams are made of,' and this helps to account both for their emotional appeal and for their resistance to rational inquiry" (p. 210).

This does not imply that the study of nationalism is worthless. As Connor argues, nationalism "can be analysed but not explained rationally" (p. 204, my emphasis). By analysed, he means that it is possible to examine "the type of catalysists to which it responds ..." (p. 204). In short, what factors make nationalism grow or decline, and what factors shape its form. This kind of examination is possible within a "normal" scientific frame, using historical examples, surveys and statistics.

I am not too convinced by the argument that emotions are resistant to rational investigation. Too see why we must distinguish between rational (or scientific) investigation and explanations based on rational choice. Given a set of evidence, I may rationally conclude that a person was motivated by love (or hate) when he did X. Rationality or scientific investigation, is then simply a way of evaluating evidence. There is nothing inherently impossible in "rationally" concluding that people sometimes are "irrational" - in fact there is a great deal of evidence which points in this direction (see, for instance, experiments by Kahneman, Slovic and Tversky).

Conclusion
I started with the question of why I should be interested in nationalism. While I think nationalism both has important consequences, and that it is possible to gain a rough understanding of what it is, I am less certain whether a focus on nationalism is "useful" if the aim is to find reliable scientific theories that can be used to shape policy. Assume, for the sake of argument, that we after much work have a "scientifically" good argument that the situation in Kazakhstan would improve if they started to follow the civic model of national integration. The problem, of course, is that the elite need not be motivated by the "scientifically" best policy, but simply by more brute considerations of what is best for the elite and how they can maintain their power. In sum, I am not yet convinced that the study of nationalism is useful from a policy perspective, but I am more convinced that it is important from a historian's standpoint - to explain historical events. However, even there doubts remain about its reliability. But, then again, no explanation is certain!


A note on some possible references
A. Rorty has edited a book called Explaining Emotions which is recommended by Jon Elster (I have not read it yet). R. Hardin and M. Hechter have both written on the relationship between rational choice and nationalim.


[Note for bibliographic reference: Melberg, Hans O. (1997), Nationalism: Is it definable, important and worthy of attention?, www.oocities.org/hmelberg/papers/971210.htm]