Nina Glass
Term Paper
Sophomore Tutorial in Hist and Sci
11 May, 2001
TF: Kenji Ito



A Surprising Response to Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorem



From Aristotle down, the laws of logic have been regarded as fixed and archetypal; and as such that they admit of no conceivable alternatives. Often they have been attributed to the structure of the Universe or to the nature of human reason; and in general they have been regarded as providing Address of the retiring chairman and vice-president an Archimedean fixed point in the realm of thought.[1]

Since the time of the Greeks, philosophers and mathematicians have been interested in defining truth. What is truth? And how do we discover what is true in the world? It has always been assumed that these questions could be answered. During the beginning of the twentieth century, in fact, mathematicians such as David Hilbert and Bertrand Russell thought that they were making great progress at answering these questions within the domain of what was called mathematical formalism. However, Gödel’s incompleteness paper of 1931[2] necessitated a reassessment of what truth was. This reassessment should have been discouraging to the mathematical formalists, because it upset their primary goal for mathematics. Despite this affront to his worldview, however, Hilbert soon came to embrace Gödel’s proof as an exposition of formal mathematical principles and as a proof of ongoing mathematical vitality–the most important goal of Hilbert’s program.
During the beginning of the twentieth century, there were two prevailing schools of thought within mathematics. One, the formalist school was led by Hilbert, Russell, Alfred North Whitehead, and others. The other, the intuitionist school, was dominated by Luitzen Egbertus Jan Brouwer. The distinction between these two groups is logical; the formalists put all faith in logical formalism, and the intuitionists in intuition. Logical formalism depended on formal systems which contain a finite number of basic axioms (self-evident rules that are accepted as true) and rules of inference (concrete methods to deduce further truths). Logical formalism says that the only way to define mathematical truth is by using this formal system. The intuitionists, on the other hand, reject logic as the standard of truth within mathematics. In other words, they said that mathematical objects could not be defined by a formal system, and that truth, as a mathematical object, is a construction of the mathematician’s mind, and could therefore only be determined within the mind.
The Austrian Kurt Gödel, born in 1906, was educated in the midst of conflicts between these two schools. He clearly worked within a formalist frame, becoming one of the leaders in set theory, the field of Bertrand Russell. Showing a strong aptitude, from the very beginning, for logic, he attended the University of Vienna from 1923 until he finished his doctoral dissertation in 1929 and took a teaching position there among the school of logical positivists.[3] Then in 1931, he published his first and second incompleteness theorems, for which he is best known.[4] Subsequently, Gödel continued to work and publish within the field of set theory, but made no discoveries as important as that of his 1931 paper.[5]
As stated above, it is Gödel’s famous 1931 paper that has earned him the most fame. Consequently, it was no surprise when it was criticized soon after it had been published; that is, it was no surprise, considering that his paper came to such shocking conclusions, by such esoteric methods. The claim of the paper was that, given any axiomatic system like Principia Mathematica, Gödel could construct a sentence within the system that was undecidable, in other words, a sentence that could be neither proven nor disproven.[6] The implications of this will be explored later.
Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorem had several necessary precursors without which it would not have been relevant. Most significantly, it depended on the presence of a book, such as Principia Mathematica,[7] originally published in 1910, which provided an entire system of arithmetic that rested on the formalism of the axiomatic system upon which it was based. That is, it provided a series of axioms or rules that were accepted to be true (for example if x=y then y=x). These simple statements were then used to derive the rest of arithmetic. Principia Mathematica is a good example of an instrumentalist text, providing “a system of meaningless marks, whose formulas (or ‘strings’) are combined and transformed in accordance with stated rules of operation.”[8] The Principia Mathematica helped greatly in examining the question of consistency, by providing a notation for the language of arithmetic, as well as for the rules of inference which are used. The idea, in other words, is that if you accepted the axioms, or basic premises of the system, then all theorems that follow by the rules of inference are true, no matter what the variables that you input represent.
This system was also sufficiently complex. For example, it addressed the problem of the theory of types established by Russell. This problem addressed a paradox that could arise from self-referential systems. It asked if you had two sets, one that contained precisely all of the sets containing themselves, and a second containing all sets that do not contain themselves, then where would you put the second set. If you put it in the first set, then it would not contain itself and belongs in the second set, but then it would contain itself and belongs in the first. Whitehead and Russell solved this problem by defining sets of different types. This way a set could only contain sets of the previous order. This system was sufficiently complex as to allow Gödel to go beyond the question of consistency to the question of completeness.
Gödel’s first incompleteness theorem, proven by his 1931 paper, set out to show that any formal system that is sufficiently complex is undecidable. The example he uses is called P, using the laws from Principia Mathematica. For a formal system to be undecidable it must contain a sentence or formula, A, for which neither A could be proven, nor could not-A be proven. The formula he came up with is in some ways similar to (and is often times conflated with) the liar’s paradox (“This sentence is false.”), in that it is self-referential. However, the sentence does not refer to truth or falsehood, but instead to provability.
Also, the output of the Gödel sentence depends more on the action of the sentence than in the liar’s paradox. A good example is given by Chad Mazzola. Let’s examine the sentence he gives, “Only a complete fool would take the time to figure out that he had just written a sentence with exactly eight A's, one B, four C's, three D's, and [?] E's."[9] If we replace [?] with “seventeen” then reexamination of the sentence would make this false, and the new value for [?] “twenty-one.” Then, on repeating this process again, we get “nineteen.” The “correct” value of [?] then proceeds to oscillate between “eighteen” and “twenty,” never settling on any one value. However, this sentence does have a correct value for [?], it just cannot be written, or it changes. The liar’s paradox, on the other hand, does not have this quality. The Gödel sentence does.
The Gödel sentence, G, says, “G is not provable.” If the Gödel sentence is provable, then it is false, and by the soundness[10] of our system P, that is not possible. So, what if the negation of the Gödel sentence is provable? Again, by soundness, this makes G true (if the negation is provable, the original sentence cannot be true). This is another contradiction. This is the kind of sentence that Gödel had set out to find. Also, by closer examination, we can see that the Gödel sentence is in fact true. It is not provable. The fact that this truth is not provable within the system leads to Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem and the subsequent affronts on formalism. Gödel goes on to prove that this sentence exists in a much more rigorous fashion, constructing a complex correspondence between formulas and positive integers, and deriving this sentence logically from the axioms provided by Principia Mathematica.
The original response to Gödel’s paper was misunderstanding by some. The biggest complaints came from Chaim Perelman. Perelman argues that Gödel’s theorem, the liar’s paradox, and other simple paradoxes like the question of “who shaves the barber who shaves every man in town who doesn’t shave himself” are all equivalent, and justify an approach like that of Brouwer, rejecting formal systems altogether, in exchange for intuitionism.[11] Perelman’s antinomy, with which he argues against Gödel, is essentially equivalent to a problem which Russell had identified and addressed previously, with his theory of types. The faults that Perelman finds with Gödel’s paper are only applicable to the cursory explanation of Gödel’s proof given in the introduction to his paper. These complaints are made null and void in the rest of his paper, when Gödel actually formalizes a language, and a system to which any sufficiently complex and consistent system can be reduced, and makes a correspondence between the sets of sentences in this language, and a set of positive integers which have come to be known as Gödel numbering.[12]
By very rigorous logical formalism, Gödel takes each sign within the language, and assigns a numerical value to it. Using these values, he formally defines numbers (products of ordered prime numbers raised to the power of the numerical assignment of the sign they represent), that represent each axiom and subsequent theorem that can be derived. One of the theorems that Gödel derives is a provability predicate–a formula that tells whether or not the inputted sentence is provable, when the sentence inputted is a numerical sentences as defined by the Gödel numbering.
It is actually the intuitionists, some making the same mistake as Perelman, who ended up understanding and using implications of Gödel’s incompleteness theorems that Gödel certainly did not intend. For example, Brouwer uses Gödel’s results to justify his rejection of non-constructive existence proofs, which are proofs that follow Hilbert’s ideal reasoning, and which is actually the type of proof Gödel uses to prove his incompleteness theorems.[13] It is not particularly surprising that intuitionists do not understand Gödel’s proof, in the same way he intended it, because it depends heavily on formal mathematical principles, in which he was trained, and the intuitionists generally were not. In particular, intuitionists rejected the Law of Excluded Middle, which says that every statement is either true or false. When this is rejected, proofs by contradiction are no longer valid, so the problem that arises from Gödel’s incompleteness theorem has no profound impact. The intuitionists, however, interpreting Gödel’s incompleteness theorem as the liar’s paradox, assumed that it was a formalized version of this law, and not what it was, in fact a much more profound statement about the meaning of proof. The formalists, on the other hand, who should have been devastated by Gödel’s proof, were instead the first to understand and embrace it, because of its formal nature.
One of the biggest names associated with logical formalism is David Hilbert who was an eminent mathematician at the turn of the century. His work was in various areas including invariant theory, algebraic number theory, and geometry. His work in Euclidean geometry was perhaps the most influential. Hilbert’s book , Die Grundlagen der Geometrie[14], or The Foundations of Geometry[15], published in 1899, was a fundamental text in formalist history. It followed many other contemporary works on Euclidean geometry. Hilbert’s book, however, went beyond the work of others like Peano, by focusing on metageometry, that is not the geometry itself, but the metamathematical structure of it. This was the first attempt to formalize mathematics by separating mathematical principles from their physical basis in the world. Hilbert believed that even basic geometry or arithmetic was not purely logical because it depended on the mathematicians’ intuition or construction of the mathematical objects. He therefore focused on closely examining the formal logic behind these mathematical objects.[16] Hilbert determined the axioms or fundamental rules that one needed to accept in order to derive the rest of Euclidean geometry, that is simple geometry of points, lines and circles in a plane.
Hilbert’s re-axiomatization of Euclidean geometry, using a much more formal system, was later able to be extended to other areas of mathematics. These principles were universal, and the idea was that no matter what the objects of the original axioms were, you could use any subsequent theorems that had been derived from the axioms. In other words, while Hilbert defined his objects, points, lines, and planes, he made sure that these objects were each interchangeable with any other group of objects that had a set of properties that were assigned to them. Hilbert is often quoted as having said, “[o]ne must always be able to say ‘tables [sic] chairs, beer-mugs’ instead of ‘points, lines, planes’.”[17] The goal of the formalists was to establish a system like this to encompass not just geometry but all of mathematics. Most of the formalists, including Hilbert, presumed that this formal system would be finite. This is the assumption that is challenged by Gödel’s incompleteness theorems.[18]
Because of the nature of geometry, however, its formalization was not directly affected by Gödel’s incompleteness theorem.[19] Geometry was originally studied by the Greeks because it required less abstraction than other mathematics.[20] Therefore, the system described is not complex enough to be concerned with proving its own consistency, a predicate for Gödel’s incompleteness theorem. This is why problems arise only subsequently, with the publication of Principia Mathematica, which attempted to have a much wider scope, for example incorporating the theory of types, which solved a paradox in set theory that Russell had discovered, that involved self-referential sets.
Following his work in geometry, Hilbert had a plan for mathematics that has come to be known as Hilbert’s Program.[21] Hilbert embraced a particular strain of mathematical instrumentalism. Instrumentalism is the examination of mathematical objects as instruments, rather than actual constructions. This goes back to Hilbert’s famous quote, on the preceding page. As opposed to others who studied instrumentalism, Hilbert emphasized two main points. One is that he focused his attention on ideal proofs, which are clear concise proofs that include only the signs of formulas needed for the proof, with no explanation of the proof’s significance.[22] The French mathematician Henri Poincaré argued that this method could grow to be self-referential, but his argument is weak.[23]
The second particular to Hilbert’s program is his answer to the dilution problem. This refers to controlling the quality, by which I mean the strength, of the results of a given proof. Hilbert emphasized the use of a restricted mathematical instrumentalism that was finite in order to avoid the problem of dilution.[24] Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem subsequently raises issue with this, by showing that an infinite system is needed for completeness. Hilbert’s emphasis on strength in mathematics is a sign of his love of the subject. This explains his hope to keep the subject alive in the future, which will be explained later in this paper.
Another implication of Gödel’s first incompleteness theorem is that the Gödel sentence is true, even if it is not provable within the system P. This means that Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem is easily derived. Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem talks about the consistency of system P (or any sufficiently complex system). The heart of this proof lies in being able to formalize the statement of Gödel’s first incompleteness theorem.[25] This theorem defines a formal predicate (Con) that denotes a statement of consistency of the system P. It then goes on to show that the statement of consistency, (Con), cannot be derivable in P unless P is in fact inconsistent. However, the system P can be strengthened to include a proof of (Con), but it is now a new system, P’ for which we must derive a new statement of consistency (we could call it (Con)P’), which is again not derivable in P’ unless the system is in fact inconsistent. This can be done over and over again, providing more and more complete systems, but never one that is complete enough to prove its own consistency.
It is this implication that makes the formalist program to find a finite axiomatic system to encompass all of mathematics impossible. We can see from Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem that there is no entirely complete and consistent system, because we can always add an axiom to strengthen a system, providing a transfinite number of axioms. Following Hilbert’s lead in geometry, the formalists had presumed that there existed a finite number of axioms that would define all of mathematics.
Then, when Hilbert published his Foundations of Mathematics or Grundlagen der Mathematik,[26] he was forced to acknowledge Gödel’s Second Incompleteness Theorem, and was in fact the first to give a formal proof of it.[27] This shows that Hilbert had understood Gödel’s original proof (because Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem follows directly from the first). It also shows that he embraced the proof, despite understanding its implications to his program. This follows Hilbert’s policy of seeking out knowledge, because he thought that there were no limitations on what one could learn.[28] This is seen in a quote that is now seen on Hilbert’s tombstone, “Wir müüssen wissen. Wir werden wissen.” That is, “We must know. We will know.”[29]
There are many scholars who argue that Gödel’s incompleteness theorems were a profound development and were extremely detrimental to the further development of formalist mathematics. As Morris Kline, a mathematician famous for his textbooks on the history of mathematics put it, “Gödel’s theorems produced a debacle.”[30] He goes on to refer to the Gödel paper as a “Pandora’s box.”[31] Similarly, another mathematician who has spent time studying Gödel’s incompleteness theorems, John Dawson argues that it is only
natural to invoke geological metaphors to describe the impact and the lasting significance of Gödel’s incompletness theorems. Indeed, how better to convey the impact of those results–whose effect on Hilbert’s Programme was so devastating and whose philosophical reverberations have yet to subside–than to speak of tremors and shock waves? The image of shaken foundation is irresistible.[32]

These implications especially caused problems for the formalists. For example Mary Tiles, a philosopher of logic and mathematics, in her book, Mathematics and the Image of Reason, argues that “The results of both Gödel and Church[33] demonstrate that Hilbert was mistaken in thinking that it might be possible, by suitable selection of notation, to have a formal system which was both sufficiently complex to be capable of being interpreted as a formalization of classical arithmetic and yet in which theorems would be recognizable as such on the basis of possession of some relatively simple morphological characteristic.”[34] Another scholar, Jeremy Gray, stated that the work of the 1930's (including Gödel, Turing, etc.) had
by and large dashed Hilbert’s hopes. . . It is not possible to set up all of mathematics along the finitistic lines Hilbert had hoped for, but perhaps something nearly as good could be achieved. . . It certainly seemed as if Gödel’s incompleteness theorem ruled out any natural starting point for a formalised mathematics, but perhaps Hilbert’s ideas could be re-interpreted, or his aims realised in some unexpected way.[35]

This asserts that Gödel’s incompleteness theorem had changed the possible scope of Hilbert’s program.
Another scholar, J. Fang, addresses the issue of why Hilbert was so interested in foundational questions. “Hilbert’s intimately personal experience of the activity in mathematical creation was ultimately and entirely responsible for his plunging into the darkness of the foundational problems. The most fundamental, and the most urgent, of them all was the proof of consistency from the very beginning: A proof must be given, for any branch of mathematics, that no contradictory theorems can ever arise from the permitted procedures of demonstration.”[36] If Fang is correct, that consistency was Hilbert’s priority, then Gödel’s results would in fact have been very significant for Hilbert and his outlook on mathematics. However, perhaps Hilbert cared more about the success of mathematics in the bigger picture.
It is clear, especially before the publication of Gödel’s incompleteness theorems, that this finitist-formalist position had been very important to Hilbert. We can see this in his 1927 lecture on “The Foundations of Mathematics.”[37] Here he says, for example: “Mathematics proper becomes an inventory of formulas.”[38] “This formula game is carried out according to certain definite rules, in which the technique of our thinking is expressed. These rules form a closed system that can be discovered and definitively stated.”[39] and throughout this paper, explaining a proof of finiteness.[40] From these quotations, we can see that in 1927 before any ideas of incompleteness, Hilbert was totally convinced that his program was viable. Then how do we explain his change of heart, with the inclusion of the proof of Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem in his later publication with Bernays, The Foundations of Mathematics?
Perhaps this proof of Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem was included by Bernays. Bernays seemed to emphasize the strength of the implications of Gödel’s incompleteness theorems on formal mathematical systems even more than Gödel himself. For example, even in his original paper, Gödel seems to doubt the scope of his paper saying,
I wish to note expressly that Theorem XI (and the corresponding results for M and A) do not contradict Hilbert’s formalistic viewpoint. For this viewpoint presupposes only the existence of a consistency proof in which nothing but finitary means of proof is used, and it is conceivable that there exist finitary proofs that cannot be expressed in the formalism of P (or of M or A).[41]

This is a note that refers to one of the steps in the proof of Gödel’s Second Incompleteness Theorem that involves a step that some have argued is weak. However Gödel was soon (by 1958, anyway) convinced by Bernays that this was an unnecessary caution.[42] In any case, the inclusion of the proof in Hilbert and Bernays’ book basically quieted all opposition to Gödel’s paper and asserted that it held appreciable developments.[43]
An alternative interpretation is that perhaps, once Hilbert had read and understood Godel’s paper, he recognized that it was an example of what he considered a great problem. It was easily stated, and then had a rigorous proof. What’s more, its proof left the field open for an infinite number of questions that could subsequently be derived from it. This meant a perpetually alive mathematics for Hilbert.
This idea of mathematics being alive is perhaps unintuitive for those people who studied mathematics in school only when they had to. However, as far as Hilbert and many other mathematicians were and are concerned, mathematics is alive. Hilbert asserted this vivacity in a lecture on Wednesday August 8th, 1900, at the International Congress of Mathematicians, in Paris.[44] At this lecture he posed the twenty-three problems that he posed in a lecture for which he is most well-known.[45] If a similar assertion were made today, of the mathematical problems facing the next generation, some of Hilbert’s original problems would remain (namely Goldbach’s conjecture), but many more would have originated from the development of Gödel’s incompleteness theorem.
Hilbert defined problems that he thought were good problems. He judged good problems by the fact that their solutions opened the mind to a wider view of mathematics, and perhaps lead to new theorems and new fields of research. It was also very important for Hilbert’s problems to be “characterized by their clarity and ease of comprehension.”[46] These problems are a good example of the intimate relationship between the mathematics of Gödel and Hilbert. Gödel had a hand in solving both of Hilbert’s first two problems, although he did not solve them in the way that Hilbert had anticipated.
Hilbert’s first problem was on the continuum hypothesis. This question was originally posed by Georg Cantor, and was partly solved by Gödel in his 1940 book,[47] and then completely solved by one of his students, Paul Cohen. However, rather than deriving an answer from concrete suppositions and inferences, they helped to prove that the First problem was undecidable (Gödel proved that the continuum hypothesis was not disprovable, and Cohen proved that it was not provable).[48] Hilbert’s second problem was on the compatibility of the axioms of arithmetic.[49] It was this second problem that helped Gödel on the road to developing his incompleteness theorems, by providing the sort of concrete finite system against which Gödel argues.[50]
In his 1900 lecture Hilbert expressed that problems within a discipline are a sign that it is alive. He said, “As long as a branch of science offers an abundance of problems, so long is it alive; a lack of problems foreshadows extinction or the cessation of independent development.”[51] During the past century, many of Hilbert’s original 23 problems have been solved. Some have, as he hoped they would, generated more questions, and a wider understanding of the mathematics they involve. There is no doubt that Gödel’s incompleteness theorem helped to ensure an abundance of mathematical problems for a long time to come.
In conclusion, although Hilbert’s program was, according to most scholars, Hilbert was not as discouraged by this as he might have been. Hilbert and Gödel respected each other as scholars, even working together as is seen by Hilbert’s influence on Gödel, Gödel’s help in solving Hilbert’s first and second problems, and Hilbert’s publication of the proof of Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem. These two mathematicians were working toward the same goal, affirming mathematical vitality.
As the German mathematician Hermann Weyl,[52] who studied under Hilbert, although he later joined the intuitionist school, said, “mathematics, in spite of its age, is not doomed to progressive sclerosis by its growing complexity, but is still intensely alive, drawing nourishment from its deep roots in mind and nature.”[53] This idea was ensured by Gödel’s incompleteness theorem, which had two very important implications in mathematics. One is that it made Hilbert’s dream of establishing a complete and consistent system that would encompass all truth impossible. The second is that it set certain limits on the scope of mathematics, allowing for problems that may be true, but have no formal axiomatic proof, for example, meaning that there will always remain problems within mathematics to solve. As one of Hilbert’s dreams, in posing his twenty-three famous problems, there is an interesting irony to this story by which Gödel has saved Hilbert’s world, while at the same time, destroying his world view.
Bibliography


Church, Alonzo “An Unsolvable Problem of Elementary Number Theory.” American Journal of Mathematics, Vol. 58, No. 2. (Apr., 1936), pp. 345-363.

Dawson, John W. Jr. “The Reception of Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems.” In Gödel’s Theorem in focus. S.G. Shanker ed. London: Croom Helm, 1988. pp. 74-95.

Detlefsen, Michael.Hilbert’s Program: An Essay on Mathematical Instrumentalism. Dordrecht: D.Reidel Publishing Company, 1986.

Fang, J. Hilbert:Towards a Philosophy of Modern Mathematics. New York: Paideia Press, 1970.

Feferman, Solomon. “Kurt Gödel: Conviction and Caution.” In Gödel’s Theorem in Focus. S.G. Shanker, ed. London: Croom Helm, 1988. pp. 96-114.

Gödel, Kurt. Collected Works, Volume 1, Publications 1929-1936. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.

Gödel, Kurt. Consistency of the axiom of choice and of the generalized continuum-hypothesis with the axioms of set theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1940.

Gödel, Kurt. “On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems.” In From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879-1931. Jean van Heijenoort ed. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971. pp. 596-616.

Gray, Jeremy J. The Hilbert Challenge. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.

Hedrick, E. R. “Tendencies in the Logic of Mathematics.” Science, New Series, Vol. 77, No. 1997. (April 7, 1933).

Helmer,Olaf. “Perelman versus Gödel.” Mind, New Series, Vol. 46, No. 181. (Jan., 1937). pp. 58-60.

Hilbert, David . The Foundations of Geometry. E. J. Townsend, trans. Chicago: The Open Court Publishing Company, 1921.

Hilbert, David. “The Foundations of Mathematics.” In From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879-1931. Jean van Heijenoort ed. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971. pp. 464-479.

Hilbert, David. Grundlagen der Geometrie. Leipzig: B.G. Teubner, 1899.
Hilbert, Daivd. “Mathematical Problems.” Lecture delivered before the International Congress of Mathematicians at Paris in 1900. Dr. Mary Winston Newson translated this address into English with the author's permission for Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society. 8 (1902). pp. 437-479. A reprint of appears in Mathematical Developments Arising from Hilbert Problems. Felix Brouder, ed. American Mathematical Society, 1976. I gained access to this source from <http://aleph0.clarku.edu/~djoyce/hilbert/problems.html>.

Hilbert, David and Paul Isaac Bernays. Grundlagen der Mathematik. Berlin: J. Springer, 1934-39.

Hilbert, David. Speech in Königsberg in 1930, now on his tombstone in Göttingen. From <http://www-groups.dcs.st-andrews.ac.uk/~history/Quotations/Hilbert.html>.

Hofstadter, Douglas. Gödel, Escher, Bach: An Eternal Golden Braid. New York: Basic Books, 1999.

Kline, Morris. Mathematics: The Loss of Certainty. New York: Oxford Universtiy Press. 1980.

Mazzola, Chad. “Kurt Gödel’s Proof of Incompleteness.” Copyright WildeWare Studios. <http://wildeware.tripod.com/reviews/godel.html>.

Nagel, Ernst and James R. Newman. Gödel’s Proof. New York: New York University Press, 1958.

Perelman, Chaim. “Les Paradoxes de la Logique.” Mind, New Series, Vol. 45, No. 178. (Apr., 1936). pp. 204-208.

Smullyan, Raymond M. Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems. New York: Oxford University Press, 1992.

Tiles, Mary. Mathematics and the Image of Reason. London: Routledge,1991.

Weyl, Hermann. “The Mathematical Way of Thinking.” Science, New Series, Vol. 92, No. 2394. (Nov. 15, 1940). pp. 446.

Whitehead, Alfred North and Bertrand Russell. Principia Mathematica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1910.

[1]C. I. Lewis, qtd. in E. R. Hedrick, “Tendencies in the Logic of Mathematics,” Science, New Series, Vol. 77, No. 1997, (April 7, 1933), pp. 335.
[2]Whenever I mention Gödel’s famous paper, or his incompleteness paper, I am referring to his paper of 1931 “Uber formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme,” Monatshefte f. Math. U. Physik 38 (1931). The translation I am using is “On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems,” found in From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879-1931, Jean van Heijenoort ed., (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 596-616.
[3]It is interesting to note Gödel’s start within the field of logical positivism, when his eventual discoveries seem to contradict positivism in so many ways.
[4]His other well-known work includes the work of his Doctoral Dissertation, known as his completeness theorem, which deals with semantics (Kurt Gödel, “On the completeness of the calculus of logic,” 1929, in Collected Works Volume 1, Publications 1929-1936, (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), pp.61-101, and his book, Consistency of the axiom of choice and of the generalized continuum-hypothesis with the axioms of set theory, (Princeton: University Press, 1940).
[5]After the war it seems that Gödel was very shaken up and although he accepted a chair at the Institute for Advanced Study at Princeton in 1951, and went on to win a National Medal of Science in 1974, he was no longer as productive. In fact, he developed a paranoia that someone was trying to poison his food and eventually starved himself to death in 1978.
[6]In this paper, I will not go deeply into the mathematics of Gödel’s proof, so I do not want to imply that my explanation is precise. Instead, I will try to explain Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorem in basic terms, so that the reader can understand his argument without any mathematical background. To find a more precise explication of Gödel’s proof, see his original paper, or examine Raymond M. Smullyan’s book, Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems, (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992).
[7]Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell, Principia Mathematica, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1910).
[8]Ernst Nagel and James R. Newman, Gödel’s Proof, (New York: New York University Press, 1958), pp. 44.
[9]Chad Mazzola, “Kurt Gödel’s Proof of Incompleteness,” Copyright WildeWare Studios, <http://wildeware.tripod.com/reviews/godel.html>.
[10]Soundness is a term that refers to the semantic property of a provable statement being true in the intended interpretation, and it is one of the assumptions with Principia Mathematica.
[11]Chaim Perelman, “Les Paradoxes de la Logique,” Mind, New Series, Vol. 45, No. 178, (Apr., 1936), pp. 204-208.
[12]Olaf Helmer, “Perelman versus Gödel,” Mind, New Series, Vol. 46, No. 181, (Jan., 1937), pp. 58-60.
[13]Solomon Feferman, “Kurt Gödel: Conviction and Caution,” in Gödel’s Theorem in Focus, S.G. Shanker, ed., (London: Croom Helm, 1988), p. 101.
[14]David Hilbert, Die Grundlagen der Geometrie, (Leipzig: B.G. Teubner, 1899).
[15]The translation that I have used is David Hilbert, The Foundations of Geometry, Translated by E. J. Townsend, (Chicago: The Open Court Publishing Company, 1921). There are, however, numerous different translations and editions of this text that have been published, showing its widespread influence.
[16]J. Fang, Hilbert:Towards a Philosophy of Modern Mathematics, (New York: Paideia Press, 1970), 83.
[17]J. Fang, Hilbert:Towards a Philosophy of Modern Mathematics, (New York: Paideia Press, 1970), p. 81, allegedly from a conversation with two fellow mathematicians; also quoted in Mary Tiles, Mathematics and the Image of Reason, (London: Routledge, 1991), p. 89, here, translated slightly differently. It is of note that although this quotation is often used, its original source is ambiguous. It could therefore not be something that Hilbert actually said, but an expression of the conventional wisdom that showed where Hilbert’s views were seen to lie. It is clear, however, that this is a fair exposition of Hilbert’s position, from the way he defines point, line, and plane in his Foundations of Geometry, “Let us consider three distinct systems of things. The things composing of the first system, we will call points and designate them by the letters A, B, C, . . . . ; those of the second, we will call straight lines and designate them by the letters a, b, c, . . . . ; and those of the third sytsem, we will call planes and designate them by the Greek letters α, β, γ, . . . .” (David Hilbert, The Foundations of Geometry, (Chicago: The Open Court Publishing Company, 1921), p.3). As we can see from this passage, Hilbert aimed to define objects, calling them points, lines and planes only for convenience’s sake.
[18]Mary Tiles, Mathematics and the Image of Reason, (London: Routledge,1991), p. 90.
[19]Interestingly enough, addition was also proven to be complete by Mojzesz Presburger in his Master’s thesis, see Jeremy J. Gray, The Hilbert Challenge, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), pp. 172-173.
[20]J. Fang, Hilbert:Towards a Philosophy of Modern Mathematics, (New York: Paideia Press, 1970), p.80.
[21]For further expositions of Hilbert’s program see either Mary Tiles, Mathematics and the Image of Reason, (London: Routledge, 1991), p. 90, or Michael Detlefsen, Hilbert’s Program: An Essay on Mathematical Instrumentalism, (Dordrecht: D.Reidel Publishing Company, 1986), pp. 59-73.
[22]Michael Detlefsen, Hilbert’s Program: An Essay on Mathematical Instrumentalism, (Dordrecht: D.Reidel Publishing Company, 1986), p. 10.
[23]Michael Detlefsen, Hilbert’s Program: An Essay on Mathematical Instrumentalism, (Dordrecht: D.Reidel Publishing Company, 1986), pp. 59-62.
[24]Michael Detlefsen, Hilbert’s Program: An Essay on Mathematical Instrumentalism, (Dordrecht: D.Reidel Publishing Company, 1986), pp. 17-20.
[25]As I stated in explaining Gödel’s first incompleteness theorem, I will not do this formally, but instead, if you’re interested, direct you to examine pages 614-615 of Gödel’s 1931 paper.
[26]David Hilbert and Paul Isaac Bernays, Grundlagen der Mathematik, (Berlin: J. Springer, 1934-39).
[27]John W. Dawson, Jr., “The Reception of Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems,” in Gödel’s Theorem in focus, S.G. Shanker ed., (London: Croom Helm, 1988), p. 87.
[28]Morris Kline, Mathematics: The Loss of Certainty, (New York: Oxford University Press, 1980), p. 264.
[29]David Hilbert, from a speech in Königsberg in 1930, now on his tomb in Göttingen, from <http://www-groups.dcs.st-andrews.ac.uk/~history/Quotations/Hilbert.html>.
[30]Morris Kline, Mathematics: The Loss of Certainty, (New York: Oxford Universtiy Press, 1980), p. 6.
[31]Morris Kline, Mathematics: The Loss of Certainty, (New York: Oxford Universtiy Press, 1980), p.260.
[32]John W. Dawson, “The Reception of Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems,” in Gödel’s Theorem in Focus, S.G.Shanker, ed., (London: Croom Helm, 1988), p. 74.
[33]Church’s theorem, developed with Turing, is one of many extensions of Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorem discussing quantification theory–see Alonzo Church, “An Unsolvable Problem of Elementary Number Theory,” American Journal of Mathematics, Vol. 58, No. 2. (Apr., 1936), pp. 345-363
[34]Mary Tiles, Mathematics and the Image of Reason, (London: Routledge,1991), p 119.
[35]Jeremy J. Gray, The Hilbert Challenge, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), p. 218.
[36]J. Fang, Hilbert:Towards a Philosophy of Modern Mathematics, (New York: Paideia Press, 1970), p. 169.
[37]David Hilbert, “The Foundations of Mathematics,” in From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879-1931, Jean van Heijenoort ed., (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 464-479.
[38]David Hilbert, “The Foundations of Mathematics,” in From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879-1931, Jean van Heijenoort ed., (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971), p. 465.
[39]David Hilbert, “The Foundations of Mathematics,” in From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879-1931, Jean van Heijenoort ed., (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971), p. 475.
[40]David Hilbert, “The Foundations of Mathematics,” in From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879-1931, Jean van Heijenoort ed., (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 464-479.
[41]Gödel’s 1931 paper, p. 615.
[42]Michael Detlefsen, Hilbert’s Program: An Essay on Mathematical Instrumentalism, (Dordrecht, D. Reidel Publishing Company: 1986), p. 91.
[43]Jeremy J. Gray, The Hilbert Challenge, (Oxford, Oxford University Press: 2000), pp. 170-171.
[44]These are discussed in great detail in Jeremy J. Gray’s book, The Hilbert Challenge. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).
[45]If these problems are not known for their mathematical significance, then they are at least known for Hilbert’s character in presenting them, see Daivd Hilbert, “Mathematical Problems,” lecture delivered before the International Congress of Mathematicians at Paris in 1900. Dr. Mary Winston Newson translated this address into English with the author's permission for Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 8 (1902), 437-479. A reprint of appears in Mathematical Developments Arising from Hilbert Problems, edited by Felix Brouder, American Mathematical Society, 1976. I gained access to this source from <http://aleph0.clarku.edu/~djoyce/hilbert/problems.html>.
[46]Jeremy J. Gray, The Hilbert Challenge, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), p. 2.
[47]Kurt Gödel, Consistency of the axiom of choice and of the generalized continuum-hypothesis with the axioms of set theory, (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1940).
[48]J. Fang, Hilbert: Towards a Philosophy of Modern Mathematics, (New York: Paideia Press, 1970), pp. 120-121.
[49]Jeremy Gray, The Hilbert Challenge, (Oxford, Oxford University Press: 2000), p. 287.
[50]J. Fang, Hilbert: Towards a Philosophy of Modern Mathematics, (New York: Paideia Press, 1970), p. 121.
[51]Daivd Hilbert, “Mathematical Problems,” lecture delivered before the International Congress of Mathematicians at Paris in 1900. Dr. Mary Winston Newson translated this address into English with the author's permission for Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 8 (1902), 437-479. A reprint of appears in Mathematical Developments Arising from Hilbert Problems, edited by Felix Brouder, American Mathematical Society, 1976. I gained access to this source from <http://aleph0.clarku.edu/~djoyce/hilbert/problems.html>.
[52]It is interesting to note that Weyl had numerous interesting reactions to Gödel’s theorems, for example proclaiming that God must exist because mathematics is consistent, and that the Devil must similarly exist as well because we cannot prove its consistency. See Morris Kline, Mathematics:The Loss of Certainty, (New York: Oxford University Press, 1980), p. 261.
[53]Hermann Weyl, “The Mathematical Way of Thinking,” Science, New Series, Vol. 92, No. 2394, (Nov. 15, 1940), pp. 446.