Erich Fromm on the difference between authoritarian and humanistic conscience 

 

 

 

A. Authoritarian conscience

 

 

The contents of the authoritarian conscience are derived from the commands and taboos of the authority; its strength is rooted in the emotions of fear of, and admiration for, the authority. Good conscience is consciousness of pleasing the (external and internalized) authority; guilty conscience id the consciousness of displeasing it. The good  (authoritarian) conscience produces a feeling of well being and security for it implies approval by, and greater closeness to, the authority; the guilty conscience produces fear and insecurity, because acting against the will of the authority implies the danger of being punished and – what is worse – of being deserted by the authority.

 

 

In order to understand the full impact of the last statement we must remember that character structure of the authoritarian person. He has found inner security by becoming, symbiotically, part of the authority felt to be greater and more powerful than himself. As long as he is part of that authority – at the expense of his own integrity – he feels that he is participating in the authority’s strength. His feeling of certainty and identity depends on this symbiosis; to be rejected by the authority means to be thrown into a void, to face the horror of nothingness. Anything, to the authoritarian character, is better than this. To be sure, the love and approval of the authority give him the greatest satisfaction; but even punishment is better than rejection. The punishing authority is still with him, and if he has “sinned”, the punishment is at least proof that the authority still cares.

 

 

As long as peoples relationships to the authority remains external, without ethical sanction, we can hardly speak of conscience; such conduct is merely expediential, regulated by fear of punishment and hope for reward, always dependent on the presence of these authorities, on their knowledge of what one is doing, and their alleged or real ability to punish and to reward. Often an experience which people take to be a feeling of guilt springing from their conscience is really nothing but their fear of such authorities. Properly speaking, these people do not feel guilty but afraid. In the formation of the conscience, however, such authorities as the parents, the church, the state, public opinion are either consciously or unconsciously accepted as ethical and moral legislators whose laws and sanctions one adopts, thus internalizing them. The laws and sanctions of external authority become part of oneself, as it were, and instead of feeling responsible to something outside oneself, one feels responsible to something inside, to ones conscience. Conscience is a more effective regulator of conduct than fear of external authority; for while one can run from the latter, one can not escape from the internalized authority which has become part of oneself. While authoritarian conscience is different from fear if punishment and hope for reward, the relationship to the authority having become internalized, it is not very different in other essential respects. The most important point of similarity is the fact that the prescriptions of authoritarian conscience are not determined by one’s own value judgment but exclusively by the fact that its commands and taboos are pronounced by authorities .If these norms happen to be good, conscience will guide man’s actions in the direction of the good. However, they have not become the norms of conscience because they are good, but because they are the norms given by authority. If they are bad, they are just as much as part of conscience. A believer in Hitler, for instance, felt he was acting according to his conscience when he committed acts that where humanly revolting.

 

 

The prime offense in the authoritarian situation is rebellion against the authority’s rule. Thus, disobedience becomes the “cardinal sin”; obedience, then cardinal virtue. Obedience implies the recognition of the authority’s superior power and wisdom; his right to command, to reward, and to punish according to his own fiats. The authority demands submission not only because of the fear of its power, but out of the conviction of its moral superiority and right. The duty of recognizing the authority’s superiority results in several prohibitions. The most comprehensive of these is the taboo against feeling oneself to be, or ever be able to become, like the authority, for this would contradict the latter’s unqualified superiority and uniqueness. The real sin of Adam and Eve is the attempt to become like God; and it is a punishment for this challenge that they are expelled from the Garden of Eden. In authoritarian systems the authority is made out to be fundamentally different from his subjects. He has powers not attainable by anyone else: magic, wisdom, strength which can never be matched by his subjects. Whatever the authority’s prerogatives are, whether he is the master of the universe of a unique leader send by fate, the fundamental inequality between him and man is the basic tenet of authoritarian conscience. One particular important aspect of the uniqueness of the authority is the privilege of being the only one who does not follow another’s will, but who himself wills; who is not a means but and end in himself; who creates and is not created. In the authoritarian orientation, the power of will and creation are the privilege of the authority. Those subjected to him are means to his end and, consequently, his property and used by him for own purpose.

 

 

But man has never yet ceased striving to produce and to create because productiveness is the source of strength, freedom, and happiness. However, to the extent to which he feels dependent on powers transcending him, his very productiveness, the assertion of his free will, makes him feel guilty. This feeling of guilt, in turn, weakens man, reduces his power, and increases his submission in order to atone for his attempt to be his “own creator and builder.” Paradoxically, the authoritarian guilty conscience is a result of the feeling if strength, independence, productiveness, and pride, while the authoritarian good conscience springs from the feeling of obedience, dependence, powerlessness, and sinfulness. St. Paul, Augustine, Luther, and Calvin have describes this good conscience in unmistakable terms. To be aware of one’s powerlessness, to despise oneself, to be burdened by the feeling of one’s own sinfulness and wickedness are sign of goodness. The very fact of having a guilty conscience is the symptom of one’s virtue because the guilty conscience is a symptom of one’s “fear and trembling” before the authority.

 

 

The internalization of authority has two implications: one where man submits to the authority, the other where man takes over the role of the authority by treating himself with the same strictness and cruelty. Man thus becomes not only the obedient slave but also the strict taskmaster who treats himself as his own slave. This second implication is very important for the understanding of the psychological mechanisms of authoritarian conscience. The authoritarian character, being more or less crippled in his productiveness, develops a certain amount of sadism and destructiveness. These destructive energies are discharged by taking over the role of the authority and dominating oneself as the servant.

 

 

The dependence on irrational authority results in a weakening of will in the dependent person and, at the same time, whatever tends to paralyze the will makes for an increase in dependence. Thus, a vicious circle is formed. We ignore the fact that we too bow down to powers, not to that of a dictator and a political bureaucracy allied with him, but to the anonymous power of the market, of success and public opinion, of “common sense” – or rather, of common nonsense, and of the machine whose servants we have become. Our moral problem is man’s indifference to himself. It lies in the fact that we have lost the sense of significance, that we have made ourselves into instruments for purposes outside ourselves, that we experience and treat ourselves as commodities and that our own powers have become alienated from ourselves. We have become things and our neighbors have become things. The result is that we are powerless and despise ourselves for our impotence. Since we do not trust our own power, we have no faith in man, no faith in ourselves or in what our own powers can create. We have no conscience in the humanistic sense, since we do not dare to trust our judgment. We are a herd believing that the road we follow must lead to a goal since everybody else is on the same road.

 

 

Again the word “responsibility” has lost it’s original meaning and is usually used as a synonym for duty. The authoritarian conscience is essentially the readiness to follow the orders of the authorities to which one submits; it is glorified obedience. The humanistic conscience is the readiness to listen to the voice of one’s own humanity and is independent of orders given by anyone else.

 

 

 

B. Humanistic conscience

 

 

Humanistic conscience is not the internalized voice of an authority whom we are eager to please and afraid of displeasing; it is our own voice, present in every human being and independent of external sanctions and rewards. What is the nature of this voice? Why do we hear it and why can we become deaf to it? Conscience judges our functioning as human beings; it is (as the root of the word con-scientia indicates) knowledge within oneself, knowledge of our respective success or failure in the art of living.

 

 

Actions, thoughts, and feelings which are conducive to the proper functioning and unfolding of our total personality produce a feeling of inner approval, of “rightness”, characteristic of the humanistic “good conscience.” On the other hand, acts, thoughts, and feelings injurious to our total personality produce a feeling of uneasiness and discomfort, characteristic of the “ guilty conscience.” Conscience is thus a reaction a re-action of ourselves to ourselves. It is the voice of our true selves, which summons us back to ourselves, to live productively, to develop fully and harmoniously – that is, to become fully what we potentially are. It is the guardian of our integrity.

 

 

It is the guardian of our integrity; it is the “ability to guarantee one’s self with all due pride, and also at the same time to say yes to one’s self (Nietsche, the Genealogy of Morals).” If love can be defined as the affirmation of the potentialities and the care for, and the respect of, the uniqueness of the loved person, humanistic conscience can be justly called the voice of our loving care for ourselves. Humanistic conscience represents not only the expression of our true selves; it contains also the essence of our moral experiences in life. In it we preserve the knowledge of our aim in life and of the principles through which attain it; those principles which we have discovered ourselves as well as those we have learned from others and which we have found to be true.

 

 

Humanistic conscience is the expression of man’s self interest and integrity, while authoritarian conscience is concerned with man’s obedience, self-sacrifice, duty, or his” social adjustment.” The goal of humanistic conscience is productiveness and, therefore happiness, since happiness is the necessary concomitant of productive living. To cripple oneself by becoming a tool of others, no matter how dignified they are made to appear, to be “selfless, “ unhappy, resigned, discouraged, is in opposition to the demands of one’s conscience; any violation of the integrity and proper functioning of our personality, with regard to thinking as well as acting, and even with regard to such matters as taste for food or sexual behavior is acting against one’s conscience.

 

 

But is our analysis of conscience not contradicted by the fact that in many people its voice is so feeble as not be heard and acted upon? Indeed, this fact is the reason for the moral precariousness of the human situation. If conscience always spoke loudly and distinctly enough, only a few would be mislead from their moral objective. One answer follows from the very nature of conscience itself: since its function is to be the guardian of man’s true self-interest, it is alive to the extent to which the person has not lost himself entirely and become the prey of his own indifference and destructiveness. The relation to one’s own productiveness is one of interaction. The more productively one lives, the stronger is one’s conscience, and , in turn furthers one’s productiveness. The less productive one lives, the weaker become one’s conscience; the paradoxical – and tragic – situation of man is that his conscience is weakest when he needs it most.

 

Another answer to the question of the relative ineffectiveness of consciousness is our refusal to listen and – what is even more important – our ignorance of knowing how to listen. People are often under the illusion that their conscience will speak with a loud voice and its message will be clear and distinct; waiting for such a voice, they do not hear anything. But when the voice of conscience is feeble; it is indistinct; and one has to learn how to listen and understand it communication in order to act accordingly.

 

 

However, learning to understand the communications of one’s conscience is exceedingly difficult, mainly for two reasons. In order to listen to the voice of our conscience we must be able to listen to ourselves, and this is exactly what most people in our culture have difficulties in doing. We listen to every voice and to everybody but not to ourselves. We are constantly exposed to the noise of opinions and ideas hammering at us from everywhere: motion pictures, newspapers, radio, idle chatter. If we had planned intentionally to prevent ourselves from ever listening to ourselves, we could have done no better.

Listening to ourselves is so difficult because this art requires another ability, rare in modern man: that of being alone with oneself. In fact, we have developed a phobia of being alone; we prefer the most trivial and even obnoxious company, the meaningless activities, to being with ourselves; we seem to be frightened at the prospect of facing ourselves. Is it because we feel we would be such bad company? I think the fear of being alone with ourselves is rather a feeling of embarrassment, bordering sometimes on terror at seeing a person at once so well known and so strange; we are afraid and run away. We thus miss the chance of listening to ourselves, and we continue to ignore our conscience.

 

Listening to the feeble and indistinct voice of our conscience is difficult also because it does not speak to us directly and because we are often not aware that it is our conscience which disturbs us. We may feel only anxious (or even sick) for a number of reasons which have no apparent connection with our conscience. Perhaps the most frequent indirect reaction of our conscience to being neglected is a vague and unspecific feeling of guilt and uneasiness, of simply a feeling of tiredness or listlessness. Sometimes such feelings are rationalized as guilt feelings for not having done this or that, when actually the omission one feels guilty about do not constitute genuine moral problems. But if the genuine though unconscious feeling of guilt has become so strong to be silenced by superficial rationalizations, it finds expression in deeper and more intense anxieties and even in physical and mental sickness.

 

 

Humanistic ethics takes the position that if man is alive he knows what is allowed; and to be alive means to be productive, to use one’s powers not for any purpose transcending man, but for oneself, to make sense of one’s existence, to be human. As long as anyone believes that his ideal and purpose is outside him, that it is above the clouds, in the past or in the future, he will go outside himself and seek fulfillment where it can not be found. He will look for solutions and answers at every point except the one where they can be found – in himself.

 

 

 

 

Please take me back to the previous page