The Austrian school of economics is well known for its "realistic"
approach to the study of human action. This importance which Austrian
economists place on reality is very similar to that which followers of
the philosophy of Objectivism adhere to. The two schools of thought are
very similar in that they both hold that "certainty is a relation
between an individual mind and reality" (Kelley 2000, p. 70). That is to
say, both Austrian economists and Objectivists believe that truth must
be discovered and understood in the context of reality. Austrian
economists are well known for their distaste for abstract models, and
Objectivists are similarly famous – if also often mocked – for their
rigid adherence to reason as a tool of perception.
Objectivism, then, can be seen as the logical
philosophical and ethical extension of Austrian economics, much as
laissez-faire libertarianism can be seen as the logical political
extension of Austrian economics. Or, viewed from the other side, the
reality-based methodology of the Austrian school is the perfect tool for
the Objectivist interested in economic studies. Austrian economics and
Objectivism fit very well as two aspects of the same worldview(1).
There are several important areas in which Austrian economists
and Objectivists agree, including the importance they place on the
virtue of rationality and a priori logic; their embracing of
reality as a standard of action and the empirical world as a subject
worthy of study; their advocacy of capitalism as the path to a more
productive society; and the fact that each discipline (especially
Objectivism) discovered a similar way to bridge the problematic
mind-body gap, or dichotomy.
What is Austrian economics? |
The Austrian school of economics (so-called
because its early members lived in Austria) was founded in the late
nineteenth century by Carl Menger (Callahan 204). It is the school of
economists who pride themselves on basing their theories and policy
recommendations on the reality of human action. In contrast to the
followers of the more mainstream schools of economics, who have a
tendency to get caught up in abstract thought experiments (commonly
making false recommendations and/or inaccurate predictions as a result),
Austrians believe that "economics ought to be relevant to real life"
(Callahan 204). Austrians base their work on the "Action Axiom," which
states very simply that: "Humans act." Ludwig von Mises states it this
way:
Human action
is purposive behavior. Or we may say: Action is will put into
operation and transformed into an agency, is aiming at ends and
goals, is the ego's meaningful response to stimuli and to the
conditions of its environment, is a person's conscious adjustment to
the state of the universe that determines life (Mises 1963, p. 11). |
For the Austrian, action is purposive,
rational, goal-driven behavior. Only the actions of humans interest the
Austrian economist, since he can only be certain of humans' rationality.
The study of the actions of animals and other apparently non-rational
animals is left to the biologist who studies them with far different
tools than the economist uses to address his work. Precisely because the
economist can apply his knowledge of what it is to be human, he can
study the actions of humans in a far different way than he could study
the actions of, say, a dog. The economist not only uses his rational
mind to address the problems of economics, but he assumes that his
subjects have rationality – and employ it – as well. For this reason,
the term "human action" is limited to purposive behavior.
The a priori deductive nature of the Austrian
economist's method (using his reason as a tool) is what sets the
Austrian school apart from other, more mainstream schools. Economics as
a discipline focuses on observing the regularity of what may be called
market phenomena. Human action is what causes market phenomena, and the
Austrians believe that the best way to study the occurrences of the
market is to study their cause: human action in the face of uncertainty.
It is this application of reason which sets Austrian economics apart
from most other disciplines, which attempt to imitate the scientific
method of the biologist or the physicist. The reason-based methodology
of the Austrian school is what makes it such an appropriate economic
method for the Objectivist to use.
The philosophy of Objectivism, founded by
the twentieth-century philosopher Ayn Rand(2),
puts a strong emphasis on reason as a tool of cognition, and on the
virtue of rationality as being essential for any productive activity.
When Ayn Rand was asked to summarize her philosophy, she answered:
1. Metaphysics:
Objective Reality. ('Nature, to be commanded, must be obeyed.')
2. Epistemology: Reason. ('You can't have your cake and eat it
too.')
3. Ethics: Self-Interest. ('Man is an end in himself.')
4. Politics: Capitalism. ('Give me liberty or give me death.') (Rand
1989, p. 3) |
Objectivism focuses on the importance of the
individual, and the absolute necessity of understanding reality and
basing one's rational actions on it.
Objectivism is often falsely accused of being nothing but a
new and more complex form of hedonism. It is important before continuing
that we address this question, and show that Objectivism is not a
form of hedonism.
Hedonism is the ethical doctrine which states that "pleasure
is the ultimate good for humans" (Feinburg 2002, p. 781). In practice,
hedonism is the doctrine followed by those who base their actions
only on the idea that each man must do what will bring him the most
happiness, as subjectively determined by his own desires. The hedonist
does not sacrifice himself for others' welfare, but if he sees fit, he
may sacrifice others for his own welfare.
In contrast, Objectivism states explicitly that a man must not
sacrifice others for his own welfare.
Central to Rand's ideal of benevolent egoism are the following
two principles:
P1: I should never
sacrifice myself for the benefit of others.
P2: I should never sacrifice others for the benefit of myself. (Huemer
2001, p. 1) |
Objectivism is, in fact, a combination of
two principles which had seemed to be mutually exclusive until combined
in this form. On the one hand, the objectivist believes (as do most
followers of traditional Western Judeo-Christian religions) that he may
not prey upon his fellow rational beings for his own benefit. On the
other hand, he believes (as does the hedonist) that he must seek his own
highest good, and that he may not allow his fellow rational beings to
prey upon him. This set of rational principles is the base of
Objectivism and as we will see, the cause of Objectivism's close kinship
with Austrian economics.
At first appraisal, there appears to be a
conflict between Mises' value-neutrality (or value-subjectivity) and
Rand's argument for the importance of objectivity. However, on closer
observation it is apparent that the difference is in the respective
function of the values in question. While both Rand and Mises focus on
the acting man, Mises recommends values for the observer of the action
as an observer (namely, value-neutrality), whereas Rand
recommends values for the actor himself as an actor (namely,
objective and life-enhancing values). When Mises advocates
value-neutrality, he refers to the idea that the good economist refrains
from imposing his own subjective preferences on those acting humans whom
he observes. The economist may not observe a tribal shaman and conclude
that "a rain dance will not work." He may simply watch; he may describe;
he may explain the shaman's actions within the scope of economics,
saying, "The shaman employs the rain dance as a means to obtain the end
of a rainstorm occurring."
For the economist, value-neutrality (understanding that each actor's
values are subjective and that, as an economist, one may not condemn
those individual values) is much like the imaginary construct of the
Evenly Rotating Economy; it is a necessary methodological tool for use
in economic appraisal. It is not a source of facts; it is not meant as a
basis for real-world action; it does not affect reality. Rather, "value
freedom is a methodological device designed to separate and isolate an
economist's scientific work from the personal preferences of the given
economic researcher" (Younkins 2004a, p. 3).
Mises' value-neutrality in the economic realm does not mean
that his ideas cannot be integrated with Objectivism's strong
value-objectivity. Indeed, his definition of value as "the importance
that acting man attaches to ultimate ends" (Mises 1963, p. 96) is
perfectly complementary to Rand's definition of value as "that which one
acts to gain and/or keep" (Rand 1964, p. 27). Each school of thought
uses the concept of "value" to describe the goals which acting man
strives towards. "A value is an object of human action" (Merrill 1991,
p. 100). Each man's goals are subjective in the sense that they relate
to his specific circumstances, and objective in the sense that they
relate to concrete reality.
Where Austrian economics is primarily descriptive in nature,
Objectivism goes on to prescribe what acting humans ought to
value. The objectivist believes that for each man, his own life is the
highest value he may strive toward. Each man makes a basic choice: to
live or to die. The man who chooses to live, must (to be rationally
consistent) also choose those smaller ends which will further the
ultimate value which he has chosen, his own life. "The fact that living
entities exist and function necessitates the existence of values and of
an ultimate value which for any given living entity is its own life"
(Rand 1964, p. 27). Rand's position on this is the same as that of
Aristotle; she holds that value is objective in the sense that there is
one ultimate value that correlates with the natural end ("telos,"
or goal) of the entity. The ultimate end for a living entity is to
continue its existence.
Although this appears at first glace to be a circular argument
("a living entities lives in order to continue its own life"), and hence
a pointless claim, one can see after some thought that it is not a
meaningless argument, when applied to human beings. Humans can, and in
fact often do, act contrary to the furtherance of their own lives. Rand
controversially used the term "altruism" to refer to non-life enhancing
behavior of a particular sort which she felt to be the most common.
Altruism, in the objectivist sense, is the approach to life which places
sacrifice as the highest ideal.
The basic
principle of altruism is that man has no right to exist for his own
sake, that service to others is the only justification of his
existence, and that self-sacrifice is his highest moral duty, virtue
and value (Rand 1982, p. 61). |
The important thing to remember when
discussing the objectivist concept of altruism is that there is a very
strong difference between "altruism" and "benevolence." The objectivist
does not claim that, for instance, Mother Theresa acted irrationally.
Her actions were benevolent: she simply desired the happiness of
others as her goal. She did not act to destroy herself – she acted to
help others. This is a concept which any economist understands
perfectly; no human acts contrary to reason or to the laws of economics
when he or she desires the happiness of others. However, the objectivist
believes that when a human acts according to the principles of altruism,
he is acting contrary to reason, since he is denying (in deed, if not in
word) that his life is his highest value. For the altruist, sacrifice is
his highest value; since sacrifice means giving up a higher value in
favor of a lesser, then the logical conclusion of altruism is death.
This is why it is important to state the principle that "an
ultimate value… for any given living entity is its own life" (Rand 1964,
p. 27). Man, of all the animals, has the strange option of choosing to
act contrary to his own welfare on a continual basis, or of choosing to
live according to principles which will help him achieve his own highest
value: his life. Thus we see that for the objectivist, as well as for
the Austrian economist, the term "value," when used in reference to man,
means "goal pursued by a acting being with volitional consciousness" –
values are goals, not ethical codes of action.
Interestingly enough, it is not Mises, but his predecessor
Carl Menger who agrees more explicitly with Ayn Rand's value theory. "Menger
and Rand agree that the ultimate standard of value is the life of the
valuer" (Younkins 2004b, p. 7). Menger specifies in his definition of
value that man's life is its source. Following in the footsteps of
Aristotle, he claims that:
the attempt to
provide for the satisfaction of our needs is synonymous with the
attempt to provide for our lives and well-being. It is the most
important of all human endeavors, since it is the prerequisite and
foundation of all others (Menger 1981, p. 77). |
For Menger, "Man… becomes the ultimate cause
as well as the ultimate end in the process of want satisfaction" (Younkins
2004b, p. 1). Without human beings, who are capable of choice and
subjective desires, the concept of value is nonsensical. It is the fact
that existence exists which makes valuation possible – which makes
choice possible – which makes the desire for economic activity and
satisfaction of economic wants possible. Without human life there would
not be human action; Menger recognizes this and bases his value theory
on man much more explicitly than does Mises. It is "life, the process of
self-sustaining and self-generated action, which makes the concept of
'value' meaningful" (Younkins 2004a, p. 7). Value is necessarily based
on life.
The importance of the individual and his
volitional consciousness |
Both Austrian economics and Objectivism
recognize that only the human individual can hold and act upon the kind
of values which are worthy of study(3). Values
cannot be held collectively; neither can the values of two different
rational beings be compared to one another. The study of the individual
actor is therefore of utmost importance to both the Austrian economist
and the objectivist.
Humans are the only "animals" which are capable of action and
rationality; capable of choosing to be or not to be; and capable not
only of living, but of choosing how to live. Man may, and
generally does, choose life. According to Mises, "To live is for man the
outcome of a choice, of a judgment of value;" (Mises 1963, p. 20) or,
according to Rand, "Man has to be man by choice…" (Rand 1964 p. 27). It
is this unique aspect of mankind which makes the study of human action
so fascinating, and so paradoxical.
The economist cannot go about his work in the same way that,
for instance, a biologist can, for a very interesting reason. The
economist cannot create scientific experiments, in the sense that a
biologist can, because humans act, and more specifically, because humans
learn in a sense that no other animal does. If the economist were to
attempt to create a valid scientific experiment (even disregarding such
issues as the morality or immorality of using humans as experimental
subjects), it would be impossible for him to study humans as they act
"naturally," since humans act differently when they know they are being
observed! The economist could not create a repeatable study, since each
human is so drastically different from every other human that the
observing economist could never build a controlled experiment. Human
action itself prohibits the use of "scientific" methods in the
observation of such; the very subject of the economist's study prevents
him from using the methods of the traditional, physical sciences. "There
cannot be controlled experiments when we confront the real world
of human activity" (Rothbard 1977, p. 58). Austrian economics is the
only branch of economics which studies man with the special tool
available to study him with: namely, reason. Only man can be studied in
a completely rational way, because only man is equipped with reason.
This is why the scientist cannot study giraffes by relying on reason
alone, but must resort to empirical sources for his work. The scientist
who wishes to study human action (the economist), however, can study
this subject from the inside out, as it were, since he is himself a man
and has an understanding of the motivations of other men(4).
Each man is an individual entity, not to be compared with other men too
closely; each man has a subjective scale of values (different from that
of his neighbor) and a means-end framework for achieving those values
(also different from that of his neighbor.
Central to the method of the Austrian economist is the
adherence to methodological individualism, meaning that this form
of economic study "deals with the actions of individual men" (Mises
1963, p. 41). Man acts as part of a social whole, and the economist must
never forget or ignore that fact, but what the individual actions of
individual men are what make up the social whole. Human action cannot be
studied in the aggregate; the Austrian economist believes that to make
sense of his discipline he must focus on the individual man. "A great
deal may be learned about society by studying man; but this process
cannot be reversed: nothing can be learned about man by studying
society" (Rand 1967, p. 15). The Austrian economist always remembers
that man is part of a social whole, but he places the emphasis of his
study on the individual actor.
Part II
The action axiom
Ludwig von Mises, who was the great champion of Austrian economics in
the twentieth century, believed that "the laws of economics are
fundamentally logical relationships and not empirical relationships" (Ebeling
1997, xvi.). This means that the uneducated layman, using his natural
powers of reason, in principle can deduce the laws of economics from the
axiom that "Humans act." In this sense, economics is more of a
philosophical science (akin to mathematics) or social science (akin to
psychology) than a physical one (such as biology).
The action axiom "is the fundamental and universal truth that individual
men exist and act by making purposive choices among alternatives" (Younkins
2004b, p. 1). For Mises, the action axiom is the "first principle" of
economics, from which all other economic truths can be deduced a
priori (meaning, roughly, that once you accept the action axiom,
these other truths are self-evident and require no sensory evidence to
verify them).
Action implies two important things. First, it implies a
values scale; an individual, subjective ranking of values, or goals,
which the actor in question desires to reach. Secondly, it implies that
a means-end framework is held by the actor. That is, the actor has ends
which he wishes to reach, and employs certain means to reach them. These
ends (or "values") are subjective; they depend entirely on the desires
and preferences of the actor in question. The means which the actor
employs to reach his ends are also subjective; whether or not the means
actually will assist the actor in achieving his end, he believes that
they will, and he is therefore acting rationally. For Mises, to act
means "purposeful behavior… or, aiming at ends and goals…" (Mises 1963,
p. 11). Action is rational choice in the face of scarcity.
These two truths (that an actor has a values-scale and a
means-end framework which he employs to reach those values) are only two
of the many things implied by the action axiom. The importance which
Mises placed on human rationality is evident; for him, the rational mind
is the all-important tool of the economist.
Objectivism places a similar importance on rationality. For
the objectivist, "Rationality is man's basic virtue, the source of all
his other virtues… The virtue of Rationality means the recognition and
acceptance of reason as one's only source of knowledge, one's only judge
of values and one's only guide to action… It means a commitment to the
reality of one's own existence" (Rand 1964, p. 20). The Austrian
economist goes so far as to claim rationality as the appropriate method
for discovery of economic truth; the objectivist goes further, and
asserts that rationality is the appropriate method for discovery of all
aspects of reality, in ethics as well as intellectual endeavors. The
difference between the two conceptions of reason is that while the
Austrian economist bases his methodology on a prioristic
reasoning, the objectivist's reasoning is more grounded in empirical
truth, and the reality of the physical world. Nonetheless, the two
disciples are compatible; the objectivist can quite consistently be an
Austrian economist, and vice versa. As Hans Hoppe puts it:
A priori
knowledge must be as much a mental thing as a reflection of the
structure of reality, since it is only through actions that the mind
comes into contact with reality… Acting is a cognitively guided
adjustment of a physical body in a physical reality… a priori
knowledge… must indeed correspond to the nature of things. The
realistic character of such knowledge would manifest itself not only
in the fact that one could not think it to be otherwise, but
in the fact that one could not undo its truth (Hoppe 1995, p.
9). |
Knowledge, according to Hoppe, must be based
in both reality and the mind, especially knowledge of human action.
Economics focuses on human action, and reason, as the tool which man
uses to integrate and isolate information received from his senses, is
the appropriate tool for this study. Herein lies the connection between
the Austrian methodology and the objectivist worldview.
The objectivist recognizes that reason, the use of his
rational mind, is man's tool for choosing and striving after his values.
"Rationality is a matter of choice – and the alternative [man's] nature
offers him is: rational being or suicidal animal" (Rand 1957, p.
931-932). This ability to choose between life and death, rather than
blindly following animal instincts, is what sets man apart in the world.
"The ingenuity of man is his noblest and most joyous power" (Rand 1957,
p. 682). Man's individual ability to rationally choose among
alternatives, and even create new alternatives when he is unsatisfied
with those available, is what makes it necessary, and possible, for him
to have values and codes of morality (valid or invalid). It is this
ability which makes human action possible. And it is this ability which
requires that man discover, and adhere to, a rational code of morality
which has a strong foundation in reality and truth.
Reality Is Real – Existence Exists |
What Objectivism offers that sets it apart
from other philosophical systems is this: Objectivism says that
knowledge is achievable – that reality is not only knowable but
must be acknowledged. In short, Objectivism accepts and embraces
the reality which mainstream philosophy evades. "Objectivism, with its
confident assertion that philosophical problems can be solved
once and for all – that there are two sides to every question, the right
side and the wrong side – is profoundly antithetical to the
philosophical tradition of the twentieth century" (Merrill 1991, p. 90).
Objectivism holds reality itself as a philosophical standard
of value. Values come from reality, and so are not subjective in a broad
sense, but only in an individual one. That is to say: good and evil are
objective, but the individual good (or "value") which each man pursues
is a subjective choice which he makes for himself. Man's choice of
values is indeed subjective, but the values which he may choose among
are not. Once he has chosen his goal, reality imposes on him a standard
which dictates how he may or may not reach that goal. "Since values are
determined by the nature of reality, it is reality that serves as men's
ultimate arbiter" (Rand 1967, p. 24).
Values which a man may strive toward exist in reality before
he chooses among them. He may choose to live or to die; life and death
exist as possible choices regardless of his decision. He may choose to
accept and act upon the choices presented to him by reality or he may
choose to deny them and "live" in the non-rational surreality which the
philosophers of the twentieth century would have him believe is his only
option; insanity and rationality exist as possibilities no matter what
he decides. Reality will not change to make way for his subjective whim
(if he desires something which is impossible); existence exists. The
power of the individual is the power of choice, and of striving towards
the chosen values. Reality is necessarily man's standard of choice as
well as his source of values to choose among. It is this unflinching
claim on reality as a moral standard which is Objectivism's distinction
in the fields of philosophy and ethics.
It is precisely this adherence to reality which makes Austrian
economics unique in its field; the object of economics, for the
Austrian, is to obtain valid knowledge about the real world and how
humans interact with it. As Mises said, "[t]he end of science is to know
reality" (Mises 1963, p. 65). The ultimate aim of the observing
economist is to think his way to objective and rational truth, in the
form of economic laws and theories. Mises defined the subject matter of
economics (rather awkwardly) as follows: "The elucidation and the
categorical and formal examination of… the regularity of phenomena with
regard to the interconnectedness of means and ends… is the subject
matter of economics" (Mises 1963, p. 885). In other words, economics is
interested in reality; specifically that aspect of reality which is
evident in the way that humans use means to achieve ends. Formally
observing the regularity of human action in this respect is what the
economist does; this is the truth which he searches for. For the
economist as well as for the objectivist, truth "is the recognition of
reality; reason, man's only means of knowledge, is his only means of
truth" (Rand 1961, p. 126) For the Austrian economist, reason is both
his subject of study (specifically, how humans employ reason as one
means to achieve their subjectively acquired values) and his means of
study (since for Mises, economic thought is aprioristic in nature, and
relies solely on the action of reason to reach a logical conclusion or
assertion).
Reason and rationality, though, are even more important than
this. It is through the proper understanding of reason that both Mises
and Rand managed to successfully bridge the so-called mind-body
dichotomy which had bothered philosophers for centuries. The
relationship between value and reason is what made this possible; value
is based implicitly on the relationship between rational man and
reality. It is rational valuation which bridges the problematic
mind-body gap.
The Mind-Body Dichotomy and Its Answer
|
The mind-body gap (or dichotomy) is only one
of three dichotomies which nineteenth century philosophers grappled
with. Ayn Rand argues that all three are invalid. The first is the
analytic-synthetic dichotomy, which we will not touch on in this paper;
the second is the mind-body dichotomy, which states that man must choose
between his mind and/or soul (which serves as the symbol of spiritual
things) and his body (which serves as the symbol of material things);
and the third is the is-ought problem, which stems directly from the
mind-body dichotomy, and which states, essentially, that since one
cannot know reality (since there is no connection between the mind and
physical reality), then one cannot advocate codes of behavior for
oneself or other humans. David Hume is one of the most important
philosophers involved in the beginning of this debate; it was he who
pointed out that even if one can know reality, such knowledge is
not enough to determine moral oughts. An argument along the lines of
"man is a living being, therefore one ought not to kill
him," is an invalid argument. How can one use an argument based on what
'is' to determine what one 'ought' to do? So goes the argument based on
the mind-body/is-ought argument, which Mises and Rand both solved
satisfactorily.
The mind-body dichotomy began, historically, with the French
philosopher René Descartes. Famous for arguing that a thing must be
true, if he was capable of conceiving a clear and distinct idea of it(1),
he wrote that:
because, on
the one hand, I have a clear and distinct idea of myself, in as far
as I am only a thinking and unextended thing, and as, on the other
hand, I possess a distinct idea of body, in as far as it is only an
extended and unthinking thing, it is certain that 'I'… that is, my
mind, by which I am what I am… is entirely and truly distinct from
my body, and may exist without it (Descartes 1974 p. 165). |
Descartes believed that since he had a
"clear and distinct idea" of his body and his mind existing separately,
then mind and body must indeed be two separate substances; and in this
logically invalid argument one can see the source of the unnecessary
problem which vexed philosophers for centuries to come.
The
dichotomy continued to perplex philosophers because they failed to
recognize the close relationship between human life and reality. Mises
wrote that, in his time, "the relation between reason and experience has
long been one of the fundamental philosophical problems" (Mises 1963, p.
39). The advocates of philosophies which are not based on the connection
between reason and reality took this distinction to its logical
conclusion when, over the centuries, they advocated that man either
totally abandon himself to the pursuits of physical pleasure (as, for
instance, hedonism recommends) or completely give himself over to the
activities of the mind and spirit (it is this last which many forms of
spiritual aestheticism occupied themselves with). The mind-body
dichotomy "cut man in two, setting one half against the other. [It has]
taught him that his body and his consciousness are two enemies engaged
in deadly conflict, two antagonists of opposite natures, contradictory
claims, incompatible needs, that to benefit one is to injure the other,
that his soul belongs to a supernatural realm, but his body is an evil
prison holding it in bondage to this earth – and that the good is to
defeat his body, to undermine it by years of patient struggle, digging
his way to that glorious jail-break which leads into the freedom of the
grave" (Rand 1961, p. 138). Rand, as we can see from this quote, was
most concerned about the tendency to reject the body in favor of the
mind (since, at the time when she wrote, the alternative – rejecting the
mind/soul in favor of material excess – was not a common
philosophical stand, however common it may have been in everyday
life). If the mind and body are divided in this way, there is indeed a
conflict between them. There is only one way to overcome the mind-body
problem: the acceptance of a synthesis of rational and empirical fact
and the re-acknowledgement of the inseparability of reason and reality.
The objectivist understands that there is no gap between mind
and body, or between reason and experience, because it is not possible
to consider the one out of the context of the other. It is irrational to
drop the context of the argument (or the situation at hand). Man is "an
indivisible entity of matter and consciousness" (Rand 1961, p. 142). It
is simply nonsensical to try to consider a choice between the material
world and the world of the mind. "Ideas divorced from consequent action
are fraudulent, and that action divorced from ideas is suicidal" (Rand
1961, p. 51). Rationality is the tool which man uses to value; values
are what guide human action. The empirical world and the intellectual
world are simply not divisible. Without one, the other has no purpose.
The Austrian economist, too, understands the necessary
relationship between reason and reality. As early as Carl Menger, the
first Austrian economist, this dichotomy was resolved: "Menger's theory
explains the inextricable ontological connection between the realm of
cognition and the sphere of objective causal processes that results from
valuation and economizing" (Younkins 2004a, p. 3). However, it is the
work of Hans Hoppe, a contemporary Austrian economist, which really
solidified the connection between mind and body. Hoppe explains that the
action axiom itself requires that there be a connection between mind and
body:
…in
substituting the model of the mind of an actor acting by means of a
physical body for the traditional rationalist model of an active
mind a priori knowledge immediately becomes realistic
knowledge (Hoppe 1995, p. 10). |
Since Austrian economics and Objectivism
have a similar understanding of the relationship between value,
rationality, and reality, it is only to be expected that philosophers in
both disciplines would reach a solution for the mind-body gap, and
consequently, the is-ought problem.
Objectivism holds that there are moral absolutes, and that they
are based on the relationship of man to reality. Man's nature as a human
being in the abstract determines what these moral absolutes are – each
man, to achieve the goal of happiness, must act in favor of his own
rational self-interest, in accordance with these moral principles.
"[Rand's] theory of rational egoism eliminates the breach between
interest and idealism: our happiness is to be achieved by fidelity to
moral absolutes that are grounded in man's nature as a living being"
(Kelley 2000, p. 75). The mind-body dichotomy is proven false by the
relationship of man's consciousness to reality. Man needs reality to
determine what actions are morally appropriate for him to undertake; his
soul cannot survive without his body. "A body with out a soul is a
corpse, a soul without a body is a ghost…" (Rand 1961, p. 138). Man is
neither corpse nor ghost – man is an acting being of volitional
consciousness, existing in a reality which is concrete and necessary.
If, as Mises and Rand argue, it is possible to maintain the
connection between the human mind and reality, then it is also possible
to specify what political-economic system is demanded by reality; if
man's mind can know reality, then it can identify how he ought to live.
By solving the mind-body problem, Mises and Rand discovered how to
determine the 'ought' from the 'is.'(2)
The 'ought' which Rand determined was
appropriate for the life of a rational, acting being, is capitalism.
Mises qualifies his endorsement of capitalism by pointing out that "All
that social policy can do is the remove the outer causes of pain and
suffering; it can further a system that feeds the hungry, clothes the
naked, and houses the homeless." (Mises 1997, p. xx) – that is to say,
capitalism is only the best alternative if one is in favor of
feeding, clothing, and housing the population. If one is in favor of a
state of affairs which would end in material comfort, then capitalism is
the society which the rational being must favor. According to modern
Austrian economist and objectivist George Reisman:
capitalism is
a social system based on private ownership of the means of
production. It is characterized by the pursuit of material
self-interest under freedom and it rests on a foundation of the
cultural influence of reason. (Reisman 1996, p. 19) |
Under this setup, the ideal economic system
is one without unnecessary government interference of any kind, where
the free market treats each individual in the same manner – it judges
him by what he brings to market. Capitalism is an inherently peaceful
system (since war is punished by economic disincentives), and it rewards
citizens of the system for fair interaction with one another. Under
capitalism, each citizen's cry is simply: Laissez-nous faire!(3)
Economics is value-neutral in the sense that the economist
does not force his personal, subjective value scale on the acting men he
observes. This does not mean, however, that Austrian economics is
value-neutral when it comes to recommending a governmental system. The
Austrian economist bases his recommendation on the idea that material
happiness (feeding the hungry, clothing the naked, housing the homeless,
etc.) is the goal of a government, and as a result finds himself
compelled to recommend a governmental system which also respects
individual rights(4). Only a government focused on
protecting individual liberty and property rights is such a system.
Mises tells us that "As far as the government… confines the exercise of
its violence and the threat of such violence to the suppression and
prevention of anti-social action, there prevails what reasonably and
meaningfully can be called liberty" (Mises 1963, p. 281). Liberty is a
very simple concept: when a man is free from the initiation of force
against him by others, he exists in a state of liberty. "The task of the
state consists solely and exclusively in guaranteeing the protection of
life, health, liberty, and private property against violent attacks.
Everything that goes beyond this is an evil" (Mises 1997, p. 52). This
implies that a free society, for Mises, is one in which no man may
lawfully initiate the use of force against others.
Objectivism even more explicitly advocates capitalism and a
free society based on the principle of non-initiation of force. In order
for a moral society to exist, it is necessary to have a system wherein
"no man may initiate the use of physical force against others"
(Rand 1964, p. 36, emphasis in original). Rand's solution to the
mind-body dichotomy makes it possible for Objectivism to derive "ought"
from "is" – that is, to take empirically valid facts about the reality
which is, and determine from those facts a moral code for how men should
act. This moral code is what the objectivist bases his argument for a
capitalistic free market government on. "The objectivist ethical code
constitutes a valid, verifiable morality, in which the distinction
between 'good' and 'bad' is not arbitrary or intuitive but logically
derivable from the facts of reality" (Merrill 1991, p. 106). The only
good/bad distinction which Objectivism makes that is relevant to the
appropriate-ness of a governmental system is the principle of
non-initiation of force.
Capitalism is the only type of society in history which has
been based upon this principle. Thus, it is capitalism which is the
social incarnation of the objectivist ethics. "The free market
represents the social application of an objective theory of
values" (Rand 1967, p. 24). The free market and the principle of
non-initiation of force are the logical conclusions (in a societal
sense) of the common principles which Objectivism and Austrian economics
share.
It is these shared values which make
Objectivism and Austrian economics compatible: their respect for
rationality; free choice; subjective and objective values, in
their appropriate contexts; reality; and most important in a practical
sense, a governmental system which allows for and protects a
capitalistic free market. Both objectivists and Austrian economists
understand that human action is the driving force of the universe; that
"every day human acts shape the world anew" (Lachman 1997, p. 29).
Footnotes: Part I
1. There is one major historical conflict between
Objectivism and Austrian economics which is worth noting, namely
that between Murray Rothbard and what he called "the Ayn Rand cult…
which flourished for just ten years in the 1960s." While the main
philosophical difference between Rothbard and Rand was the issue of
anarchism (Rand believed that the market for defense was a natural
monopoly, whereas Rothbard felt that it was a market open to
competition like any other and that it was inappropriate to have a
coercive government), Rothbard's 1972 article "The Sociology of the
Ayn Rand Cult" is a poorly defended attack on Rand's personal
character and the characters of her closest friends and associates.
Rothbard's claim that "the structure and implicit creed, the actual
functioning, of the Randian movement, was in striking and diametric
opposition to the official, exoteric creed of individuality, [and]
independence" ("The Sociology of the Ayn Rand Cult") is most
probably correct, but it does not constitute a strong enough
difference between Austrian economics and Objectivism for it to be
of any note. The behavior of professed followers of a philosophy is
hardly an appropriate method by which to judge the philosophy.
2. It must be stressed that for the purposes of this paper, I am
referring to the philosophy of Objectivism as such, not the actions
of Ayn Rand. It is her ideas which are relevant here, not the
details of her sensational private life.
3. When an animal instinctively acts to protect its own life or feed
itself it is not, as far as one can observe, acting in a rational
manner in the sense that it is choosing between life and death, so
it cannot hold values in the sense that a human being can.
4. It is important to point out that psychology, as a science, falls
into neither of these categories. It neither entirely relies on
reason as a tool to study human action, nor on the methods of
biological science to study human behavior. The special case of
psychology must acknowledge but is decidedly out of the scope of
this paper. |
Footnotes: Part II
1. It is important to realize that Descartes'
argument, although now discredited, is not as simple as it first
seems. The nuances of the argument lie in his very specific
definition of "clear and distinct idea."
2. Mises referred to himself as a utilitarian, but this does not
mean that he necessarily endorsed the is-ought dichotomy. A
utilitarian merely qualifies his argument with a reference to total
happiness. For instance, his argument might read as follows: "If
I want to maximize happiness, and X is B, then I ought
to Y."
3. The expression "laissez-faire capitalism" reputedly comes
from an incident at an overly regulated French factory, when a
government official asked the factory workers how else the
government could assist them, and they replied: "Laissez-nous
faire!" ("Leave us alone!")
4. While there are definite exceptions to the assertion that
Austrians are in favor of capitalism and free markets, notably in
such economists as Hans Meyer, it is reasonable for my purposes here
to make the generalization that, in a broad sense, Austrians
advocate governments based on the principle of non-initiation of
force. |
References
|
• Branden, Nathaniel. (1961) Who Is Ayn Rand?,
N.Y., N.Y: Random House.
• Callahan, Gene. (2001) Economics For Real People, Auburn,
AL: Ludwig von Mises Institute.
• Descartes, René. (1974) "Meditation VI," in The Rationalists,
trans. John Veitch, R. H. M. Else, and G. Montgomery, N.Y.: Anchor
Books.
• Ebeling, Richard M. (1997) "Introduction," in The Austrian
Reader, ed. Richard M. Ebeling, Hillsdale, MI: Hillsdale College
Press.
• Feinberg, Joel. (2002) Reason and Responsibility,
Wadsworth.
• Hoppe, Hans-Herman. (1995) "Economic
Science and The Austrian Method," Mises.org.
• Huemer, Michael. (2001) "Is Benevolent Egoism Coherent?"
Unpublished manuscript.
• Kelley, David. (2000) The Contested Legacy of Ayn Rand, New
Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.
• Lachman, Ludwig M. (1997) "The Significance of the Austrian School
of Economics in the History of Ideas," in The Austrian Reader,
ed. Richard M. Ebeling, Hillsdale, MI: Hillsdale College Press.
• Menger, Carl. (1981) The Principles of Economics. New York
: New York University Press.
• Merrill, Ronald E. (1991) The Ideas of Ayn Rand, LaSalle,
IL: Open Court.
• Mises, Ludwig von (1963) Human Action, San Francisco: Fox &
Wilkes.
• Mises, Ludwig von. (1997) Liberalism: The Classical Tradition.
New York: The Foundation for Economic Education.
• Rand, Ayn. (1957) Atlas Shrugged, New York: Signet
• Rand, Ayn. (1961) For the New Intellectual, New York:
Signet
• Rand, Ayn. (1967) Capitalism: the Unknown Ideal, New York:
Signet
• Rand, Ayn. (1964) "The Objectivist Ethics;" in The Virtue of
Selfishness, New York: Signet
• Rand, Ayn. (1989) "Introducing Objectivism," in The Voice of
Reason, U.S.A.: Penguin Books
• Reisman, George. (1996) Capitalism: A Treatise on Economics,
Chicago: Jameson Books.
• Rothbard, Murray N. (1997) "Excerpts from Individualism and the
Philosophy of the Social Sciences," in The Austrian Reader,
ed. Richard M. Ebeling, Hillsdale, MI: Hillsdale College Press.
• Rothbard, Murray N. (1972) "The Sociology of the Ayn Rand Cult,"
www.lewrockwell.com.
• Younkins, Edward W. "Austrian
Economics Can Be Compatible with Objectivist Ethics,"
www.quebecoislibre.org.
• Younkins, Edward W. (2004a) "Can
the Ideas of Mises and Rand Be Reconciled?" www.solohq.com.
• Younkins, Edward W. (2004b) "Murray
Rothbard's Randian Austrianism," www.solohq.com. |
Heidi C. Morris is currently a junior at Hillsdale College
(Michigan), majoring in Economics and minoring in Biology.