It
is widely acknowledged that North American academia regularly lapses into
anti capitalism and naïve faith in government intervention. It should
therefore come as no surprise that the education lobby in Quebec has since
the 1960s been sharing this core philosophy of politicizing everything.
While doing so, the Quebec intellectual and political establishment has
driven out most other intellectual impulses. No cracks are yet visible in
the "liberal" edifice. For that the culture keepers feel morally and
intellectually superior.
What is
less expected is that explicit censorship should be openly practised in a
university department. As professors in the Law Faculty of Université
Laval, the two of us have recently been the victims of such ostracism. As
consigned on paper in the minutes of a meeting of the Law Faculty
professors, our offence has consisted in writing on and encouraging such
"subversive" ideas as "state non-interventionism" and "free markets."
Being a senior fellow at the Fraser Institute did not help one of us.
Indignant faculty members pressed the department to show more caution in
hiring lecturers. What disturbed us most was that teaching unconventional
ideas should be less than taken for granted in a university, that it
should be viewed as dangerous and extremist by the bien pensants in
place, that it should not even be part of "minority rights" so fashionable
in those circles. Diversity in race, ethnicity and sexual preference is
extolled but not in thought. From our angle, this only serves to show that
the dominant leftist doctrine is what is extremist in our society.
The principle of freedom of thought was evoked by one member of
the assembly and the danger of promoting a faculty ideology was raised by
another. On the other hand, this witch hunt went on in a formal meeting of
the Law Faculty. While not officially endorsing this form of censorship,
neither the Law Faculty nor the University deemed it appropriate to
officially dissociate from this shameful position, even though the case
was widely reported in a Quebec City daily (Michel Hébert, "Parfum de
censure à l'Université Laval," Le Journal de Québec, November 13,
2004) as well as discussed in radio talk shows.
Note that the pseudo trial instituted against two of us did not
question our scientific credentials, nor did it produce any incriminating
evidence from the actual content of our course. The indictment solely
relied on assumed moral and ideological persuasion. Because of the
political implications of the case, more objective readers may be curious
to learn what so deeply divides us from our accusers.
While based on accepted methodological rules, our teaching
subject and content are in a real sense not conventional in Quebec human
sciences departments. They are arguably controversial in the society at
large. One explicit assumption of the intellectual debate states that,
once unleashed, the electoral process automatically seeks and realizes the
common good. In holding this naïve concept of the state, Quebec academics
do not fundamentally differ from social philosophers around the world.
Most modern moralisers adhere to a view of the state as the embodiment of
some common will, as the instrument of altruistic endeavours, as the
promoter of the noblest causes, as the guarantor of virtue in the
citizenry.
We argue differently. To believe that the political apparatus can serve as
the premier and ultimate expression of the popular will constitutes the
"fatal conceit" of 20th Century social thinking. As amply shown by
economists in the public choice tradition, our analysis argues that even
if it actively sought the common good, a government could not define a
social welfare function even in theory. To pursue such a lofty goal, the
state should possess a full knowledge of each and every individual
subjective preference in society. In a valid concept of social welfare,
there is no special value attached to a majority opinion, or to the
interests of any particular social grouping, be it composed of farmers,
members of the middle class, part of large families or unattached
individuals. In contrast with the rest of us, politicians and bureaucrats
should be immune to self-interest and greed and predisposed to adopt
strictly altruistic behaviour. In fact, under present less than
encompassing political rules, politicians respond to the preferences of
successive majorities or to the interests of narrow factions. Because they
receive their mandate for a few short years, immediate popular
gratification is the preferred political option. Consumption at the
expense of saving and investment prevails.
Another dogma in the social democratic religion holds that "free
goods" at the point of consumption is the unquestionable symbol of social
justice, the purest expression of our compassion, in clear contrast with
the rugged individualism of materialist Americans. As the indictment
pronounced by the socialist tradition against the capitalist system has
it, the wealth-creating virtues of free markets solely rest on unfettered
selfish and materialistic instincts. Even organized churches hit upon this
straw man.
Our counter attack to this superficial analysis goes broadly as
follows. Far from embodying the noble ideal of sharing, the apparent
predilection for the state monopoly in education and health care expresses
the concern of a majority to access services with other people's money. In
a similar vein, law students are reminded that confiscating other people's
wealth in the private sphere is called stealing. When carried out
collectively by state coercion, it becomes income redistribution or social
justice. Charity is the product of an honourable instinct; stealing,
legally or illegally, remains morally despicable, a necessary evil in a
free society.
We also reflect before our law student audience on how in little
more than a generation, the concept of social justice and collective
rights have driven out individual rights as the organizing principle of
society. The notion of collective rights implemented by state action have
now supplanted property rights for the benefit of all sorts of minorities,
including racial or ethnic groups, women in the labour force, homosexuals
and cultural communities. Forced equality of results, not their quality or
diversity, is the defining concern of egalitarians.
We argue by contrast that opposing collective rights to
individual rights is repellent to free minds. In direct contrast with
collective rights, a right is the freedom to escape from state power.
Suggesting a trade-off between social justice and simple justice is to
legitimise state action without the consent of one contracting party; it
is to subscribe to the violation of property rights. History teaches that
this perversion feeds antagonisms and hampers wealth creation.
This contrast between the two protagonist schools in the culture
war brings out the century-old opposing views on the place of government
in society and its relation with individuals. As was the case throughout
the history of industrial countries, the defining distinction between
these two philosophies is the primacy accorded to equality on the one hand
as opposed to liberty on the other. Collectivists of all stripes prescribe
coercive redistribution in the service of egalitarianism. Their idealized
outcome? A population relying on the state to alleviate life fears: old
age, illness, unemployment and reversals of fortune. Equal dependence of
all on socialized risk protection has undermined self-reliance and
self-esteem while encouraging dependency, poverty and relative decline.
Our line of analysis argues that inequality of results is an
expression of freedom and the necessary concomitant of wealth creation. In
a word, the welfare state has been a failure and it has done substantial
damage to society and economy. Institutionally, political calculus
determines the options of these two doctrinal schools. Groups who live by
the state tend to support its growth and to vehemently oppose arrangements
favourable to freedom of choice and private initiatives: school vouchers,
health and retirement accounts and tax cuts. Winning this battle of ideas
would be ample reward for us. However, simply being able to exercise our
right to openly discuss the issues in a university environment without
being the subject of institutionally-condoned hostility remains, for the
time being, a battle that we are still fighting.
Jean-Luc Migué
is a Senior Fellow at the Fraser Institute. Réjean Breton is a
Professor at the Law Faculty of the Université Laval.
(Article originally posted in
Le Québécois Libre,
Issue 150, January 15, 2005. This article is reprinted with
permission from the authors.) |
Order Mr.
Stolyarov's newest science fiction novel, Eden against the Colossus,
in eBook form, here.
You only pay $10.00, with no shipping and handling fees.
Give feedback on
this work at TRA's forum, which you can access at
http://rationalarg.proboards24.com.
Advertise your business or product permanently
on TRA for a mere $1 donation to a worthy endeavor to combat human aging.
Click
here to learn more.
Help bring about the cure for human aging
within our lifetimes. Learn how you can help through the
Chicago Methuselah Foundation Fund.
Visit The Rational
Argumentator's new
Online Store.
Visit TRA's Yahoo! Group, a means of
notification and communication for our subscribers. You can find it at
http://groups.yahoo.com/group/rationalargumentator.
You can sign up by sending an e-mail to
rationalargumentator-subscribe@yahoogroups.com.
Click here to return to the Issue XXX index.
Visit
TRA's Master Index, a convenient way of navigating throughout the issues
of the magazine. Click
here. |