I had established the foundations of philosophically verifiable
etiquette in the
Public-Private Ethical Distinction, which is explicated in an
essay of the same name. Etiquette is thoroughly grounded in
rational egoism; it is a scientific classification of the
instances and categories of action which are best for an
individual to keep solely to himself or within a self-defined
delimited circle of pertinent associates and which it is to his
advantage to seek the cooperation and contribution of others
toward. That former treatise had addressed with considerable
specificity the alternative of withholding or disclosing and how
profoundly it permeates all public discussions and endeavors. Yet
another crucial part of etiquette as we encounter it (which is not
to presume, at least thus far, that this is in concord with
objective etiquette—that much remains to be reasoned toward)
consists of expressions and gestures of politeness,
including greetings and farewells, manners for all sorts of
occasions: dining, gameplay, discourse, as well as the ubiquitous
expectation of hospitality from a host.
Politeness, the undertaking of a
positive behavior toward another party deemed mutually proper and
pleasant by both, can be traced to an essential component of
rational human interaction: value-trading. The rational
egoist seeks some form of value, be it material or intellectual,
tangible or ideological, particular or underlying, which he can at
some later instant(s) employ for the advancement of his survival
and prosperity. In the realm of material skills and commodities,
as well as in that of insights, systems, feedback, and
constructive criticism, many of these values, optimal for the
particular selfish aims of the pursuing individual, are possessed
by others; they are, in other words, the property of other
individuals. Those individuals' right to gain, keep, and
dispose of that property prevents the agent of our deliberation
from justifiably confiscating their possessions without their
consent. In order to receive these values, the agent must present
certain values of his own, in accordance with the
material/intellectual context of the given exchange. He must also
act in a manner that demonstrates his approbation of the
attributes of his partner in trade (the attributes which he seeks
to gain) and emphasizes his peaceful intentions in attempting to
accomplish the transaction's objective. Hence, all exchanges of
values should be accompanied by bilateral valuation, which
is accomplished via politeness.
An expression of greetings
indicates the willingness to undertake a transaction of some sort,
a universal signal (with plenty of rich stylistic variations) that
directs the other party's attention toward the agent and at the
same time demonstrates the friendly, appreciative conduct that
befits a peaceful trader. A statement of farewell confirms that
the exchange or series thereof has been concluded (with whatever
result) and that each party can attend to affairs not requiring
mutual presence or interaction without demonstrating a
semi-oblivious contempt for the other, which latter manner is
quite a hindrance to the successful outcome of any present or
future cooperation. As for those instances where a short
salutation is uttered to a friend or acquaintance in passing him
by, but no other words are intended to follow, either due to a
shortage of time or an abundance of other affairs, this is an
expression of an intent to transact in the future, all the
meantime maintaining cognizance and valuation of the other party.
Neither philosophers nor laymen can permit themselves to think in
stasis, only of the immediately accessible moment and desire.
Every rational man plans ahead in his endeavors and
associations alike, and so must thinkers in their
interpretations of rational conduct. This planning need not be
precise or even definite, but it does contain an underlying
recognition that "this person and his values will be of use to me
sometime, given the nature of the goals that I seek to
accomplish." And all the meantime, interest will accumulate in the
individual's intellectual deposit into that particular trader
relationship.
In the associations of close
friends, who offer each other the means toward intellectual
amelioration, it is often a proper expression of politeness to
inquire of the most recent condition of one's internal state,
using such phrases as "How are you?" However, in order to qualify
as an objective exchange of values, this question must be
sincere and in preparation for a particular,
non-superficial reply. In the present state of
politically-correct culture, it has been posed all too often with
the expectation of a brisk "Fine, thank you," which has no
relation to the actual condition of the responding individual, who
may well be utterly miserable. The root of this crisis in
etiquette is the neglect of the public-private ethical
distinction; one's inner mental state, with its constant dynamic
of creation, its saturation with the yet developing, incomplete,
not yet suited for public presentation, is best kept private; a
close friend or a professional psychologist, under conditions of
non-disclosure, can best assist an individual in remedying
confusions, removing stumbling blocks, or simply completing a
thought process at a swifter pace, due to those persons' extensive
acquaintance with the properties of that individual's mind. Hence
the question "How are you?" is quite appropriate when posed by one
of them. However, when uttered by semi-acquaintances, it loses the
moral sanction. The semi-acquaintances are not interested in the
individual's mental state, which they rightly should not be; they
are not fit to ameliorate it. But, in the hypocritical or outright
ignorant attempt to seem closer in relationship to that man than
is their objective condition, they yet feign that interest in a
gross violation of a key Objectivist precept, Honesty. Though
there are in fact times when every individual is "fine" or even
"great" in his internal functions, and does not require the
assistance of others, the respondent cannot, due to the very
nature of the human mind, be in such a state 100 percent of the
time he so claims in such exchanges of mock courtesy. Thus,
socially acceptable "etiquette" forces him to subvert Objective
Etiquette and outright lie; if he refuses and comments on the
inappropriateness of the inquiry in the given context, it is he
who is accused of being impolite! This devious double bind of
mindless irrationality can only be cleansed by means of a cultural
injection of the recognition of the objectivity and egoistic
foundations of etiquette.
Other verbal exchanges of
politeness are perhaps simpler to trace to their logical roots. To
say "I would like" or "please" (which is quite efficient shorthand
for both "It would please me to…" and "Do this if it pleases
you…") is an indication of one's desire to peacefully gain a
value, with one's reciprocal payment either forthcoming or already
presented. To thank an individual for his services is an
indication that a value was received and that the exchange has
accomplished a multifaceted satisfaction (material and
intellectual); this grants the other party the fulfillment of the
expectation of bilateral intellectual pleasantness as well as the
hope that further value-trading of this sort shall come in the
future. To apologize for an accidental transgression or intrusion
on another's material or intellectual property is to declare that
one's intent was not forceful/confiscatory, that one regrets the
action and is prepared to remedy the damage in any manner desired
by the injured party (which sometimes requires no response, if
that latter party sees it optimal to correct the harm without
assistance).
In the company of others, another
category subsumed by politeness is that of manners, which
are to conduct what the aforementioned expressions are to
language. Manners are those unspoken actions which are
demonstrative of politeness. When one dines in anyone else's
company, one is expected to remain tidy and constantly monitor the
stainlessness of one's flesh and attire. This is because, to quote
from "The
Public-Private Ethical Distinction," " to shield himself from
public knowledge of physical imperfections and occasional
infestations with dirt or wear, the tactful man will practice
proper hygiene without discussing it; he will adhere to
standards of cleanliness and order both in his body and clothing;
he will not deliberately brandish wounds, stains, shreds,
or haphazard hairdos." To slobber over one's plate or shove chunks
into one's mouth or to tolerate any accidental breach of the
integrity of one's body or clothing is to flaunt bodily
imperfections in public, where they, as has already been proved,
do not belong. It violates not only the purpose of food (which is
to be eaten, not used as coloring in the style of Jackson Pollock)
but the purpose of a dinner with others, which is to share
desirably public values, such as completed ideas (and, of course,
completed food!).
It is to be noted that
cleanliness and auditory propriety (which is indicative of proper
bodily function) in table manners are the only philosophically
objective criteria as concerns etiquette. The remainder (such
as whether to hold one's knife and fork in one hand consistently
or to cumbersomely alternate, as many Americans do, or whether to
place one's napkin under one's lap or tuck it into one's collar)
is contextual and utility-based. Whichever method achieves the
maximum efficiency, as concerns the cleanliness, pleasure, and
unhindered nature of the consumption, under the particular
circumstances, is the one that should be used. Note that this
"applied logic" (as all non-dialectic, non-subjective, logical
logic) is culturally independent, and does not consider any
traditional formalities that have developed in regard to dining
etiquette in any given society, the United States included.
Manners also feature
significantly in the playing of games, be it in the imperative to
obey game rules or to demonstrate courtesy toward one's
co-players. A game is a simulation of an aspect of reality or of
the imagination whose general dynamic characterizes a larger world
dominated by the trader principle. The players compete with each
other in order to gain the most desirable result, or even to
defeat other players within the parameters of the game,
just as businesses and entrepreneurs seek to outcompete each other
and, in certain cases, drive their competitors out of their field.
Yet this rivalry is always civil and delimited; no
side is permitted to initiate physical force against the other.
Thus, one's success or failure is founded purely on the skill and
intellect in the acquisition of any advantageous attribute, be it
an economic resource, a game point, or a checkmate. The loser of
the game, like the one of the business competition, is harmed only
within the context of the game or the competition; he fails to
gain the object of his undertaking. Yet, in a game, this object is
far less substantial in terms of considerations relevant to
survival and prosperity than it is in the economy. Hence, while a
businessman who had driven his firm into bankruptcy may rightly be
called incompetent, the loser of a game has merely been "bested."
To stress his defeat in a manner that pesters him is to state that
the objective of the game possesses greater import for the agent
individual than interaction and value trading with his accomplice
in gameplay and thus to commit a gross moral infraction upon the
integrity of the relationship. After all, a game is undertaken by
a multiplicity of persons only because each has an egoistic
interest in mind; to develop a given skill by means of the very
undertaking of the game; chess sharpens the reasoning and
anticipation of both the winner and loser, Monopoly teaches both
certain elementary (though imperfect) theories and concepts of
business, and soccer develops the endurance and aim of all who
ever contact the ball. This greater intent should always be kept
in mind when a player combats the urge to shout an obscenity or to
taunt an opponent. And it should be applied in full, when, at the
enterprise's conclusion, the opponents part with a solemn,
dignified "Good game."
Of course, each participant
undertakes a game with the expectation of something particular
and something definite. A game being a simulation of a
rational reality, rules and their obedience are of the utmost
import. A bishop cannot suddenly shift its movement pattern to
that of a knight; a helicopter cannot arbitrarily be introduced
into a basketball court to lift the ball and drop it into the
hoop. Nor can a game precept be violated simply because its
dynamic produces a result which is counter a given player's
intentions. Of course, if the unanimous body of the game
participants resolves to alter the rules in such a manner as to
better fulfill each member's interests, then they are free to play
this modified version, or to create an entirely new game of their
own, without breaching proper etiquette. After all, the rational
purpose of a particular game is to enhance the skills of the
participants, not to follow the instructions on the game box
to the letter.
Discourse, an undertaking
inevitably involving a multitude of persons, is, too, thoroughly
guided by objective manners. Discussion as such, be it verbal,
written, printed, or electronic, is a prime example of
intellectual value trading; one person's ideas are exchanged for
those of the other. Each side gains values, and—which is most
attractive about this form of trading—does not lose the values
that it presents, excepting one, time. To partake in a
discussion implies that one's valuation of one's partner(s) and
his/their ideas is prioritized over all other accessible
undertakings, so that one is willing to spend one's present time
in the acquisition of such pertinent intellectual commodities. As
this valuation is present, in a world of honest traders, it must
be expressed by means of tactful, courteous dialogue, which takes
care not to spew insulting phrases onto the person uttering
the ideas, even if the ideas themselves are false. Denunciation of
false ideas is permissible and even necessary at times; this is a
case of constructive criticism, encountering which should be an
expectation for anyone who discloses his thought to another
person. Likewise, so is express disapprobation of questionable
actions; this is always undertaken with the underlying presumption
that the erring individual is capable of volitional amelioration,
that he is amenable to reason, and that the agent of the critique
is willing to offer him valuable suggestions for improvement.
However, at no time, if the discourse is intended to continue, is
it permissible to sincerely state to the other, "You are a foul
person." Whereas this remark may be deserved by a brute, vulgar,
savage enemy, a partner in consensual discourse cannot be a foe by
definition; he, too, non-forcefully seeks some value for himself
from the interaction. If the content of his suggestions seems
repugnant or intended to doom the other individual to failure;
then that other can thoroughly demolish them and expose
their probable consequences, while still refraining from insults
and preparing to utter a courteous farewell at the conclusion of
the exchange.
This does not, however, imply
that all discourse must proceed in a timid, even tone of voice.
Passionate emphasis, variation, and even outright booming
proclamation are permissible, so long as they are kept within the
bounds of the subject matter discussed and are not aimed against
the other person(s). Screaming to insult and raising one's voice
to reinforce a principle are a world apart; I would even venture
to contend that they are diametrical opposites. The former
destroys a value exchange by means of its impropriety, the latter
seeks to amplify the exchange by employing the entire arsenal of
persuasive tools legitimately available to the individual. The
former is an example of unrefined savagery, the latter—a signal of
oratorical finesse.
Lastly, in the realm of public
manners, whenever a party coordinates a gathering for any purpose,
it, as the host, is expected to provide a contextually adequate
level of comfort, aesthetic satisfaction, and material necessities
and introduce them into the vicinity of the guests that partake in
the occasion. The host usually being the initiator of the
gathering, it is his prerogative to offer additional values to his
companions so that they would consider their time best spent and
their own material/intellectual commodities presented to amplest
selfish gain. He is not morally obliged to bring about any state
of luxury, though he should rightly be thanked if he does. It is,
however, imperative, for him to assure his guests' freedom from
unease. They must not remain hungry, be shoved into a dank
cellar, or experience any other facet of deprivation, if they had
chosen to yield their time in search for some positive,
constructive gain. Depending on the duration and other contextual
circumstances of the occasion, the host must ensure that his
guests are endowed with a standard of living that is at least the
minimum of their expectation of a life proper to a human being. He
seeks to gain values from the guests, but in the process he must
ensure that they are not drained of theirs.
By now, the fact that rational
egoism is the only legitimate foundation for mutual politeness
should be evident; the altruist has no need for manners or
courtesy. If his purpose is to pander to others' whims, he will do
so as a selfless drone, uncaring of whether he is treated like a
beneficent servant at best, or a lowly slave at worst. And no
recipient of values permeated by the philosophy of altruism will
respond with any manner of tact; he has been taught that values
must be surrendered without expectation of reward, and, in the
most consistent instances of altruism, without expectation of even
gratitude. And if, according to this conception, it is unnecessary
to express, why should he undertake the effort to do so? The
philosophy of sacrifice will also inevitably bring about
relationships other than that which exists between traders. When
men are not consensual value-exchangers, they become inevitably
split into two categories, the slaves and the dependents, the
former being the coerced agents of selfless surrender, the latter
being its thankless beneficiaries, each inextricably linked to the
other by a web of suffering and lack, of streams of tears and
rivers of blood. What honest civility can possibly exist in a
world guided by such a philosophy?
The rational man will practice
proper etiquette because he is dependent on no one else for
the determination of his goals and pursuits. He will respect
others because he loves himself and constantly endeavors
toward selfish gain. He will deem all property rights sacred
because his is the most sacred property of all, the autonomy and
functionality of his rational mind.
G. Stolyarov II is a science fiction
novelist, independent philosophical essayist, poet, amateur
mathematician and composer, contributor to Enter Stage Right and
SoloHQ, writer for Objective Medicine, and Editor-in-Chief of The
Rational Argumentator. He can be contacted at
gennadystolyarovii@yahoo.com.
|