Duty
(Drawn
from Lawrence Hinman, Ethics: A
Pluralistic Approach to Moral Theory (2nd ed.), pp. 208-238, and
Mr. Hinman’s website at http://ethics.acusd.edu)
- Immanuel Kant (1742-1804) is the
foremost philosopher of Duty-based Ethics.
- “Duty” is defined as:
·
doing what any rational agent would do (such as
throwing a life preserver or a rope to a drowning child)
·
fulfilling one’s professional role (as a doctor has a
duty to care for the sick, even if the patient cannot pay right away)
·
fulfilling a social role (such as a parent’s obligation
to care for their children).
- Two visions of Kant’s vision have
emerged.
- The Adolf Eichmann model, where
duty is “just following orders” without regard for consequences.
·
Eichmann was a famous Nazi responsible for carrying out
many of Hitler’s extermination orders. At his trial, Eichmann said in his
defense that he was not personally responsible, as he was following orders
given to him by his supervisors.
·
Here “duty” is seen as external and imposed by
others.
·
Note that the Eichmann error is so easy to make that
the U.S. Armed Forces has addressed this issue explicitly!! Service personnel
have a duty to disobey “illegal orders” regardless of personal cost.
- Kant’s real intention was to
see duty as internal, something that we impose upon ourselves.
- Returning to the doctor example:
people who choose to become physicians do so knowing full well that they
will incur the duty to care for people, some of whom cannot pay.
- Kant’s major achievement was clearly
stating the notion of CATAGORICAL IMERITIVES. These are
unconditional commands that are binding to all people at all times.
- The underlying conviction is that what
is fair for one is fair for one must be fair for all: one should “always
act in such a way that the maxim of your action can be willed as a
universal law of humanity.”
- “Maxims,” by the way, are rules
or proverbs used to guide actions. They are stated as imperatives such as
“Do unto others as you would have them do unto you” or “Never do something
in private that you would not also do in public.”
- Another of Kant’s categorical
imperatives was focused on respect: “Always treat humanity, whether in
yourself or in other people, as an end in itself and never as a mere
means.”
·
Let’s take the example of “Harold,” an annoying nerdy
guy just starting out at college (p. 224). His lack of social skills result in
his having only a few friends. During his second year, however, his father
gives him a nice sports car. Also, his sister—who happens to be
beautiful—enrolls at a nearby school. Suddenly Harold becomes much more
popular, and is often invited to parties—as long as he brings his sister, too!
·
In all likelihood, many of Harold’s new “friends” are
using him as a means to achieve their own ends—using him to drive them around
and/or to meet his sister.
- Kant did allow exceptions to rules, as
long as the exceptions could be universalized. One example: the speeding
car. A friend goes into labor. Are you justified in speeding to get them
to a hospital? Kant would say “yes,” so long as you do not pose a threat
to others with your speeding. This exception can be universalized, and
makes sense to most rational people.
- Kant wanted to get away from using
emotions as motivators to ethical action. He saw them as unreliable,
passive, and too subject to whim and passing fashion.
- It requires persons to fulfill their
duty, regardless of personal consequences to themselves. Hinman uses the
example of the politician Edmund Ross, who was called to choose between
personal feeling and advancement or doing the right thing. Ross chose the
right thing, although it ended his political career (p. 208-210).
- Kant tended to think that actions were
morally admirable only if they were done without regard to feeling or
emotion. For example, if I give money to homeless person because I feel
bad for them, this lacks moral merit: I get something out of my donation
because I feel good helping somebody else. It would have more merit if I
really had not desire to help, but did so anyway because it was simply the
right thing to do.
- This has led some to claim that Kant
wanted people to do only the minimum to fulfill their duties, rather than
doing things for heart-felt reasons.
- It also can make people feel
mistrustful of their feelings, as Kant felt that they were an unreliable
guide.
- Finally, there is the Eichmann
problem. This is the notion that a person should just follow orders of
superiors, regardless of outcome.
- We have already shown why the Eichmann
view of duty is incorrect. However, it is probably true that Kant was
overly mistrustful of human emotions—sometimes (but not always) feelings
and inclinations do point us in the correct direction, and we may enjoy
doing our duties.
- The power of Kant’s vision was his
recognition that morality must be fair and evenhanded.
- It also provides a sort of moral
safety that can help us to avoid sliding down the slippery slope to
pure utilitarianism without regard for individuals.
- Finally, it is probably
under-recognized that Kant’s ethics are good for the individual as well—individuals
should not mistreat themselves (through working themselves to death,
or even undertaking weird fad diets) any more than they would impose these
things upon others.