BOOK V
GENERAL RELATIONS OF DEMAND, SUPPLY AND VALUE
CHAPTER 1
INTRODUCTORY. ON MARKETS
1. A business firm grows and attains great strength, and afterwards perhaps stagnates and decays; and at the turning point there is a balancing or equilibrium of the forces of life and decay: the latter part of Book IV has been chiefly occupied with such balancing of forces in the life and decay of a people, or of a method of industry or trading. And as we reach to the higher stages of our work, we shall need ever more and more to think of economic forces as resembling those which make a young man grow in strength, till he reaches his prime; after which he gradually becomes stiff and inactive, till at last he
sinks to make room for other and more vigorous life. But to prepare the way for this advanced study we want first to look at a simpler balancing of forces which corresponds rather to the mechanical equilibrium of a stone hanging by an elastic string, or of a number of balls resting against one another in a basin.
We have now to examine the general relations of demand and supply; especially
those which are connected with that adjustment of price, by which they are
maintained in "equilibrium." This term is in common use and may be used for the
present without special explanation. But there are many difficulties connected
with it, which can only be handled gradually: and indeed they will occupy our
attention during a great part of this Book.
Illustrations will be taken now from one class of economic problems and now from
another, but the main course of the reasoning will be kept free from assumptions
which specially belong to any particular class.
Thus it is not descriptive, nor does it deal constructively with real problems.
But it sets out the theoretical backbone of our knowledge of the causes which
govern value, and thus prepares the way for the construction which is to begin
in the following Book. It aims not so much at the attainment of knowledge, as at
the power to obtain and arrange knowledge with regard to two opposing sets of
forces, those which impel man to economic efforts and sacrifices, and those
which hold him back.
We must begin with a short and provisional account of markets: for that is
needed to give precision to the ideas in this and the following Books. But the
organization of markets is intimately connected both as cause and effect with
money, credit, and foreign trade; a full study of it must therefore be deferred
to a later volume, where it will be taken in connection with commercial and
industrial fluctuations, and with combinations of producers and of merchants, of
employers and employed.
2. When demand and supply are spoken of in relation to one another, it is of
course necessary that the markets to which they refer should be the same. As
Cournot says, "Economists understand by the term Market, not any particular
market place in which things are bought and sold, but the whole of any region in
which buyers and sellers are in such free intercourse with one another that the
prices of the same goods tend to equality easily and quickly."(1*) Or again as
Jevons says: -- "Originally a market was a public place in a town where
provisions and other objects were exposed for sale; but the word has been
generalized, so as to mean any body of persons who are in intimate business
relations and carry on extensive transactions in any commodity. A great city may
contain as many markets as there are important branches of trade, and these
markets may or may not be localized. The central point of a market is the public
exchange, mart or auction rooms, where the traders agree to meet and transact
business. In London the Stock Market, the Corn Market, the Coal Market, the
Sugar Market, and many others are distinctly localized; in Manchester the Cotton
Market, the Cotton Waste Market, and others. But this distinction of locality is
not necessary. The traders may be spread over a whole town, or region of
country, and vet make a market, if they are, by means of fairs, meetings,
published price lists, the post-office or otherwise, in close communication with
each other."(2*)
Thus the more nearly perfect a market is, the stronger is the tendency for the
same price to be paid for the same thing at the same time in all parts of the
market: but of course if the market is large, allowance must be made for the
expense of delivering the goods to different purchasers; each of whom must be
supposed to pay in addition to the market price a special charge on account of
delivery.(3*)
3. In applying economic reasonings in practice it is often difficult to
ascertain how far the movements of supply and demand in any one place are
influenced by those in another. It is clear that the general tendency of the
telegraph, the printing-press and steam traffic is to extend the area over which
such influences act and to increase their force. The whole Western World may, in
a sense, be regarded as one market for many kinds of stock exchange securities,
for the more valuable metals, and to a less extent for wool and cotton and even
wheat; proper allowance being made for expenses of transport, in which may be
included taxes levied by any customs houses through which the goods have to
pass. For in all these cases the expenses of transport, including customs
duties, are not sufficient to prevent buyers from all parts of the Western World
from competing with one another for the same supplies.
There are many special causes which may widen or narrow the market of any
particular commodity: but nearly all those things for which there is a very wide
market are in universal demand, and capable of being easily and exactly
described. Thus for instance cotton, wheat, and iron satisfy wants that are
urgent and nearly universal. They can be easily described, so that they can be
bought and sold by persons at a distance from one another and at a distance also
from the commodities. If necessary, samples can be taken of them which are truly
representative: and they can even be "graded," as is the actual practice with
regard to grain in America, by an independent authority; so that the purchaser
may be secure that what he buys will come up to a given standard, though he has
never seen a sample of the goods which he is buying and perhaps would not be
able himself to form an opinion on it if he did.(4*)
Commodities for which there is a very wide market must also be such as will bear
a long carriage: they must be somewhat durable, and their value must be
considerable in proportion to their bulk. A thing which is so bulky that its
price is necessarily raised very much when it is sold far away from the place in
which it is produced, must as a rule have a narrow market. The market for common
bricks for instance is practically confined to the near neighbourhood of the
kilns in which they are made: they can scarcely ever bear a long carriage by
land to a district which has any kilns of its own. But bricks of certain
exceptional kinds have markets extending over a great part of England.
4. Let us then consider more closely the markets for things which satisfy in an
exceptional way these conditions of being in general demand, cognizable and
portable. They are, as we have said, stock exchange securities and the more
valuable metals.
Any one share or bond of a public company, or any bond of a government is of
exactly the same value as any other of the same issue: it can make no difference
to any purchaser which of the two he buys. Some securities, principally those of
comparatively small mining, shipping, and other companies, require local
knowledge, and are not very easily dealt in except on the stock exchanges of
provincial towns in their immediate neighbourhood. But the whole of England is
one market for the shares and bonds of a large English railway. In ordinary
times a dealer will sell, say, Midland Railway shares, even if he has not them
himself; because he knows they are always coming into the market, and he is sure
to be able to buy them.
But the strongest case of all is that of securities which are called
"international," because they are in request in every part of the globe. They
are the bonds of the chief governments, and of very large public companies such
as those of the Suez Canal and the New York Central Railway. For bonds of this
class the telegraph keeps prices at almost exactly the same level in all the
stock exchanges of the world. If the price of one of them rises in New York or
in Paris, in London or in Berlin, the mere news of the rise tends to cause a
rise in other markets; and if for any reason the rise is delayed, that
particular class of bonds is likely soon to be offered for sale in the high
priced market under telegraphic orders from the other markets, while dealers in
the first market will be making telegraphic purchases in other markets. These
sales on the one hand, and purchases on the other, strengthen the tendency which
the price has to seek the same level everywhere; and unless some of the markets
are in an abnormal condition, the tendency soon becomes irresistible.
On the stock exchange also a dealer can generally make sure of selling at nearly
the same price as that at which he buys; and he is often willing to buy first
class stocks at a half, or a quarter, or an eighth, or in some cases even a
sixteenth per cent less than he offers in the same breath to sell them at. If
there are two securities equally good, but one of them belongs to a large issue
of bonds, and the other to a small issue by the same government, so that the
first is constantly coming on the market, and the latter but seldom, then the
dealers will on this account alone require a larger margin between their selling
price and their buying price in the latter case than in the former.(5*) This
illustrates well the great law, that the larger the market for a commodity the
smaller generally are the fluctuations in its price, and the lower is the
percentage on the turnover which dealers charge for doing business in it.
Stock exchanges then are the pattern on which markets have been, and are being
formed for dealing in many kinds of produce which can be easily and exactly
described, are portable and in general demand. The material commodities however
which possess these qualities in the highest degree are gold and silver. For
that very reason they have been chosen by common consent for use as money, to
represent the value of other things: the world market for them is most highly
organized, and will be found to offer many subtle illustrations of the actions
of the laws which we are now discussing.
5. At the opposite extremity to international stock exchange securities and the
more valuable metals are, firstly, things which must be made to order to suit
particular individuals, such as well-fitting clothes; and, secondly, perishable
and bulky goods, such as fresh vegetables, which can seldom be profitably
carried long distances. The first can scarcely be said to have a wholesale
market at all; the conditions by which their price is determined are those of
retail buying and selling, and the study of them may be postponed.(6*)
There are indeed wholesale markets for the second class, but they are confined
within narrow boundaries; we may find our typical instance in the sale of the
commoner kinds of vegetables in a country town. The market-gardeners in the
neighbourhood have probably to arrange for the sale of their vegetables to the
townspeople with but little external interference on either side. There may be
some check to extreme prices by the power on the one side of selling, and on the
other of buying elsewhere; but under ordinary circumstances the check is
inoperative, and it may happen that the dealers in such a case are able to
combine, and thus fix an artificial monopoly price; that is, a price determined
with little direct reference to cost of production, but chiefly by a
consideration of what the market will bear.
On the other hand, it may happen that some of the market-gardeners are almost
equally near a second country town, and send their vegetables now to one and now
to the other; and some people who occasionally buy in the first town may have
equally good access to the second. The least variation in price will lead them
to prefer the better market; and thus make the bargainings in the two towns to
some extent mutually dependent. It may happen that this second town is in close
communication with London or some other central market, so that its prices are
controlled by the prices in the central market; and in that case prices in our
first town also must move to a considerable extent in harmony with them. As news
passes from mouth to mouth till a rumour spreads far away from its forgotten
sources, so even the most secluded market is liable to be influenced by changes
of which those in the market have no direct cognizance, changes that have had
their origin far away and have spread gradually from market to market.
Thus at the one extreme are world markets in which competition acts directly
from all parts of the globe; and at the other those secluded markets in which
all direct competition from afar is shut out, though indirect and transmitted
competition may make itself felt even in these; and about midway between these
extremes lie the great majority of the markets which the economist and the
business man have to study.
6. Again, markets vary with regard to the period of time which is allowed to the
forces of demand and supply to bring themselves into equilibrium with one
another, as well as with regard to the area over which they extend. And this
element of Time requires more careful attention just now than does that of
Space. For the nature of the equilibrium itself, and that of the causes by which
it is determined, depend on the length of the period over which the market is
taken to extend. We shall find that if the period is short, the supply is
limited to the stores which happen to be at hand: if the period is longer, the
supply will be influenced, more or less, by the cost of producing the commodity
in question; and if the period is very long, this cost will in its turn be
influenced, more or less, by the cost of producing the labour and the material
things required for producing the commodity. These three classes of course merge
into one another by imperceptible degrees. We will begin with the first class;
and consider in the next chapter those temporary equilibria of demand and
supply, in which "supply" means in effect merely the stock available at the time
for sale in the market; so that it cannot be directly influenced by the cost of
production.
NOTES:
1. Recherches sur les Principes Mathématiques de la Théorie des Richesses, ch.
IV. See also above III, IV, section 7.
2. Theory of Political Economy, ch. IV.
3. Thus it is common to see the prices of bulky goods quoted as delivered "free
on board" (f.o.b.) any vessel in a certain port, each purchaser having to make
his own reckoning for bringing the goods home.
4. Thus the managers of a public or private "elevator," receive grain from a
farmer, divide it into different grades, and return to him certificates for as
many bushels of each grade as he has delivered. His grain is then mixed with
those of other farmers; his certificates are likely to change hands several
times before they reach a purchaser who demands that the grain shall be actually
delivered to him; and little or none of what that purchaser receives may have
come from the farm of the original recipient of the certificate.
5. In the case of shares of very small and little known companies, the
difference between the price at which a dealer is willing to buy and that at
which he will sell may amount to from five per cent. or more of the selling
value. If he buys, he may have to carry this security a long time before he
meets with any one who comes to take it from him, and meanwhile it may fall in
value: while if he undertakes to deliver a security which he has not himself got
and which does not come on the market every day, he may be unable to complete
his contract without much trouble and expense.
6. A man may not trouble himself much about small retail purchases: he may give
half-a-crown for a packet of paper in one shop which he could have got for two
shillings in another. But it is otherwise with wholesale prices. A manufacturer
cannot sell a ream of paper for six shillings while his neighbour is selling it
at five. For those whose business it is to deal in paper know almost exactly the
lowest price at which it can be bought, and will not pay more than this. The
manufacturer has to sell at about the market price, that is at about the price
at which other manufacturers are selling at the same time.
CHAPTER 2
TEMPORARY EQUILIBRIUM OF DEMAND AND SUPPLY
1. The simplest case of balance or equilibrium between. desire and effort is
found when a person satisfies one of his wants by his own direct work. When a
boy picks blackberries for his own eating, the action of picking is probably
itself pleasurable for a while; and for some time longer the pleasure of eating
is more than enough to repay the trouble of picking. But after he has eaten a
good deal, the desire for more diminishes; while the task of picking begins to
cause weariness, which may indeed be a feeling of monotony rather than of
fatigue. Equilibrium is reached when at last his eagerness to play and his
disinclination for the work of picking counterbalance the desire for eating. The
satisfaction which he can get from picking fruit has arrived at its maximum: for
up to that time every fresh picking has added more to his pleasure than it has
taken away; and after that time any further picking would take away from his
pleasure more than it would add.(1*)
In a casual bargain that one person makes with another, as for instance when two
backwoodsmen barter a rifle for a canoe, there is seldom anything that can
properly be called an equilibrium of supply and demand: there is probably a
margin of satisfaction on either side; for probably the one would be willing to
give something besides the rifle for the canoe, if he could not get the canoe
otherwise; while the other would in case of necessity give something besides the
canoe for the rifle.
It is indeed possible that a true equilibrium may be arrived at under a system
of barter; but barter, though earlier in history than buying and selling, is in
some ways more intricate; and the simplest cases of a true equilibrium value are
found in the markets of a more advanced state of civilization.
We may put aside as of little practical importance a class of dealings which has
been much discussed. They relate to pictures by old masters, rare coins and
other things, which cannot be "graded" at all. The price at which each is sold,
will depend much on whether any rich persons with a fancy for it happen to be
present at its sale. If not, it will probably be bought by dealers who reckon on
being able to sell it at a profit; and the variations in the price for which the
same picture sells at successive auctions, great as they are, would be greater
still if it were not for the steadying influence of professional purchasers.
2. Let us then turn to the ordinary dealings of modern life; and take an
illustration from a corn-market in a country town, and let us assume for the
sake of simplicity that all the corn in the market is of the same quality. The
amount which each farmer or other seller offers for sale at any price is
governed by his own need for money in hand, and by his calculation of the
present and future conditions of the market with which he is connected. There
are some prices which no seller would accept, some which no one would refuse.
There are other intermediate prices which would be accepted for larger or
smaller amounts by many or all of the sellers. Everyone will try to guess the
state of the market and to govern his actions accordingly. Let us suppose that
in fact there are not more than 600 quarters, the holders of which are willing
to accept as low a price as 35s.; but that holders of another hundred would be
tempted by 36s.; and holders of yet another three hundred by 37s. Let us suppose
also that a price of 37s. would tempt buyers for only 600 quarters; while
another hundred could be sold at 36s., and yet another two hundred at 35s. These
facts may be put out in a table thus:--
At the price Holders will be Buyer will be
willing to sell willing to buy
37s. 1000 quarters 600 quarters
36s. 700 " 700 "
35s. 600 " 900 "
Of course some of those who are really willing to take 36s. rather than leave
the market without selling, will not show at once that they are ready to accept
that price. And in like manner buyers will fence, and pretend to be less eager
than they really are. So the price may be tossed hither and thither like a
shuttlecock, as one side or the other gets the better in the "higgling and
bargaining" of the market. But unless they are unequally matched; unless, for
instance, one side is very simple or unfortunate in failing to gauge the
strength of the other side, the price is likely to be never very far from 36s.;
and it is nearly sure to be pretty close to 36s. at the end of the market. For
if a holder thinks that the buyers will really be able to get at 36s. all that
they care to take at that price, he will be unwilling to let slip past him any
offer that is well above that price.
Buyers on their part will make similar calculations; and if at any time the
price should rise considerably above 36s. they will argue that the supply will
be much greater than the demand at that price: therefore even those of them who
would rather pay that price than go unserved, wait; and by waiting they help to
bring the price down. On the other hand, when the price is much below 36s., even
those sellers who would rather take the price than leave the market with their
corn unsold, will argue that at that price the demand will be in excess of the
supply: so they will wait, and by waiting help to bring the price up.
The price of 36s. has thus some claim to be called the true equilibrium price:
because if it were fixed on at the beginning, and adhered to throughout, it
would exactly equate demand and supply (i.e. the amount which buyers were
willing to purchase at that price would be just equal to that for which sellers
were willing to take that price); and because every dealer who has a perfect
knowledge of the circumstances of the market expects that price to be
established If he sees the price differing much from 36s. he expects that a
change will come before long, and by anticipating it he helps it to come
quickly.
It is not indeed necessary for our argument that any dealers should have a
thorough knowledge of the circumstances of the market. Many of the buyers may
perhaps underrate the willingness of the sellers to sell, with the effect that
for some time the price rules at the highest level at which any buyers can be
found; and thus 500 quarters may be sold before the price sinks below 37s. But
afterwards the price must begin to fall and the result will still probably be
that 200 more quarters will be sold, and the market will close on a price of
about 36s. For when 700 quarters have been sold, no seller will be anxious to
dispose of any more except at a higher price than 36s., and no buyer will be
anxious to purchase any more except at a lower price than 36s. In the same way
if the sellers had underrated the willingness of the buyers to pay a high price,
some of them might begin to sell at the lowest price they would take, rather
than have their corn left on their hands, and in this case much corn might be
sold at a price of 35s.; but the market would probably close on a price of 36s.
and a total sale of 700 quarters.(2*)
3. In this illustration there is a latent assumption which is in accordance with
the actual conditions of most markets; but which ought to be distinctly
recognized in order to prevent its creeping into those cases in which it is not
justifiable. We tacitly assumed that the sum which purchasers were willing to
pay, and which sellers were willing to take, for the seven hundredth quarter
would not be affected by the question whether the earlier bargains had been made
at a high or a low rate. We allowed for the diminution in the buyers' need of
corn [its marginal utility to them] as the amount bought increased. But we did
not allow for any appreciable change in their unwillingness to part with money
[its marginal utility]; we assumed that that would be practically the same
whether the early payments had been at a high or a low rate.
This assumption is justifiable with regard to most of the market dealings with
which we are practically concerned. When a person buys anything for his own
consumption, he generally spends on it a small part of his total resources;
while when he buys it for the purposes of trade, he looks to re-selling it, and
therefore his potential resources are not diminished. In either case there is no
appreciable change in his willingness to part with money. There may indeed be
individuals of whom this is not true; but there are sure to be present some
dealers with large stocks of money at their command; and their influence
steadies the market.(3*)
The exceptions are rare and unimportant in markets for commodities; but in
markets for labour they are frequent and important. When a workman is in fear of
hunger, his need of money [its marginal utility to him] is very great; and, if
at starting, he gets the worst of the bargaining, and is employed at low wages,
it remains great, and he may go on selling his labour at a low rate. That is all
the more probable because, while the advantage in bargaining is likely to be
pretty well distributed between the two sides of a market for commodities, it is
more often on the side of the buyers than on that of the sellers in a market for
labour. Another difference between a labour market and a market for commodities
arises from the fact that each seller of labour has only one unit of labour to
dispose of. These are two among many facts, in which we shall find, as we go on,
the explanation of much of that instinctive objection which the working classes
have felt to the habit of some economists, particularly those of the employer
class, of treating labour simply as a commodity and regarding the labour market
as like every other market; whereas in fact the differences between the two
cases, though not fundamental from the point of view of theory, are yet clearly
marked, and in practice often very important.
The theory of buying and selling becomes therefore much more complex when we
take account of the dependence of marginal utility on amount in the case of
money as well as of the commodity itself. The practical importance of this
consideration is not very great. But a contrast is drawn in Appendix F between
barter and dealings in which one side of each exchange is in the form of general
purchasing power. In barter a person 's stock of either commodity exchanged
needs to be adjusted closely to his individual wants. If his stock is too large
he may have no good use for it. If his stock is too small he may have some
difficulty in finding any one who can conveniently give him what he wants and is
also in need of the particular things of which he himself has a superfluity. But
any one who has a stock of general purchasing power, can obtain any thing he
wants as soon as he meets with any one who has a superfluity of that thing. he
needs not to hunt about till he comes across "the double coincidence" of a
person who can spare what he wants, and also wants what he can spare.
Consequently every one, and especially a professional dealer, can afford to keep
command over a large stock of money; and can therefore make considerable
purchases without depleting his stock of money or greatly altering its marginal
value.
NOTES:
1. See IV, I, section 2, and Note XII in the Mathematical Appendix.
2. A simple form of the influence which opinion exerts on the action of dealers,
and therefore on market price, is indicated in this illustration: we shall be
much occupied with more complex developments of it later on.
3. For instance a buyer is sometimes straitened for want of ready money, and has
to let offers pass by him in no way inferior to others which he has gladly
accepted: his own funds being exhausted, he could not perhaps borrow except on
terms that would take away all the profit that the bargains had at first sight
offered. But if the bargain is really a good one, some one else, who is not so
straitened, is nearly sure to get hold of it.
Again, it is possible that several of those who had been counted as ready to
sell corn at a price of 36s. were willing to sell only because they were in
urgent need of a certain amount of ready money; if they succeeded in selling
some corn at a high price, there might be a perceptible diminution in the
marginal utility of ready money to them; and therefore they might refuse to sell
for 36s. a quarter all the corn which they would have sold if the price had been
36s. throughout.
In this case the sellers in consequence of getting an advantage in bargaining at
the beginning of the market might retain to the end a price higher than the
equilibrium price. The price at which the market dosed would be an equilibrium
price; and though not properly described as the equilibrium price, it would be
very unlikely to diverge widely from that price.
Conversely, if the market had opened much to the disadvantage of the sellers and
they had sold some corn very cheap, so that they remained in great want of ready
money, the final utility of money to them might have remained so high that they
would have gone on selling considerably below 36s. until the buyers had been
supplied with all that they cared to take. The market would then close without
the true equilibrium price having ever been reached, but a very near approach
would have been made to it.
CHAPTER 3
EQUILIBRIUM OF NORMAN DEMAND AND SUPPLY
1. We have next to inquire what causes govern supply prices, that is prices
which dealers are willing to accept for different amounts. In the last chapter
we looked at the affairs of only a single day. and supposed the stocks offered
for sale to be already in existence. But of course these stocks are dependent on
the amount of wheat sown in the preceding year; and that, in its turn, was
largely influenced by the farmers' guesses as to the price which they would get
for it in this year. This is the point at which we have to work in the present
chapter.
Even in the corn-exchange of a country town on a market-day the equilibrium
price is affected by calculations of the future relations of production and
consumption; while in the leading corn-markets of America and Europe dealings
for future delivery already predominate and are rapidly weaving into one web all
the leading threads of trade in corn throughout the whole world. Some of these
dealings in "futures" are but incidents in speculative manoeuvres; but in the
main they are governed by calculations of the world's consumption on the one
hand, and of the existing stocks and coming harvests in the Northern and
Southern hemispheres on the other. Dealers take account of the areas sown with
each kind of grain, of the forwardness and weight of the crops, of the supply of
things which can be used as substitutes for grain, and of the things for which
grain can be used as a substitute. Thus, when buying or selling barley, they
take account of the supplies of such things as sugar, which can be used as
substitutes for it in brewing, and again of all the various feeding stuffs, a
scarcity of which might raise the value of barley for consumption on the farm.
If it is thought that the growers of any kind of grain in any part of the world
have been losing money, and are likely to sow a less area for a future harvest;
it is argued that prices are likely to rise as soon as that harvest comes into
sight, and its shortness is manifest to all. Anticipations of that rise exercise
an influence on present sales for future delivery, and that in its turn
influences cash prices; so that these prices are indirectly affected by
estimates of the expenses of producing further supplies.
But in this and the following chapters we are specially concerned with movements
of price ranging over still longer periods than those for which the most
far-sighted dealers in futures generally make their reckoning.. we have to
consider the volume of production adjusting itself to the conditions of the
market, and the normal price being thus determined at the position of stable
equilibrium of normal demand and normal supply.
2. In this discussion we shall have to make frequent use of the terms cost and
expenses of production; and some provisional account of them must be given
before proceeding further.
We may revert to the analogy between the supply price and the demand price of a
commodity. Assuming for the moment that the efficiency of production depends
solely upon the exertions of the workers, we saw that "the price required to
call forth the exertion necessary for producing any given amount of a commodity
may be called the supply price for that amount, with reference of course to a
given unit of time."(1*) But now we have to take account of the fact that the
production of a commodity generally requires many different kinds of labour and
the use of capital in many forms. The exertions of all the different kinds of
labour that are directly or indirectly involved in making it; together with the
abstinences or rather the waitings required for saving the capital used in
making it: all these efforts and sacrifices together will be called the real
cost of production of the commodity. The sums of money that have to be paid for
these efforts and sacrifices will be called either its money cost of production,
or, for shortness, its expenses of production; they are the prices which have to
be paid in order to call forth an adequate supply of the efforts and waitings
that are required for making it; or, in other words, they are its supply
price.(2*)
The analysis of the expenses of production of a commodity might be carried
backward to any length; but it is seldom worth while to go back very far. It is
for instance often sufficient to take the supply prices of the different kinds
of raw materials used in any manufacture as ultimate facts, without analysing
these supply prices into the several elements of which they are composed;
otherwise indeed the analysis would never end. We may then arrange the things
that are required for making a commodity into whatever groups are convenient,
and call them its factors of production.
Its expenses of production when any given amount of it is produced are thus the
supply prices of the corresponding quantities of its factors of production. And
the sum of these is the supply price of that amount of the commodity.
3. The typical modern market is often regarded as that in which manufacturers
sell goods to wholesale dealers at prices into which but few trading expenses
enter. But taking a broader view, we may consider that the supply price of a
commodity is the price at which it will be delivered for sale to that group of
persons whose demand for it we are have considering; or, in other words, in the
market which we have in view. On the character of that market will depend how
many trading expenses have to be reckoned to make up the supply price.(3*) For
instance, the supply price of wood in the neighbourhood of Canadian forests
often consists almost exclusively of the price of the labour of lumber men: but
the supply price of the same wood in the wholesale London market consists in a
large measure of freights; while its supply price to a small retail buyer in an
English country town is more than half made up of the charges of the railways
and middlemen who have brought what he wants to his doors, and keep a stock of
it ready for him. Again, the supply price of a certain kind of labour may for
some purposes be divided up into the expenses of rearing, of general education
and of special trade education. The possible combinations are numberless; and
though each may have incidents of its own which will require separate treatment
in the complete solution of any problem connected with it, yet all such
incidents may be ignored, so far as the general reasonings of this Book are
concerned.
In calculating the expenses of production of a commodity we must take account of
the fact that changes in the amounts produced are likely, even when there is no
new invention, to be accompanied by changes in the relative quantities of its
several factors of production. For instance, when the scale of production
increases, horse or steam power is likely to be substituted for manual labour;
materials are likely to be brought from a greater distance and in greater
quantities, thus increasing those expenses of production which correspond to the
work of carriers, middlemen and traders of all kinds.
As far as the knowledge and business enterprise of the producers reach, they in
each case choose those factors of production which are best for their purpose;
the sum of the supply prices of those factors which are used is, as a rule, less
than the sum of the supply prices of any other set of factors which could be
substituted for them; and whenever it appears to the producers that this is not
the case, they will, as a rule, set to work to substitute the less expensive
method. And further on we shall see how in a somewhat similar way society
substitutes one undertaker for another who is less efficient in proportion to
his charges. We may call this, for convenience of reference, The principle of
substitution.
The applications of this principle extend over almost every field of economic
inquiry.(4*)
4. The position then is this: we are investigating the equilibrium of normal
demand and normal supply in their most general form; we are neglecting those
features which are special to particular parts of economic science, and are
confining our attention to those broad relations which are common to nearly the
whole of it. Thus we assume that the forces of demand and supply have free play;
that there is no close combination among dealers on either side, but each acts
for himself, and there is much free competition; that is, buyers generally
compete freely with buyers, and sellers compete freely with sellers. But though
everyone acts for himself, his knowledge of what others are doing is supposed to
be generally sufficient to prevent him from taking a lower or paying a higher
price than others are doing. This is assumed provisionally to be true both of
finished goods and of their factors of production, of the hire of labour and of
the borrowing of capital. We have already inquired to some extent, and we shall
have to inquire further, how far these assumptions are in accordance with the
actual facts of life. But meanwhile this is the supposition on which we proceed;
we assume that there is only one price in the market at one and the same time;
it being understood that separate allowance is made, when necessary, for
differences in the expense of delivering goods to dealers in different parts of
the market; including allowance for the special expenses of retailing, if it is
a retail market.
In such a market there is a demand price for each amount of the commodity, that
is, a price at which each particular amount of the commodity can find purchasers
in a day or week or year. The circumstances which govern this price for any
given amount of the commodity vary in character from one problem to another; but
in every case the more of a thing is offered for sale in a market the lower is
the price at which it will find purchasers; or in other words, the demand price
for each bushel or yard diminishes with every increase in the amount offered.
The unit of time may be chosen according to the circumstances of each particular
problem: it may be a day, a month, a year, or even a generation: but in every
case it must be short relatively to the period of the market under discussion.
It is to be assumed that the general circumstances of the market remain
unchanged throughout this period; that there is, for instance, no change in
fashion or taste, no new substitute which might affect the demand, no new
invention to disturb the supply.
The conditions of normal supply are less definite; and a full study of them must
be reserved for later chapters. They will be found to vary in detail with the
length of the period of time to which the investigation refers; chiefly because
both the material capital of machinery and other business plant, and the
immaterial capital of business skill and ability and organization, are of slow
growth and slow decay.
Let us call to mind the "representative firm," whose economies of production,
internal and external, are dependent on the aggregate volume of production of
the commodity that it makes;(5*) and, postponing all further study of the nature
of this dependence, let us assume that the normal supply price of any amount of
that commodity may be taken to be its normal expenses of production (including
gross earnings of management(6*)) by that firm. That is, let us assume that this
is the price the expectation of which will just suffice to maintain the existing
aggregate amount of production; some firms meanwhile rising and increasing their
output, and others falling and diminishing theirs; but the aggregate production
remaining unchanged. A price higher than this would increase the growth of the
rising firms, and slacken, though it might not arrest, the decay of the falling
firms; with the net result of an increase in the aggregate production. On the
other hand, a price lower than this would hasten the decay of the falling firms,
and slacken the growth of the rising firms; and on the whole diminish
production: and a rise or fall of price would affect in like manner though
perhaps not in an equal degree those great joint-stock companies which often
stagnate, but seldom die.
5. To give definiteness to our ideas let us take an illustration from the
woollen trade. Let us suppose that a person well acquainted with the woollen
trade sets himself to inquire what would be the normal supply price of a certain
number of millions of yards annually of a particular kind of cloth. He would
have to reckon (i) the price of the wool, coal, and other materials which would
be used up in making it, (ii) wear-and-tear and depreciation of the buildings,
machinery and other fixed capital, (iii) interest and insurance on all the
capital, (iv) the wages of those who work in the factories, and (v) the gross
earnings of management (including insurance against loss), of those who
undertake the risks, who engineer and superintend the working. He would of
course estimate the supply prices of all these different factors of production
of the cloth with reference to the amounts of each of them that would be wanted,
and on the supposition that the conditions of supply would be normal; and he
would add them all together to find the supply price of the cloth.
Let us suppose a list of supply prices (or a supply schedule) made on a similar
plan to that of our list of demand prices:(7*) the supply price of each amount
of the commodity in a year, or any other unit of time, being written against
that amount.(8*) As the flow, or (annual) amount of the commodity increases, the
supply price may either increase or diminish; or it may even alternately
increase and diminish.(9*) For if nature is offering a sturdy resistance to
man's efforts to wring from her a larger supply of raw material, while at that
particular stage there is no great room for introducing important new economies
into the manufacture, the supply price will rise; but if the volume of
production were greater, it would perhaps be profitable to substitute largely
machine work for hand work and steam power for muscular force; and the increase
in the volume of production would have diminished the expenses of production of
the commodity of our representative firm. But those cases in which the supply
price falls as the amount increases involve special difficulties of their own;
and they are postponed to chapter XII of this Book.
6. When therefore the amount produced (in a unit of time) is such that the
demand price is greater than the supply price, then sellers receive more than is
sufficient to make it worth their while to bring goods to market to that amount;
and there is at work an active force tending to increase the amount brought
forward for sale. On the other hand, when the amount produced is such that the
demand price is less than the supply price, sellers receive less than is
sufficient to make it worth their while to bring goods to market on that scale;
so that those who were just on the margin of doubt as to whether to go on
producing are decided not to do so, and there is an active force at work tending
to diminish the amount brought forward for sale. When the demand price is equal
to the supply price, the amount produced has no tendency either to be increased
or to be diminished; it is in equilibrium.
When demand and supply are in equilibrium, the amount of the commodity which is
being produced in a unit of time may be called the equilibrium-amount, and the
price at which it is being sold may be called the equilibrium-price.
Such an equilibrium is stable; that is, the price, if displaced a little from
it, will tend to return, as a pendulum oscillates about its lowest point; and it
will be found to be a characteristic of stable equilibria that in them the
demand price is greater than the supply price for amounts just less than the
equilibrium amount, and vice versa. For when the demand price is greater than
the supply price, the amount produced tends to increase. Therefore, if the
demand price is greater than the supply price for amounts just less than an
equilibrium amount; then, if the scale of production is temporarily diminished
somewhat below that equilibrium amount, it will tend to return; thus the
equilibrium is stable for displacements in that direction. If the demand price
is greater than the supply price for amounts just less than the equilibrium
amount, it is sure to be less than the supply price for amounts just greater:
and therefore, if the scale of production is somewhat increased beyond the
equilibrium position, it will tend to return; and the equilibrium will be stable
for displacements in that direction also.
When demand and supply are in stable equilibrium, if any accident should move
the scale of production from its equilibrium position, there will be instantly
brought into play forces tending to push it back to that position; just as, if a
stone hanging by a string is displaced from its equilibrium position, the force
of gravity will at once tend to bring it back to its equilibrium position. The
movements of the scale of production about its position of equilibrium will be
of a somewhat similar kind.(10*)
But in real life such oscillations are seldom as rhythmical as those of a stone
hanging freely from a string; the comparison would be more exact if the string
were supposed to hang in the troubled waters of a mill-race, whose stream was at
one time allowed to flow freely, and at another partially cut off. Nor are these
complexities sufficient to illustrate all the disturbances with which the
economist and the merchant alike are forced to concern themselves. If the person
holding the string swings his hand with movements partly rhythmical and partly
arbitrary, the illustration will not outrun the difficulties of some very real
and practical problems of value. For indeed the demand and supply schedules do
not in practice remain unchanged for a long time together, but are constantly
being changed; and every change in them alters the equilibrium amount and the
equilibrium price, and thus gives new positions to the centres about which the
amount and the price tend to oscillate.
These considerations point to the great importance of the element of time in
relation to demand and supply, to the study of which we now proceed. We shall
gradually discover a great many different limitations of the doctrine that the
price at which a thing can be produced represents its real cost of production,
that is, the efforts and sacrifices which have been directly and indirectly
devoted to its production. For, in an age of rapid change such as this, the
equilibrium of normal demand and supply does not thus correspond to any distinct
relation of a certain aggregate of pleasures got from the consumption of the
commodity and an aggregate of efforts and sacrifices involved in producing it:
the correspondence would not be exact, even if normal earnings and interest were
exact measures of the efforts and sacrifices for which they are the money
payments. This is the real drift of that much quoted, and much-misunderstood
doctrine of Adam Smith and other economists that the normal, or "natural," value
of a commodity is that which economic forces tend to bring about in the long
run. It is the average value which economic forces would bring about if the
general conditions of life were stationary for a run of time long enough to
enable them all to work out their full effect.(11*)
But we cannot foresee the future perfectly. The unexpected may happen; and the
existing tendencies may be modified before they have had time to accomplish what
appears now to be their full and complete work. The fact that the general
conditions of life are not stationary is the source of many of the difficulties
that are met with in applying economic doctrines to practical problems.
Of course Normal does not mean Competitive. Market prices and Normal prices are
alike brought about by a multitude of influences, of which some rest on a moral
basis and some on a physical; of which some are competitive and some are not. It
is to the persistence of the influences considered, and the time allowed for
them to work out their effects that we refer when contrasting Market and Normal
price, and again when contrasting the narrower and the broader use of the term
Normal price.(12*)
7. The remainder of the present volume will be chiefly occupied with
interpreting and limiting this doctrine that the value of a thing tends in the
long run to correspond to its cost of production. In particular the notion of
equilibrium, which has been treated rather slightly in this chapter, will be
studied more carefully in chapters V and XII of this Book: and some account of
the controversy whether "cost of production" or "utility" governs value will be
given in Appendix I. But it may be well to say a word or two here on this last
point.
We might as reasonably dispute whether it is the upper or the under blade of a
pair of scissors that cuts a piece of paper, as whether value is governed by
utility or cost of production. It is true that when one blade is held still, and
the cutting is effected by moving the other, we may say with careless brevity
that the cutting is done by the second; but the statement is not strictly
accurate, and is to be excused only so long as it claims to be merely a popular
and not a strictly scientific account of what happens.
In the same way, when a thing already made has to be sold, the price which
people will be willing to pay for it will be governed by their desire to have
it, together with the amount they can afford to spend on it. Their desire to
have it depends partly on the chance that, if they do not buy it, they will be
able to get another thing like it at as low a price: this depends on the causes
that govern the supply of it, and this again upon cost of production. But it may
so happen that the stock to be sold is practically fixed. This, for instance, is
the case with a fish market, in which the value of fish for the day is governed
almost exclusively by the stock on the slabs in relation to the demand: and if a
person chooses to take the stock for granted, and say that the price is governed
by demand, his brevity may perhaps be excused so long as he does not claim
strict accuracy. So again it may be pardonable, but it is not strictly accurate
to say that the varying prices which the same rare book fetches, when sold and
resold at Christie 's auction room, are governed exclusively by demand.
Taking a case at the opposite extreme, we find some commodities which conform
pretty closely to the law of constant return; that is to say, their average cost
of production will be very nearly the same whether they are produced in small
quantities or in large. In such a case the normal level about which the market
price fluctuates will be this definite and fixed (money) cost of production. If
the demand happens to be great, the market price will rise for a time above the
level; but as a result production will increase and the market price will fall:
and conversely, if the demand falls for a time below its ordinary level.
In such a case, if a person chooses to neglect market fluctuations, and to take
it for granted that there will anyhow be enough demand for the commodity to
insure that some of it, more or less, will find purchasers at a price equal to
this cost of production, then he may be excused for ignoring the influence of
demand, and speaking of (normal) price as governed by cost of production --
provided only he does not claim scientific accuracy for the wording of his
doctrine, and explains the influence of demand in its right place.
Thus we may conclude that, as a general rule, the shorter the period which we
are considering, the greater must be the share of our attention which is given
to the influence of demand on value; and the longer the period, the more
important will be the influence of cost of production on value. For the
influence of changes in cost of production takes as a rule a longer time to work
itself out than does the influence of changes in demand. The actual value at any
time, the market value as it is often called, is often more influenced by
passing events and by causes whose action is fitful and short lived, than by
those which work persistently. But in long periods these fitful and irregular
causes in large measure efface one another's influence; so that in the long run
persistent causes dominate value completely. Even the most persistent causes are
however liable to change. For the whole structure of production is modified, and
the relative costs of production of different things are permanently altered,
from one generation to another.
When considering costs from the point of view of the capitalist employer, we of
course measure them in money; because his direct concern with the efforts needed
for the work of his employees lies in the money payments he must make. His
concern with the real costs of their effort and of the training required for it
is only indirect, though a monetary assessment of his own labour is necessary
for some problems, as will be seen later on. But when considering costs from the
social point of view, when inquiring whether the cost of attaining a given
result is increasing or diminishing with changing economic conditions, then we
are concerned with the real costs of efforts of various qualities, and with the
real cost of waiting. If the purchasing power of money, in terms of effort has
remained about constant, and if the rate of remuneration for waiting has
remained about constant, then the money measure of costs corresponds to the real
costs: but such a correspondence is never to be assumed lightly. These
considerations will generally suffice for the interpretation of the term Cost in
what follows, even where no distinct indication is given in the context.
NOTES:
1. IV, I, section 2.
2. Mill and some other economists have followed the practice of ordinary life in
using the term Cost of production in two senses, sometimes to signify the
difficulty of producing a thing, and sometimes to express the outlay of money
that has to be incurred in order to induce people to overcome this difficulty
and produce it. But by passing from one use of the term to the other without
giving explicit warning, they have led to many misunderstandings and much barren
controversy. The attack on Mill's doctrine of Cost of Production in relation to
Value, which is made in Cairnes' leading Principles, was published just after
Mill's death; and unfortunately his interpretation of Mill's words was generally
accepted as authoritative, because he was regarded as a follower of Mill. But in
an article by the present writer on "Mill's Theory of Value" (Fortnightly
Review, April 1876) it is argued that Cairnes had mistaken Mill's meaning, and
had really seen not more but less of the truth than Mill had done.
The expenses of production of any amount of a raw commodity may best be
estimated with reference to the "margin of production" at which no rent is paid.
But this method of speaking has great difficulties with regard to commodities
that obey the law of increasing return. It seemed best to note this point in
passing: it will be fully discussed later on, chiefly in ch. XII.
3. We have already (II, iii) noticed that the economic use of the term
"production", includes the production of new utilities by moving a thing from a
place in which it is less wanted to a place in which it is more wanted, or by
helping consumers to satisfy their needs.
4. See III, v and IV, VII, section 8.
5. See IV XIII, section 2.
6. See last paragraph of IV, XII.
7. See III, III, section 4.
8. Measuring, as in the case of the demand curve, amounts of the commodity along
Ox and prices parallel to 0y, We get for each point M along Ox a line MP drawn
at right angles to it measuring the supply price for the amount OM, the
extremity of which, P, may be called a supply point; this price MP being made up
of the supply prices of the several factors of production for the amount OM. The
locus of P may be called the supply curve.
Suppose, for instance, that we classify the expenses of production of our
representative firm, when an amount OM of cloth is being produced under the
heads of (i) Mp1' the supply price of the wool and other circulating capital
which would be consumed in making it, (ii) p1 p2 the corresponding wearand-tear
and depreciation on buildings, machinery and other fixed capital; (iii) p2p3 the
interest and insurance on all the capital, (iv) p3p4 the wages of those who work
in the factory, and (v) p4P the gross earnings of management, etc. of those who
undertake the risks and direct the work. Thus as M moves from O towards the
right p1' p2, p3' p4 will each trace out a curve, and the ultimate supply curve
traced out by P will be thus shown as obtained by superimposing the supply
curves for the several factors of production of the cloth.
It must be remembered that these supply prices are the prices not of units of
the several factors but of those amounts of the several factors which for
producing a yard of the cloth. Thus, for instance, p3p4 is the supply price are
required not of any fixed amount of labour but of that amount of labour which is
employed in making a yard where there is an aggregate production of OM yards.
(See above, section 3.) We need not trouble ourselves to consider just here
whether the groundrent of the factory must be put into a class by itself: this
belongs to a group of questions which will be discussed later. We are taking no
notice of rates and taxes, for which he would of course have to make his
account.
9. That is, a point moving along the supply curve towards the right may either
rise or fall, or even it may alternately rise and fall; in other words, the
supply curve may be inclined positively or negatively, or even at some parts of
its course it may be inclined positively and at others negatively. (See footnote
on p. 99.)
10. Compare V, I, section 1. To represent the equilibrium of demand and supply
geometrically we may draw the demand and supply curves together as in Fig. 19.
If then OR represents the rate at which production is being actually carried on,
and Rd the demand price is greater than Rs the supply price, the production is
exceptionally profitable, and will be increased. R, the amount-index, as we may
call it, will move to the right. On the other hand, if Rd is less than Rs, R
will move to the left. If Rd is equal to Rs, that is, if R is vertically under a
point of intersection of the curves, demand and supply are in equilibrium.
This may be taken as the typical diagram for stable equilibrium for a commodity
that obeys the law of diminishing return. But if we had made SS' a horizontal
straight line, we should have represented the case of "constant return," in
which the supply price is the same for all amounts of the commodity. And if we
had made SS' inclined negatively, but less steeply than DD' (the necessity for
this condition will appear more fully later on), we should have got a case of
stable equilibrium for a commodity which obeys the law of increasing return. In
either case the above reasoning remains unchanged without the alteration of a
word or a letter; but the last case introduces difficulties which we have
arranged to postpone.
11. See below V, v, section 2 and Appendix H, section 4.
12. See above, pp. 34-6.
CHAPTER 4
THE INVESTMENT AND DISTRIBUTION OF RESOURCES
1. The first difficulty to be cleared up in our study of normal values, is the
nature of the motives which govern the investment of resources for a distant
return. It will be well to begin by watching the action of a person who neither
buys what he wants nor sells what he makes, but works on his own behalf; and who
therefore balances the, efforts and sacrifices which he makes on the one hand
against the pleasures which he expects to derive from their fruit on the other,
without the intervention of any money payments at all.
Let us then take the case of a man who builds a house for himself on land, and
of materials, which nature supplies gratis; and who makes his implements as he
goes, the labour of making them being counted as part of the labour of building
the house. He would have to estimate the efforts required for building on any
proposed plan; and to allow almost instinctively an amount increasing in
geometrical proportion (a sort of compound interest) for the period that would
elapse between each effort and the time when the house would be ready for his
use. The utility of the house to him when finished would have to compensate him
not only for the efforts, but for the waitings.(1*)
If the two motives, one deterring, the other impelling, seemed equally balanced,
he would be on the margin of doubt. Probably the gain would much more than
outweigh the "real" cost with regard to some part of the house. But as he turned
over more and more ambitious plans, he would at last find the advantages of any
further extension balanced by the efforts and waitings required for making it;
and that extension of the building would be on the outer limit, or margin of
profitableness of the investment of his capital.
There would probably be several ways of building parts of the house; some parts
for instance might almost equally well be built of wood or of rough stones: the
investment of capital on each plan for each part of the accommodation would be
compared with the advantages offered thereby, and each would be pushed forward
till the outer limit or margin of profitableness had been reached. Thus there
would be a great many margins of profitableness: one corresponding to each kind
of plan on which each kind of accommodation might be provided.
2. This illustration may serve to keep before us the way in which the efforts
and sacrifices which are the real cost of production of a thing, underlie the
expenses which are its money cost. But, as has just been remarked, the modern
business man commonly takes the payments which he has to make, whether for wages
or raw material, as he finds them; without staying to inquire how far they are
an accurate measure of the efforts and sacrifices to which they correspond. His
expenditure is generally made piece-meal; and the longer he expects to wait for
the fruit of any outlay, the richer must that fruit be in order to compensate
him. The anticipated fruit may not be certain; and in that case he will have to
allow for the risk of failure. After making that allowance, the fruit of the
outlay must be expected to exceed the outlay itself by an amount which,
independently of his own remuneration, increases at compound interest in
proportion to the time of waiting.(2*) Under this head are to be entered the
heavy expenses, direct and indirect, which every business must incur in building
up its connection.
For brevity we may speak of any element of outlay (allowance being made for the
remuneration of the undertaker himself) when increased by compound interest in
this way, as accumulated; just as we used the term discounted to represent the
present value of a future gratification. Each element of outlay has then to be
accumulated for the time which will elapse between its being incurred and its
bearing fruit; and the aggregate of these accumulated elements is the total
outlay involved in the enterprise. The balance between efforts and the
satisfactions resulting from them may be made up to any day that is found
convenient. But whatever day is chosen, one simple rule must be followed: --
Every element whether an effort or a satisfaction, which dates from a time
anterior to that day, must have compound interest for the interval accumulated
upon it: and every element, which dates from a time posterior to that day, must
have compound interest for the interval discounted from it. If the day be
anterior to the beginning of the enterprise, then every element must be
discounted. But if, as is usual in such cases, the day be that when the efforts
are finished, and the house is ready for use; then the efforts must carry
compound interest up to that day, and the satisfactions must all be discounted
back to that day.
Waiting is an element of cost as truly as effort is, and it is entered in the
cost when accumulated: it is therefore of course not counted separately.
Similarly, on the converse side, whatever money or command over satisfaction
"comes in" at any time is part of the income of that time: if the time is before
the day for which accounts are balanced up, then it must be accumulated up to
that day; if after it must be discounted back. If, instead of being converted to
immediate enjoyment, it is used as a stored up source of future income, that
later income must not be counted as an additional return to the investment.(3*)
If the enterprise were, say, to dig out a dock-basin on a contract, the payment
for which would be made without fail when the work was finished; and if the
plant used in the work might be taken to be worn out in the process, and
valueless at the end of it; then the enterprise would be just remunerative if
this aggregate of outlays, accumulated up to the period of payment, were just
equal to that payment.
But, as a rule, the proceeds of the sales come in gradually. and we must suppose
a balance-sheet struck, looking both backwards and forwards. Looking backwards
we should sum up the net outlays, and add in accumulated compound interest on
each element of outlay. Looking forwards we should sum up all net incomings, and
from the value of each subtract compound interest for the period during which it
would be deferred. The aggregate of the net incomings so discounted would be
balanced against the aggregate of the accumulated outlays: and if the two were
just equal, the business would be just remunerative. In calculating the
outgoings the head of the business must reckon in the value of his own work.(4*)
3. At the beginning of his undertaking, and at every successive stage, the alert
business man strives so to modify his arrangements as to obtain better results
with a given expenditure, or equal results with a less expenditure. In other
words, he ceaselessly applies the principle of substitution, with the purpose of
increasing his profits; and, in so doing, he seldom fails to increase the total
efficiency of work, the total power over nature which man derives from
organization and knowledge.
Every locality has incidents of its own which affect in various ways the methods
of arrangement of every class of business that is carried on in it: and even in
the same place and the same trade no two persons pursuing the same aims will
adopt exactly the same routes. The tendency to variation is a chief cause of
progress; and the abler are the undertakers in any trade the greater will this
tendency be. In some trades, as for instance cotton-spinning, the possible
variations are confined within narrow limits; no one can hold his own at all who
does not use machinery, and very nearly the latest machinery, for every part of
the work. But in others, as for instance in some branches of the wood and metal
trades, in farming, and in shopkeeping, there can be great variations. For
instance, of two manufacturers in the same trade, one will perhaps have a larger
wages bill and the other heavier charges on account of machinery; of two retail
dealers one will have a larger capital locked up in stock and the other will
spend more on advertisements and other means of building up the immaterial
capital of a profitable trade connection. And in minor details the variations
are numberless.
Each man's actions are influenced by his special opportunities and resources, as
well as by his temperament and his associations: but each, taking account of his
own means, will push the investment of capital in his business in each several
direction until what appears in his judgment to be the outer limit, or margin,
of profitableness is reached; that is, until there seems to him no good reason
for thinking that the gains resulting from any further investment in that
particular direction would compensate him for his outlay. The margin of
profitableness, even in regard to one and the same branch or sub-branch of
industry, is not to be regarded as a mere point on any one fixed line of
possible investment; but as a boundary line of irregular shape cutting one after
another every possible line of investment.
4. This principle of substitution is closely connected with, and is indeed
partly based on, that tendency to a diminishing rate of return from any
excessive application of resources or of energies in any given direction, which
is in accordance with general experience. It is thus linked up with the broad
tendency of a diminishing return to increased applications of capital and labour
to land in old countries which plays a prominent part in classical economics.
And it is so closely akin to the principle of the diminution of marginal utility
that results in general from increased expenditure, that some applications of
the two principles are almost identical. It has already been observed that new
methods of production bring into existence new commodities, or lower the price
of old commodities so as to bring them within the reach of increased numbers of
consumers: that on the other hand changes in the methods and volume of
consumption cause new developments of production, and new distribution of the
resources of production: and that though some methods of consumption which
contribute most to man's higher life, do little if anything towards furthering
the production of material wealth, yet production and consumption are intimately
correlated.(5*) But now we are to consider more in detail how the distribution
of the resources of production between different industrial undertakings is the
counterpart and reflex of the distribution of the consumers' purchases between
different classes of commodities.(6*)
Let us revert to the primitive housewife, who having "a limited number of hanks
of yarn from the year's shearing, considers all the domestic wants for clothing
and tries to distribute the yarn between them in such a way as to contribUte as
much as possible to the family well-being. She will think she has failed if,
when it is done, she has reason to regret that she did not apply more to making,
say, socks, and less to vests. But if, on the other hand, she hit on the right
points to stop at, then she made just so many socks and vests that she got an
equal amount of good out of the last bundle of yarn that she applied to socks,
and the last she applied to vests."(7*) If it happened that two ways of making a
vest were open to her, which were equally satisfactory as regards results, but
of which one, while using up a little more yarn, involved a little less trouble
than the other; then her problems would be typical of those of the larger
business world. They would include first decisions as to the relative urgency of
various ends; secondly, decisions as to the relative advantages of various means
of attaining each end; thirdly, decisions, based on these two sets of decisions,
as to the margin up to which she could most profitably carry the application of
each means towards each end.
These three classes of decisions have to be taken on a larger scale by the
business man, who has more complex balancings and adjustments to make before
reaching each decision.(8*) Let us take an illustration from the building trade.
Set us watch the operations of a "speculative builder" in the honourable sense
of the term: that is, a man who sets out to erect honest buildings in
anticipation of general demand; who bears the penalty of any error in his
judgment; and who, if his judgment is approved by events, benefits the community
as well as himself. Let him be considering whether to erect dwelling houses, or
warehouses, or factories or shops. He is trained to form at once a fairly good
opinion as to the method of working most suitable for each class of building,
and to make a rough estimate of its cost. He estimates the cost of various sites
adapted for each class of building: and he reckons in the price that he would
have to pay for any site as a part of his capital expenditure, just as he does
the expense to which he would be put for laying foundations in it, and so on. He
brings this estimate of cost into relation with his estimate of the price he is
likely to get for any given building, together with its site. If he can find no
case in which the demand price exceeds his outlays by enough to yield him a good
profit, with some margin against risks, he may remain idle. Or he may possibly
build at some risk in order to keep his most trusty workmen together, and to
find some occupation for his plant and his salaried assistance: but more on this
later on.
Suppose him now to have decided that (say) villa residences of a certain type,
erected on a plot of ground which he can buy, are likely to yield him a good
profit. The main end to be sought being thus settled, he sets himself to study
more carefully the means by which it is to be obtained, and, in connection with
that study, to consider possible modifications in the details of his plans.
Given the general character of the houses to be built, he will have to consider
in what proportions to use various materials-brick, stone, steel, cement,
plaster, wood, etc., with a view to obtaining the result which will contribute
most, in proportion to its cost, to the efficiency of the house in gratifying
the artistic taste of purchasers and in ministering to their comfort. In thus
deciding what is the best distribution of his resources between various
commodities, he is dealing with substantially the same problem as the primitive
housewife, who has to consider the most economic distribution of her yarn
between the various needs of her household.
Like her, he has to reflect that the yield of benefit which any particular use
gave would be relatively large up to a certain point, and would then gradually
diminish. Like her, he has so to distribute his resources that they have the
same marginal utility in each use: he has to weigh the loss that would result
from taking away a little expenditure here, with the gain that would result from
adding a little there. In effect both of them work on lines similar to those
which guide the farmer in so adjusting the application of his capital and labour
to land, that no field is stinted of extra cultivation to which it would have
given a generous return, and none receives so great an expenditure as to call
into strong activity the tendency to diminishing return in agriculture.(9*)
Thus it is that the alert business man, as has just been said, "pushes the
investment of capital in his business in each several direction until what
appears in his judgment to be the outer limit, or margin, of profitableness is
reached; that is, until there seems to him no good reason for thinking that the
gains resulting from any further investment in that particular direction would
compensate him for his outlay." He never assumes that roundabout methods will be
remunerative in the long run. But he is always on the look out for roundabout
methods that promise to be more effective in proportion to their cost than
direct methods: and he adopts the best of them, if it lies within his means.
######
5. Some technical terms relating to costs may be considered here. When investing
his capital in providing the means of carrying on an undertaking, the business
man looks to being recouped by the price obtained for its various products; and
he expects to be able under normal conditions to charge for each of them a
sufficient price; that is, one which will not only cover the special, direct, or
prime cost, but also bear its proper share of the general expenses of the
business; and these we may call its general, or supplementary cost. These two
elements together make its total cost.
There are great variations in the usage of the term Prime cost in business. But
it is taken here in a narrow sense. Supplementary costs are taken to include
standing charges on account of the durable plant in which much of the capital of
the business has been invested, and also the salaries of the upper employees:
for the charges to which the business is put on account of their salaries cannot
generally be adapted quickly to changes in the amount of work there is for them
to do. There remains nothing but the (money) cost of the raw material used in
making the commodity and the wages of that part of the labour spent on it which
is paid by the hour or the piece and the extra wear-and-tear of plant. This is
the special cost which a manufacturer has in view, when his works are not fully
employed, and he is calculating the lowest price at which it will be worth his
while to accept an order, irrespectively of any effect that his action may have
in spoiling the market for future orders, and trade being slack at the time. But
in fact he must as a rule take account of this effect: the price at which it is
just worth his while to produce, even when trade is slack, is in practice
generally a good deal above this prime cost, as we shall see later on.(10*)
6. Supplementary costs must generally be covered by the selling price to some
considerable extent in the short run. And they must be completely covered by it
in the long run; for, if they are not, production will be checked. Supplementary
costs are of many different kinds; and some of them differ only in degree from
prime costs. For instance, if an engineering firm is in doubt whether to accept
an order at a rather low price for a certain locomotive, the absolute prime
costs include the value of the raw material and the wages of the artisans and
labourers employed on the locomotive. But there is no clear rule as to the
salaried staff: for, if work is slack, they will probably have some time on
their hands; and their salaries will therefore commonly be classed among general
or supplementary costs. The line of division is however often blurred over. For
instance, foremen and other trusted artisans are seldom dismissed merely because
of a temporary scarcity of work; and therefore an occasional order may be taken
to fill up idle time, even though its price does not cover their salaries and
wages. That is they may not be regarded as prime costs in such a case. But, of
course the staff in the office can be in some measure adjusted to variations in
the work of the firm by leaving vacancies unfilled and even by weeding out
inefficient men during slack times; and by getting extra help or putting out
some of the work in busy times.
If we pass from such tasks to larger and longer tasks, as for instance the
working out a contract to deliver a great number of locomotives gradually over a
period of several years, then most of the office work done in connection with
that order must be regarded as special for it: for if it had been declined and
nothing else taken in its place, the expenses under the head of salaries could
have been reduced almost to a proportionate extent.
The case is much stronger when we consider a fairly steady market for any class
of staple manufactures extending over a long time. For then the outlay incurred
for installing specialized skill and organization, the permanent office staff,
and the durable plant of the workshops can all be regarded as part of the costs
necessary for the process of production. That outlay will be increased up to a
margin at which the branch of manufacture seems in danger of growing too fast
for its market.
In the next chapter the argument of Chapter III and of this chapter is
continued. It is shown in more detail how those costs which most powerfully act
on supply and therefore on price, are limited to a narrow and arbitrary group in
the case of a single contract for, say, a locomotive; but are much fuller, and
correspond much more truly to the broad features of industrial economy in the
case of a continuous supply to a fairly steady general market: the influence of
cost of production on value does not show itself clearly except in relatively
long periods; and it is to be estimated with regard to a whole process of
production rather than a particular locomotive, or a particular parcel of goods.
And a similar study is made in Chapters VIII-X of variations in the character of
those prime and supplementary costs which consist of charges for interest (or
profits) on investments in agents of production, according as the periods of the
market under consideration are long or short.
Meanwhile it may be noticed that the distinction between prime and supplementary
costs operates in every phase of civilization, though it is not likely to
attract much attention except in a capitalistic phase. Robinson Crusoe had to do
only with real costs and real satisfactions: and an old-fashioned peasant
family, which bought little and sold little, arranged its investments of present
"effort and waiting" for future benefits on nearly the same lines. But, if
either were doubting whether it was worth while to take a light ladder on a trip
to gather wild fruits, the prime costs alone would be weighed against the
expected benefits: and yet the ladder would not have been made, unless it had
been expected to render sufficient service in the aggregate of many little
tasks, to remunerate the cost of making it. In the long run it had to repay its
total costs, supplementary as well as prime.
Even the modern employer has to look at his own labour as a real cost in the
first instance. He may think that a certain enterprise is likely to yield a
surplus of money incomings over money outgoings (after proper allowances for
risks and for discountings of future happenings); but that the surplus will
amount to less than the money equivalent of the trouble and worry that the
enterprise will cause to himself: and, in that case, he will avoid it.(11*)
NOTES:
1. For he might have applied these efforts, or efforts equivalent to them, to
producing immediate gratifications; and if he deliberately chose the deferred
gratifications, it would be because, even after allowing for the disadvantages
of waiting, he regarded them as outweighing the earlier gratifications which he
could have substituted for them. The motive force then tending to deter him from
building the house would be his estimate of the aggregate of these efforts, the
evil or discommodity of each being increased in geometrical proportion (a sort
of compound interest) according to the corresponding interval of waiting. The
motive on the other hand impelling him to build it, would be expectation of the
satisfaction which he would have from the house when completed; and that again
might be resolved into the aggregate of many satisfactions more or less remote,
and more or less certain, which he expected to derive from its use. If he
thought that this aggregate of discounted values of satisfactions that it would
afford him, would be more than a recompense to him for all the efforts and
waitings which he had undergone, he would decide to build. (See III, v, section
3, IV, VII, section 8 and Note XIII in the Mathematical Appendix.)
2. We may, if we choose, regard the price of the business undertaker's own work
as part of the original outlay, and reckon compound interest on it together with
the rest. Or we may substitute for compound interest a sort of "compound
profit." The two courses are not strictly convertible: and at a later stage we
shall find that in certain cases the first is to be preferred, and in others the
second.
3. In the aggregate the income from the saving will in the ordinary course be
larger in amount than the saving by the amount of the interest that is the
reward of saving. But, as it will be turned to account in enjoyment later than
the original saving could have been, it will be discounted for a longer period
(or accumulated for a shorter); and if entered in the balance sheet of the
investment in place of the original saving, it would stand for exactly the same
sum. (Both the original income which was saved and the subsequent income earned
by it are assessed to income tax; on grounds similar to those which make it
expedient to levy a larger income tax from the industrious than from the lazy
man.) The main argument of this section is expressed mathematically in Note
XIII.
4. Almost every trade has its own difficulties and its own customs connected
with the task of valuing the capital that has been invested in a business, and
of allowing for the depreciation which that capital has undergone from
wear-and-tear, from the influence of the elements, from new inventions, and from
changes in the course of trade. These two last causes may temporarily raise the
value of some kinds of fixed capital, at the same time that they are lowering
that of others. And people whose minds are cast in different moulds, or whose
interests in the matter point in different directions, will often differ widely
on the question what part of the expenditure required for adapting buildings and
plant to changing conditions of trade, may be regarded as an investment of new
capital; and what ought to be set down as charges incurred to balance
depreciation, and treated as expedenditure deducted from the current receipts,
before determining the net profits of true income earned by the business. These
difficulties, and the consequent differences of opinion, are greatest of all
with regard to the investment of capital in building up a business connection,
and the proper method of appraising the goodwill of a business, or its value "as
a going concern." On the whole of this subject see Matheson's Depreciation of
Factories and their Valuation.
Another group of difficulties arises from changes in the general purchasing
Power of money. If that has fallen, or, in other words, if there has been a rise
of general prices, the value of a factory may appear to have risen when it has
really remained stationary. Confusions arising from this source introduce
greater errors into estimates of the real profitableness of different classes of
business than would at first sight appear probable. But all questions of this
kind must be deferred till we have discussed the theory of money.
5. See pp. 84-91, and 64-7.
6. The substance of part of this section was placed in VI, i, section 7 in
earlier editions. But it seems to be needed here in preparation for the central
chapters of Book V.
7. See III, v, section i.
8. The remainder of this section goes very much on the lines of the earlier half
of Note XIV in the Mathematical Appendix; which may be read in connection with
it. The subject is one in which the language of the differential calculusnot its
reasonings -- are specially helpful to clear thought: but the main outlines can
be presented in ordinary language.
9. See above III, iii section 1; and the footnote on pp. 156-7.
10. Especially in V, IX, "There are many systems of Prime Cost in vogue... we
take Prime Cost to mean, as in fact the words imply, only the original or direct
cost of production; and while in some trades it may be a matter of convenience
to include in the cost of production a proportion of indirect expenses, and a
charge for depreciation on plant and buildings, in no case should it comprise
interest on capital or profit." (Garcke and Fells, Factory Accounts, ch. i.)
11. The Supplementary costs, which the owner of a factory expects to be able to
add to the prime costs of its products, are the source of the quasi-rents which
it will yield to him. If they come up to his expectation, then his business so
far yields good profits: if they fall much short of it, his business tends to go
to the bad. But this statement bears only on long-period problems of value: and
in that connection the difference between Prime and Supplementary costs has no
special significance. The importance of the distinction between them is confined
to shortperiod problems.
CHAPTER 5
EQUILIBRIUM OF NORMAL DEMAND AND SUPPLY, CONTINUED, WITH REFERENCE TO LONG AND
SHORT PERIODS
1. The variations in the scope of the term Normal, according as the periods of
time under discussion are long or short, were indicated in Chapter III. We are
now ready to study them more closely.
In this case, as in others, the economist merely brings to light difficulties
that are latent in the common discourse of life, so that by being frankly faced
they may be thoroughly overcome. For in ordinary life it is customary to use the
word Normal in different senses, with reference to different periods of time;
and to leave the context to explain the transition from one to another. The
economist follows this practice of every-day life: but, by taking pains to
indicate the transition, he sometimes seems to have created a complication which
in fact he has only revealed.
Thus, when it is said that the price of wool on a certain day was abnormally
high though the average price for the year was abnormally low, that the wages of
coal-miners were abnormally high in 1872 and abnormally low in 1879, that the
(real) wages of labour were abnormally high at the end of the fourteenth century
and abnormally low in the middle of the sixteenth; everyone understands that the
scope of the term normal is not the same in these various cases.
The best illustrations of this come from manufactures where the plant is
long-lived, and the product is short-lived.
When a new textile fabric is first introduced into favour, and there is very
little plant suitable for making it, its normal price for some months may be
twice as high as those of other fabrics which are not less difficult to make,
but for making which there is an abundant stock of suitable plant and skill.
Looking at long periods we may say that its normal price is on a par with that
of the others: but if during the first few months a good deal of it were offered
for sale in a bankrupt's stock we might say that its price was abnormally low
even when it was selling for half as much again as the others. Everyone takes
the context as indicating the special use of the term in each several case; and
a formal interpretation clause is seldom necessary, because in ordinary
conversation misunderstandings can be nipped in the bud by question and answer.
But let us look at this matter more closely.
We have noticed(1*) how a cloth manufacturer would need to calculate the
expenses of producing all the different things required for making cloth with
reference to the amounts of each of them that would be wanted; and on the
supposition in the first instance that the conditions of supply would be normal.
But we have yet to take account of the fact that he must give to this term a
wider or narrower range, according as he was looking more or less far ahead.
Thus in estimating the wages required to call forth an adequate supply of labour
to work a certain class of looms, he might take the current wages of similar
work in the neighbourhood: or he might argue that there was a scarcity of that
particular class of labour in the neighbourhood, that its current wages there
were higher than in other parts of England, and that looking forward over
several years so as to allow for immigration, he might take the normal rate of
wages at a rather lower rate than that prevailing there at the time. Or lastly,
he might think that the wages of weavers all over the country were abnormally
low relatively to others of the same grade, in consequence of a too sanguine
view having been taken of the prospects of the trade half a generation ago. He
might argue that this branch of work was overcrowded, that parents had already
begun to choose other trades for their children which offered greater net
advantages and yet were not more difficult; that in consequence a few years
would see a falling-off in the supply of labour suited for his purpose; so that
looking forward a long time he must take normal wages at a rate rather higher
than the present average.(2*)
Again, in estimating the normal supply price of wool, he would take the average
of several past years. He would make allowance for any change that would be
likely to affect the supply in the immediate future; and he would reckon for the
effect of such droughts as from time to time occur in Australia and elsewhere;
since their occurrence is too common to be regarded as abnormal. But he would
not allow here for the chance of our being involved in a great war, by which the
Australian supplies might be cut off; he would consider that any allowance for
this should come under the head of extraordinary trade risks, and not enter into
his estimate of the normal supply price of wool.
He would deal in the same way with the risk of civil tumult or any violent and
long-continued disturbance of the labour market of an unusual character; but in
his estimate of the amount of work that could be got out of the machinery, etc.
under normal conditions, he would probably reckon for minor interruptions from
trade disputes such as are continually occurring, and are therefore to be
regarded as belonging to the regular course of events, that is as not abnormal.
In all these calculations he would not concern himself specially to inquire how
far mankind are under the exclusive influence of selfish or self-regarding
motives. He might be aware that anger and vanity, jealousy and offended dignity
are still almost as common causes of strikes and lockouts, as the desire for
pecuniary gain: but that would not enter into his calculations. All that he
would want to know about them would be whether they acted with sufficient
regularity for him to be able to make a reasonably good allowance for their
influence in interrupting work and raising the normal supply price of the
goods.(3*)
2. The element of time is a chief cause of those difficulties in economic
investigations which make it necessary for man with his limited powers to go
step by step; breaking up a complex question, studying one bit at a time, and at
last combining his partial solutions into a more or less complete solution of
the whole riddle. In breaking it up, he segregates those disturbing causes,
whose wanderings happen to be inconvenient, for the time in a pound called
Caeteris Paribus. The study of some group of tendencies is isolated by the
assumption other things being equal: the existence of other tendencies is not
denied, but their disturbing effect is neglected for a time. The more the issue
is thus narrowed, the more exactly can it be handled: but also the less closely
does it correspond to real life. Each exact and firm handling of a narrow issue,
however, helps towards treating broader issues, in which that narrow issue is
contained, more exactly than would otherwise have been possible. With each step
more things can be let out of the pound; exact discussions can be made less
abstract, realistic discussions can be made less inexact than was possible at an
earlier stage.(4*)
Our first step towards studying the influences exerted by the element of time on
the relations between cost of production and value may well be to consider the
famous fiction of the "Stationary state" in which those influences would be but
little felt; and to contrast the results which would be found there with those
in the modern world.
This state obtains its name from the fact that in it the general conditions of
production and consumption, of distribution and exchange remain motionless; but
yet it is full of movement; for it is a mode of life. The average age of the
population may be stationary; though each individual is growing up from youth
towards his prime, or downwards to old age. And the same amount of things per
head of the population will have been produced in the same ways by the same
classes of people for many generations together; and therefore this supply of
the appliances for production will have had full time to be adjusted to the
steady demand.
Of course we might assume that in our stationary state every business remained
always of the same size, and with the same trade connection. But we need not go
so far as that; it will suffice to suppose that firms rise and fall, but that
the "representative" firm remains always of about the same size, as does the
representative tree of a virgin forest, and that therefore the economies
resulting from its own resources are constant: and since the aggregate volume of
production is constant, so also are those economies resulting from subsidiary
industries in the neighbourhood, etc. [That is, its internal and external
economies are both constant. The price, the expectation of which just induced
persons to enter the trade, must be sufficient to cover in the long run the cost
of building up a trade connection; and a proportionate share of it must be added
in to make up the total cost of production.]
In a stationary state then the plain rule would be that cost of production
governs value. Each effect would be attributable mainly to one cause; there
would not be much complex action and reaction between cause and effect. Each
element of cost would be governed by "natural" laws, subject to some control
from fixed custom. There would be no reflex influence of demand; no fundamental
difference between the immediate and the later effects of economic causes. There
would be no distinction between long-period and short-period normal value, at
all events if we supposed that in that monotonous world the harvests themselves
were uniform: for the representative firm being always of the same size, and
always doing the same class of business to the same extent and in the same way,
with no slack times, and no specially busy times, its normal expenses by which
the normal supply price is governed would be always the same. The demand lists
of prices would always be the same, and so would the supply lists; and normal
price would never vary.
But nothing of this is true in the world in which we live. Here every economic
force is constantly changing its action, under the influence of other forces
which are acting around it. Here changes in the volume of production, in its
methods, and in its cost are ever mutually modifying one another; they are
always affecting and being affected by the character and the extent of demand.
Further all these mutual influences take time to work themselves out, and, as a
rule, no two influences move at equal pace. In this world therefore every plain
and simple doctrine as to the relations between cost of production, demand and
value is necessarily false: and the greater the appearance of lucidity which is
given to it by skilful exposition, the more mischievous it is. A man is likely
to be a better economist if he trusts to his common sense, and practical
instincts, than if he professes to study the theory of value and is resolved to
find it easy.
3. The Stationary state has just been taken to be one in which population is
stationary. But nearly all its distinctive features may be exhibited in a place
where population and wealth are both growing, provided they are growing at about
the same rate, and there is no scarcity of land: and provided also the methods
of production and the conditions of trade change but little; and above all,
where the character of man himself is a constant quantity. For in such a state
by far the most important conditions of production and consumption, of exchange
and distribution will remain of the same quality, and in the same general
relations to one another, though they are all increasing in volume.(5*)
This relaxation of the rigid bonds of a purely stationary state brings us one
step nearer to the actual conditions of life: and by relaxing them still further
we get nearer still. We thus approach by gradual steps towards the difficult
problem of the interaction of countless economic causes. In the stationary state
all the conditions of production and consumption are reduced to rest: but less
violent assumptions are made by what is, not quite accurately, called the
statical method. By that method we fix our minds on some central point: we
suppose it for the time to be reduced to a stationary state; and we then study
in relation to it the forces that affect the things by which it is surrounded,
and any tendency there may be to equilibrium of these forces. A number of these
partial studies may lead the way towards a solution of problems too difficult to
be grasped at one effort.(6*)
4. We may roughly classify problems connected with fishing industries as those
which are affected by very quick changes, such as uncertainties of the weather;
or by changes of moderate length, such as the increased demand for fish caused
by the scarcity of meat during the year or two following a cattle plague; or
lastly, we may consider the great increase during a whole generation of the
demand for fish which might result from the rapid growth of a high-strung
artisan population making little use of their muscles.
The day to day oscillations of the price of fish resulting from uncertainties of
the weather, etc., are governed by practically the same causes in modern England
as in the supposed stationary state. The changes in the general economic
conditions around us are quick; but they are not quick enough to affect
perceptibly the short-period normal level about which the price fluctuates from
day to day: and they may be neglected [impounded in caeteris paribus] during a
study of such fluctuations.
Let us then pass on; and suppose a great increase in the general demand for
fish, such for instance as might arise from a disease affecting farm stock, by
which meat was made a dear and dangerous food for several years together. We now
impound fluctuations due to the weather in caeteris paribus, and neglect them
provisionally: they are so quick that they speedily obliterate one another, and
are therefore not important for problems of this class. And for the opposite
reason we neglect variations in the numbers of those who are brought up as
seafaring men: for these variations are too slow to produce much effect in the
year or two during which the scarcity of meat lasts. Having impounded these two
sets for the time, we give our full attention to such influences as the
inducements which good fishing wages will offer to sailors to stay in their
fishing homes for a year or two, instead of applying for work on a ship. We
consider what old fishing boats, and even vessels that were not specially made
for fishing, can be adapted and sent to fish for a year or two. The normal price
for any given daily supply of fish, which we are now seeking, is the price which
will quickly call into the fishing trade capital and labour enough to obtain
that supply in a day's fishing of average good fortune; the influence which the
price of fish will have upon capital and labour available in the fishing trade
being governed by rather narrow causes such as these. This new level about which
the price oscillates during these years of exceptionally great demand, will
obviously be higher than before. Here we see an illustration of the almost
universal law that the term Normal being taken to refer to a short period of
time an increase in the amount demanded raises the normal supply price. This law
is almost universal even as regards industries which in long periods follow the
tendency to increasing return.(7*)
But if we turn to consider the normal supply price with reference to a long
period of time, we shall find that it is governed by a different set of causes,
and with different results. For suppose that the disuse of meat causes a
permanent distaste for it, and that an increased demand for fish continues long
enough to enable the forces by which its supply is governed to work out their
action fully (of course oscillations from day to day and from year to year would
continue: but we may leave them on one side). The source of supply in the sea
might perhaps show signs of exhaustion, and the fishermen might have to resort
to more distant coasts v, and to deeper waters, Nature giving a Diminishing
Return to the increased application of capital and labour of a given order of
efficiency. On the other hand, those might turn out to be right who think that
man is responsible for but a very small part of the destruction of fish that is
constantly going on; and in that case a boat starting with equally good
appliances and an equally efficient crew would be likely to get nearly as good a
haul after the increase in the total volume of the fishing trade as before. In
any case the normal cost of equipping a good boat with an efficient crew would
certainly not be higher, and probably be a little lower after the trade had
settled down to its now increased dimensions than before. For since fishermen
require only trained aptitudes, and not any exceptional natural qualities, their
number could be increased in less than a generation to almost any extent that
was necessary to meet the demand; while the industries connected with building
boats, making nets, etc. being now on a larger scale would be organized more
thoroughly and economically. If therefore the waters of the sea showed no signs
of depletion of fish, an increased supply could be produced at a lower price
after a time sufficiently long to enable the normal action of economic causes to
work itself out: and, the term Normal being taken to refer to a long period of
time, the normal price of fish would decrease with an increase in demand.(8*)
Thus we may emphasize the distinction already made between average price and
normal price. An average may be taken of the prices of any set of sales
extending over a day or a week or a year or any other time: or it may be the
average of sales at any time in many markets; or it may be the average of many
such averages. But the conditions which are normal to any one set of sales are
not likely to be exactly those which are normal to the others: and therefore it
is only by accident that an average price will be a normal price; that is, the
price which any one set of conditions tends to produce. In a stationary state
alone, as we have just seen, the term normal always means the same thing: there,
but only there, "average price" and "normal price" are convertible terms.(9*)
5. To go over the ground in another way. Market values are governed by the
relation of demand to stocks actually in the market; with more or less reference
to "future" supplies, and not without some influence of trade combinations.
But the current supply is in itself partly due to the action of producers in the
past; and this action has been determined on as the result of a comparison of
the prices which they expect to get for their goods with the expenses to which
they will be put in producing them. The range of expenses of which they take
account depends on whether they are merely considering the extra expenses of
certain extra production with their existing plant, or are considering whether
to lay down new plant for the purpose. In the case, for instance, of an order
for a single locomotive, which was discussed a little while ago(10*), the
question of readjusting the plant to demand would hardly arise: the main
question would be whether more work could conveniently be got out of the
existing plant. But in view of an order for a large number of locomotives to be
delivered gradually over a series of years, some extension of plant "specially"
made for the Purpose, and therefore truly to be regarded as prime marginal costs
would almost certainly be carefully considered.
Whether the new production for which there appears to be a market be large or
small, the general rule will be that unless the price is expected to be very low
that portion of the supply which can be most easily produced, with but small
prime costs, will be produced: that portion is not likely to be on the margin of
production. As the expectations of price improve, an increased part of the
production will yield a considerable surplus above prime costs, and the margin
of production will be pushed outwards. Every increase in the price expected
will, as a rule, induce some people who would not otherwise have produced
anything, to produce a little; and those, who have produced something for the
lower price, will produce more for the higher price. That part of their
production with regard to which such persons are on the margin of doubt as to
whether it is worth while for them to produce it at the price, is to be included
together with that of the persons who are in doubt whether to produce at all;
the two together constitute the marginal production at that price. The
producers, who are in doubt whether to produce anything at all, may be said to
lie altogether on the margin of production (or) if they are agriculturists, on
the margin of cultivation). But as a rule they are very few in number, and their
action is less important than that of those who would in any case produce
something.
The general drift of the term normal supply price is always the same whether the
period to which it refers is short or long; but there are great differences in
detail. In every case reference is made to a certain given rate of aggregate
production; that is, to the production of a certain aggregate amount daily or
annually. In every case the price is that the expectation of which is sufficient
and only just sufficient to make it worth while for people to set themselves to
produce that aggregate amount; in every case the cost of production is marginal;
that is, it is the cost of production of those goods which are on the margin of
not being produced at all, and which would not be produced if the price to be
got for them were expected to be lower. But the causes which determine this
margin vary with the length of the period under consideration. For short periods
people take the stock of appliances for production as practically fixed; and
they are governed by their expectations of demand in considering how actively
they shall set themselves to work those appliances. In long periods they set
themselves to adjust the flow of these appliances to their expectations of
demand for the goods which the appliances help to produce. Let us examine this
difference closely.
6. The immediate effect of the expectation of a high price is to cause people to
bring into active work all their appliances of production, and to work them full
time and perhaps overtime. The supply price is then the money cost of production
of that part of the produce which forces the undertaker to hire such inefficient
labour (perhaps tired by working overtime) at so high a price, and to put
himself and others to so much strain and inconvenience that he is on the margin
of doubt whether it is worth his while to do it or not. The immediate effect of
the expectation of a low price is to throw many appliances for production out of
work, and slacken the work of others; and if the producers had no fear of
spoiling their markets, it would be worth their while to produce for a time for
any price that covered the prime costs of production and rewarded them for their
own trouble.
But, as it is, they generally hold out for a higher price; each man fears to
spoil his chance of getting a better price later on from his own customers; or,
if he produces for a large and open market, he is more or less in fear of
incurring the resentment of other producers, should he sell needlessly at a
price that spoils the common market for all. The marginal production in this
case is the production of those whom a little further fall of price would cause,
either from a regard to their own interest or by formal or informal agreement
with other producers, to suspend production for fear of further spoiling the
market. The price which, for these reasons, producers are just on the point of
refusing, is the true marginal supply price for short periods. It is nearly
always above, and generally very much above the special or prime cost for raw
materials, labour and wear-and-tear of plant, which is immediately and directly
involved by getting a little further use out of appliances which are not fully
employed. This point needs further study.
In a trade which uses very expensive plant, the prime cost of goods is but a
small part of their total cost; and an order at much less than their normal
price may leave a large surplus above their prime cost. But if producers accept
such orders in their anxiety to prevent their plant from being idle, they glut
the market and tend to prevent prices from reviving. In fact however they seldom
pursue this policy constantly and without moderation. If they did, they might
ruin many of those in the trade, themselves perhaps among the number; and in
that case a revival of demand would find little response in supply, and would
raise violently the prices of the goods produced by the trade. Extreme
variations of this kind are in the long run beneficial neither to producers nor
to consumers; and general opinion is not altogether hostile to that code of
trade morality which condemns the action of anyone who "spoils the market" by
being too ready to accept a price that does little more than cover the prime
cost of his goods, and allows but little on account of his general
expenses.(11*)
For example, if at any time the prime cost, in the narrowest sense of the word,
of a bale of cloth is £100; and if another £100 are needed to make the cloth pay
its due share of the general expenses of the establishment, including normal
profits to its owners, then the practically effective supply price is perhaps
not very likely to fall below £150 under ordinary conditions, even for short
periods; though of course a few special bargains may be made at lower prices
without much affecting the general market.
Thus, although nothing but prime cost enters necessarily and directly into the
supply price for short periods, it is yet true that supplementary costs also
exert some influence indirectly. A producer does not often isolate the cost of
each separate small parcel of his output; he is apt to treat a considerable part
of it, even in some cases the whole of it, more or less as a unit. He inquires
whether it is worth his while to add a certain new line to his present
undertakings, whether it is worth while to introduce a new machine and so on. He
treats the extra output that would result from the change more or less as a unit
beforehand; and afterwards he quotes the lowest prices, which he is willing to
accept, with more or less reference to the whole cost of that extra output
regarded as a unit.
In other words he regards an increase in his processes of production, rather
than an individual parcel of his products, as a unit in most of his
transactions. And the analytical economist must follow suit, if he would keep in
close touch with actual conditions. These considerations tend to blur the
sharpness of outline of the theory of value: but they do not affect its
substance.(12*)
To sum up then as regards short periods. The supply of specialized skill and
ability, of suitable machinery and other material capital, and of the
appropriate industrial organization has not time to be fully adapted to demand;
but the producers have to adjust their supply to the demand as best they can
with the appliances already at their disposal. On the one hand there is not time
materially to increase those appliances if the supply of them is deficient; and
on the other, if the supply is excessive, some of them must remain imperfectly
employed, since there is not time for the supply to be much reduced by gradual
decay, and by conversion to other uses. Variations in the particular income
derived from them do not for the time affect perceptibly the supply; and do not
directly affect the price of the commodities produced by them. The income is a
surplus of total receipts over prime cost; [that is, it has something of the
nature of a rent as will be seen more clearly in chapter VIII]. But unless it is
sufficient to cover in the long run a fair share of the general costs of the
business, production will gradually fall off. In this way a controlling
influence over the relatively quick movements of supply price during short
periods is exercised by causes in the background which range over a long period;
and the fear of "spoiling the market" often makes those causes act more promptly
than they otherwise would.
7. In long periods on the other hand all investments of capital and effort in
providing the material plant and the organization of a business, and in
acquiring trade knowledge and specialized ability, have time to be adjusted to
the incomes which are expected to be earned by them: and the estimates of those
incomes therefore directly govern supply, and are the true long-period normal
supply price of the commodities produced.
A great part of the capital invested in a business is generally spent on
building up its internal organization and its external trade connections. If the
business does not prosper all that capital is lost, even though its material
plant may realize a considerable part of its original cost. And anyone proposing
to start a new business in any trade must reckon for the chance of this loss. If
himself a man of normal capacity for that class of work, be may look forward ere
long to his business being a representative one, in the sense in which we have
used this term, with its fair share of the economies of production on a large
scale. If the net earnings of such a representative business seem likely to be
greater than he could get by similar investments in other trades to which he has
access, he will choose this trade. Thus that investment of capital in a trade,
on which the price of the commodity produced by it depends in the long run, is
governed by estimates on the one hand of the outgoings required to build up and
to work a representative firm, and on the other of the incomings, spread over a
long period of time, to be got by such a price.
At any particular moment some businesses will be rising and others falling: but
when we are taking a broad view of the causes which govern normal supply price,
we need not trouble ourselves with these eddies on the surface of the great
tide. Any particular increase of production may be due to some new manufacturer
who is struggling against difficulties, working with insufficient capital, and
enduring great privations in the hope that he may gradually build up a good
business. Or it may be due to some wealthy firm which by enlarging its premises
is enabled to attain new economies, and thus obtain a larger output at a lower
proportionate cost: and, as this additional output will be small relatively to
the aggregate volume of production in the trade, it will not much lower the
price; so that the firm will reap great gains from its successful adaptation to
its surroundings. But while these variations are occurring in the fortunes of
individual businesses, there may be a steady tendency of the long-period normal
supply price to diminish, as a direct consequence of an increase in the
aggregate volume of production.
8. Of course there is no hard and sharp line of division between "long" and
"short" periods. Nature has drawn no such lines in the economic conditions of
actual life; and in dealing with practical problems they are not wanted. Just as
we contrast civilized with uncivilized races, and establish many general
propositions about either group, though no hard and fast division can be drawn
between the two; so we contrast long and short periods without attempting any
rigid demarcation between them. If it is necessary for the purposes of any
particular argument to divide one case sharply from the other, it can be done by
a special interpretation clause: but the occasions on which this is necessary
are neither frequent nor important.
Four classes stand out. In each, price is governed by the relations between
demand and supply. As regards market prices, Supply is taken to mean the stock
of the commodity in question which is on hand, or at all events " in sight." As
regards normal prices, when the term Normal is taken to relate to short periods
of a few months or a year, supply means broadly what can be produced for the
price in question with the existing stock of plant, personal and impersonal, in
the given time. As regards normal prices, when the term Normal is to refer to
long periods of several years, Supply means what can be produced by plant, which
itself can be remuneratively produced and applied within the given time; while
lastly, there are very gradual or Secular movements of normal price, caused by
the gradual growth of knowledge, of population and of capital, and the changing
conditions of demand and supply from one generation to another.(13*)
The remainder of the present volume is chiefly concerned with the third of the
above classes: that is, with the normal relations of wages, profits, prices,
etc., for rather long periods. But occasionally account has to be taken of
changes that extend over very many years; and one chapter, Book VI, ch. XII, is
given up to "The Influence of Progress on Value," that is, to the study of
secular changes of value.
NOTES:
1. V, III, section 5.
2. There are indeed not many occasions on which the calculations of a business
man for practical purposes need to look forward so far, and to extend the range
of the term Normal over a whole generation: but in the broader applications of
economic science it is sometimes necessary to extend the range even further, and
to take account of the slow changes that in the course of centuries affect the
supply price of the labour of each industrial grade.
3. Compare I, II, section 7.
4. As has been explained in the Preface, pp. vi-ix, this volume is concerned
mainly with normal conditions; and these are sometimes described as Statical.
But in the opinion of the present writer the problem of normal value belongs to
economic Dynamics: partly because Statics is really but a branch of Dynamics,
and partly because all suggestions as to economic rest, of which the hypothesis
of a Stationary state is the chief, are merely provisional, used only to
illustrate particular steps in the argument, and to be thrown aside when that is
done.
5. See below, V, XII, section 3; and compare Keynes, Scope and Method of
Political Economy, VI, 2.
6. Compare the Preface and Appendix H, section 4.
7. See V, XII, section I.
8. Tooke (History of Prices, Vol. I, p. 104) tells us: "There are particular
articles of which the demand for naval and military purposes forms so large a
proportion to the total supply, that no diminution of consumption by individuals
can keep pace with the immediate increase of demand by government; and
consequently, the breaking out of a war tends to raise the price of such
articles to a great relative height. But even of such articles, if the
consumption were not on a progressive scale of increase so rapid that the
supply, with all the encourage ment of a relatively high price, could not keep
pace with the demand, the tendency is (supposing no impediment, natural or
artificial, to production or importation) to occasion such an increase of
quantity, as to reduce the price to nearly the same level as that from which it
had advanced. And accordingly it will be observed, by reference to the table of
prices, that salt petre, hemp, iron, etc., after advancing very considerably
under the influence of a greatly extended demand for military and naval
purposes, tended downwards again whenever that demand was not progressively and
rapidly increasing." Thus a continuously progressive increase in demand may
raise the supply price of a thing even for several years together; though a
steady increase of demand for that thing, at a rate not too great for supply to
keep pace with it, would lower price.
9. V, III, section 6. The distinction will be yet further discussed in V, XII
and Appendix H. See also Keynes, Scope and Method of Political Economy, ch. VII.
10. pp. 360-7.
11. Where there is a strong combination, tacit or overt, producers may sometimes
regulate the price for a considerable time together with very little reference
to cost of production. And if the leaders in that combination were those who had
the best facilities for production, it might be said, in apparent though not in
real contradiction to Ricardo's doctrines, that the price was governed by that
part of the supply which was most easily produced. But as a fact, those
producers whose finances are weakest, and who are bound to go on producing to
escape failure, often impose their policy on the rest of the combination:
insomuch that it is a common saying, both in America and England, that the
weakest members of a combination are frequently its rulers.
12. This general description may suffice for most purposes: but in chapter XII
there will be found a more detailed study of that extremely complex notion, a
marginal increment in the processes of production by a representative firm;
together with a fuller explanation of the necessity of referring our reasonings
to the circumstances of a representative firm, especially when we are
considering industries which show a tendency to increasing return.
13. Compare the first section of this chapter. Of course the periods required to
adapt the several factors of production to the demand may be very different; the
number of skilled compositors, for instance, cannot be increased nearly as fast
as the supply of type and printing presses. And this cause alone would prevent
any rigid division being made between long and short periods. But in fact a
theoretically perfect long period must give time enough to enable not only the
factors of production of the commodity to be adjusted to the demand, but also
the factors of production of those factors of production to be adjusted and so
on; and this, when carried to its logical consequences, will be found to involve
the supposition of a stationary state of industry, in which the requirements of
a future age can be anticipated an indefinite time beforehand. Some such
assumption is indeed unconsciously implied in many popular renderings of
Ricardo's theory of value, if not in his own versions of it; and it is to this
cause more than any other that we must attribute that simplicity and sharpness
of outline, from which the economic doctrines in fashion in the first half of
this century derived some of their seductive charm, as well as most of whatever
tendency they may have to lead to false practical conclusions.
Relatively short and long period problems go generally on similar lines. In both
use is made of that paramount device, the partial or total isolation for special
study of some set of relations. In both opportunity is gained for analysing and
comparing similar episodes, and making them throw light upon one another; and
for ordering and co-ordinating facts which are suggestive in their similarities,
and are still more suggestive in the differences that peer out through their
similarities. But there is a broad distinction between the two cases. In the
relatively short-period problem no great violence is needed for the assumption
that the forces not specially under consideration may be taken for the time to
be inactive. But violence is required for keeping broad forces in the pound of
Caeteris Paribus during, say, a whole generation, on the ground that they have
only an indirect bearing on the question in hand. For even indirect influences
may produce great effects in the course of a generation, if they happen to act
cumulatively; and it is not safe to ignore them even provisionally in a
practical problem without special study. Thus the uses of the statical method in
problems relating to very long periods are dangerous; care and forethought and
self-restraint are needed at every step. The difficulties and risks of the task
reach their highest point in connection with industries which conform to the law
of Increasing Return; and it is just in connection with those industries that
the most alluring applications of the method are to be found. We must postpone
these questions to chapter XII and Appendix H.
But an answer may be given here to the objection that since "the economic world
is subject to continual changes, and is becoming more complex,... the longer the
run the more hopeless the rectification": so that to speak of that position
which value tends to reach in the long run is to treat "variables as constants."
(Devas, Political Economy, Book IV, ch. v.) It is true that we do treat
variables provisionally as constants. But it is also true that this is the only
method by which science has ever made any great progress in dealing with complex
and changeful matter, whether in the physical or moral world. See above V, v,
section 2.
CHAPTER 6
JOINT AND COMPOSITE DEMAND. JOINT AND COMPOSITE SUPPLY
1. Bread satisfies man's wants directly: and the demand for it is said to be
direct. But a flour mill and an oven satisfy wants only indirectly, by helping
to make bread, etc., and the demand for them is said to be indirect. More
generally: --
The demand for raw materials and other means of production is indirect and is
derived from the direct demand for those directly serviceable products which
they help to produce.
The services of the flour mill and the oven are joined together in the ultimate
product, bread: the demand for them is therefore called a joint demand. Again,
hops and malt are complementary to one another; and are joined together in the
common destination of ale: and so on. Thus the demand for each of several
complementary things is derived from the services which they jointly render in
the production of some ultimate product, as for instance a loaf of bread, a cask
of ale. In other words there is a joint demand for the services which any of
these things render in helping to produce a thing which satisfies wants directly
and for which there is therefore a direct demand: the direct demand for the
finished product is in effect split up into many derived demands for the things
used in producing it.(1*)
To take another illustration, the direct demand for houses gives rise to a joint
demand for the labour of all the various building trades, and for bricks, stone,
wood, etc. which are factors of production of building work of all kinds, or as
we may say for shortness, of new houses. The demand for any one of these, as for
instance the labour of plasterers, is only an indirect or derived demand.
Let us pursue this last illustration with reference to a class of events that
are of frequent occurrence in the labour market; the period over which the
disturbance extends being short, and the causes of which we have to take account
as readjusting demand and supply being only such as are able to operate within
that short period.
This case has important practical bearings, which give it a special claim on our
attention; but we should notice that, referring as it does to short periods, it
is an exception to our general rule of selecting illustrations in this and the
neighbouring chapters from cases in which there is time enough for the full
long-period action of the forces of supply to be developed.
Let us then suppose that the supply and demand for building being in
equilibrium, there is a strike on the part of one group of workers, say the
plasterers, or that there is some other disturbance to the supply of plasterers'
labour. In order to isolate and make a separate study of the demand for that
factor, we suppose firstly that the general conditions of the demand for new
houses remain unchanged (that is, that the demand schedule for new houses
remains valid); and secondly we assume that there is no change in the general
conditions of supply of the other factors, two of which are of course the
business faculties and the business organizations of the master builders; (that
is, we assume that their lists of supply prices also remain valid). Then a
temporary check to the supply of plasterers' labour will cause a proportionate
check to the amount of building: the demand price for the diminished number of
houses will be a little higher than before; and the supply prices for the other
factors of production will not be greater than before.(2*) Thus new houses can
now be sold at prices which exceed by a good margin the sum of the prices at
which these other requisites for the production of houses can be bought; and
that margin gives the limit to the possible rise of the price that will be
offered for plasterers' labour, on the supposition that plasterers' labour is
indispensable. The different amounts of this margin, corresponding to different
checks to the supply of plasterers' labour, are governed by the general rule
that: The price that will be offered for any thing used in producing a commodity
is, for each separate amount of the commodity, limited by the excess of the
price at which that amount of the commodity can find purchasers, over the sum of
the prices at which the corresponding supplies of the other things needed for
making it will be forthcoming.
To use technical terms, the demand schedule for any factor of production of a
commodity can be derived from that for the commodity by subtracting from the
demand price of each separate amount of the commodity the sum of the supply
prices for corresponding amounts of the other factors.(3*)
2. When however we come to apply this theory to the actual conditions of life,
it will be important to remember that if the supply of one factor is disturbed,
the supply of others is likely to be disturbed also. In particular, when the
factor of which the supply is disturbed is one class of labour, as that of the
plasterers, the employers' earnings generally act as a buffer. That is to say,
the loss falls in the first instance on them; but by discharging some of their
workmen and lowering the wages of others, they ultimately distribute a great
part of it among the other factors of production. The details of the process by
which this is effected are various, and depend on the action of trade
combinations, on the higgling and bargaining of the market, and on other causes
with which we are not just at present concerned.
Let us inquire what are the conditions, under which a check to the supply of a
thing that is wanted not for direct use, but as a factor of production of some
commodity, may cause a very great rise in its price. The first condition is that
the factor itself should be essential, or nearly essential to the production of
the commodity, no good substitute being available at a moderate price.
The second condition is that the commodity in the production of which it is a
necessary factor, should be one for which the demand is stiff and inelastic; so
that a check to its supply will cause consumers to offer a much increased price
for it rather than go without it; and this of course includes the condition that
no good substitutes for the commodity are available at a price but little higher
than its equilibrium price. If the check to house building raises the price of
houses very much, builders, anxious to secure the exceptional profits, will bid
against one another for such plasterers' labour as there is in the market.(4*)
The third condition is that only a small part of the expenses of production of
the commodity should consist of the price of this factor. Since the plasterers'
wages are but a small part of the total expenses of building a house, a rise of
even 50 per cent in them would add but a very small percentage to the expenses
of production of a house and would check demand but little.(5*)
The fourth condition is that even a small check to amount demanded should cause
a considerable fall in the supply prices of other factors of production; as that
will increase the margin available for paying a high price for this one.(6*) If,
for instance, bricklayers and other classes of workmen, or the employers
themselves cannot easily find other things to do, and cannot afford to remain
idle, they may be willing to work for much lower earnings than before, and this
will increase the margin available for paying higher wages to plasterers. These
four conditions are independent, and the effects of the last three are
cumulative.
The rise in plasterers' wages would be checked if it were possible either to
avoid the use of plaster, or to get the work done tolerably well and at a
moderate price by people outside the plasterers' trade: the tyranny, which one
factor of production of a commodity might in some cases exercise over the other
factors through the action of derived demand, is tempered by the principle of
substitution.(7*)
Again, an increased difficulty in obtaining one of the factors of a finished
commodity can often be met by modifying the character of the finished product.
Some plasterers' labour may be indispensable; but people are often in doubt how
much plaster work it is worth while to have in their houses, and if there is a
rise in its price they will have less of it. The intensity of the satisfaction
of which they would be deprived if they had a little less of it, is its marginal
utility; the price which they are just willing to pay in order to have it, is
the true demand price for plasterers' work up to the amount which is being used.
So again there is a joint demand for malt and hops in ale. But their proportions
can be varied. A higher price can be got for an ale which differs from others
only in containing more hops; and this excess price represents the demand for
hops.(8*)
The relations between plasterers, bricklayers, etc., are representative of much
that is both instructive and romantic in the history of alliances and conflicts
between trades-unions in allied trades. But the most numerous instances of joint
demand are those of the demand for a raw material and the operatives who work it
up; as for instance cotton or jute or iron or copper, and those who work up
these several materials. Again, the relative prices of different articles of
food vary a good deal with the supply of skilled cooks' labour: thus for
instance many kinds of meat and many parts of vegetables which are almost
valueless in America, where skilled cooks are rare and expensive, have a good
value in France, where the art of cooking is widely diffused.
3. We have already(9*) discussed the way in which the aggregate demand for any
commodity is compounded of the demands of the different groups of people who may
need it. But we now may extend this notion of composite demand to requisites of
production which are needed by several groups of producers.
Nearly every raw material and nearly every kind of labour is applied in many
different branches of industry, and contributes to the production of a great
variety of commodities. Each of these commodities has its own direct demand; and
from that the derived demand for any of the things used in making it can be
found, and the thing is "distributed between its various uses" in the manner
which we have already discussed.(10*) The various uses are rivals, or
competitors with one another; and the corresponding derived demands are rival or
competitive demands relatively to one another. But in relation to the supply of
the product, they co-operate with one another; being "compounded" into the total
demand that carries off the supply: in just the same way as the partial demands
of several classes of society for a finished commodity are aggregated, or
compounded together into the total demand for it.(11*)
4. We may now pass to consider the case of joint products: i.e. of things which
cannot easily be produced separately; but are joined in a common origin, and may
therefore be said to have a joint supply, such as beef and hides, or wheat and
straw.(12*) This case corresponds to that of things which have a joint demand,
and it may be discussed almost in the same words, by merely substituting
"demand" for "supply," and vice versa. As there is a joint demand for things
joined in a common destination: so there is a joint supply of things which have
a common origin. The single supply of the common origin is split up into so many
derived supplies of the things that proceed from it.(13*)
For instance, since the repeal of the Corn Laws much of the wheat consumed in
England has been imported, of course without any straw. This has caused a
scarcity and a consequent rise in the price of straw, and the farmer who grows
wheat looks to the straw for a great part of the value of the crop. The value of
straw then is high in countries which import wheat, and low in those which
export wheat. In the same way the price of mutton in the wool-producing
districts of Australia was at one time very low. The wool was exported, the meat
had to be consumed at home; and as there was no great demand for it, the price
of the wool had to defray almost the whole of the joint expenses of production
of the wool and the meat. Afterwards the low price of meat gave a stimulus to
the industries of preserving meat for exportation, and now its price in
Australia is higher.
There are very few cases of joint products the cost of production of both of
which together is exactly the same as that of one of them alone. So long as any
product of a business has a market value, it is almost sure to have devoted to
it some special care and expense, which would be diminished, or dispensed with
if the demand for that product were to fall very much. Thus, for instance, if
straw were valueless, farmers would exert themselves more than they do to make
the ear bear as large a proportion as possible to the stalk. Again, the
importation of foreign wool has caused English sheep to be adapted by judicious
crossing and selection so as to develop heavy weights of good meat at an early
age, even at the expense of some deterioration of their wool. It is only when
one of two things produced by the same process is valueless, unsaleable, and yet
does not involve any expense for its removal, that there is no inducement to
attempt to alter its amount; and, it is only in these exceptional cases that we
have no means of assigning its separate supply price to each of the joint
products. For when it is possible to modify the proportions of these products,
we can ascertain what part of the whole expense of the process of production
would be saved, by so modifying these proportions as slightly to diminish the
amount of one of the joint products without affecting the amounts of the others.
That part of the expense is the expense of production of the marginal element of
that product; it is the supply price of which we are in search.(14*)
But these are exceptional cases. It more frequently happens that a business, or
even an industry finds its advantage in using a good deal of the same plant,
technical skill, and business organization for several classes of products. In
such cases the cost of anything used for several purposes has to be defrayed by
its fruits in all of them: but there is seldom any rule of nature to determine
either the relative importance of these uses, or the proportions in which the
total cost should be distributed among them: much depends on the changing
features of markets.(15*)
5. We may pass to the problem of composite supply which is analogous to that of
composite demand. A demand can often be satisfied by any one of several routes,
according to the principle of substitution. These various routes are rivals or
competitors with one another; and the corresponding supplies of commodities are
rival, or competitive supplies relatively to one another. But in relation to the
demand they co-operate with one another; being "compounded" into the total
supply that meets the demands.(16*)
If the causes which govern their production are nearly the same, they may for
many purposes be treated as one commodity.(17*) For instance, beef and mutton
may be treated as varieties of one commodity for many purposes; but they must be
treated as separate for others, as for instance for those in which the question
of the supply of wool enters. Rival things are however often not finished
commodities, but factors of production: for instance, there are many rival
fibres which are used in making ordinary printing paper. We have just noticed
how the fierce action of derived demand for one of several complementary
supplies, as e.g. for the supply of plasterers' labour, was liable to be
moderated, when the demand was met by the competitive supply of a rival thing,
which could be substituted for it.(18*)
6. All the four chief problems which have been discussed in this chapter have
some bearing on the causes that govern the value of almost every commodity: and
many of the most important cross connections between the values of different
commodities are not obvious at first sight.
Thus when charcoal was generally used in making iron, the price of leather
depended in some measure on that of iron; and the tanners petitioned for the
exclusion of foreign iron in order that the demand on the part of English iron
smelters for oak charcoal might cause the production of English oak to be kept
up, and thus prevent oak bark from becoming dear.(19*) This instance may serve
to remind us of the way in which an excessive demand for a thing may cause its
sources of supply to be destroyed, and thus render scarce any joint products
that it may have: for the demand for wood on the part of the ironmakers led to a
relentless destruction of many forests in England. Again, an excessive demand
for lamb was assigned as a cause of the prevailing scarcity of sheep some years
ago; while some argued on the contrary that the better the price to be got for
spring lamb sold to the rich, the more profitable would be the production of
sheep, and the cheaper would mutton be for the people. The fact is that an
increase of demand may have opposite effects according as it does or does not
act so suddenly as to prevent producers from adapting their action to it.
Again, the development of railways and other means of communication for the
benefit of one trade, as for instance wheat growing in some parts of America and
silver mining in others, greatly lowers some of the chief expenses of production
of nearly every other product of those districts. Again, the prices of soda, and
bleaching materials and other products of industries, the chief raw material of
which is salt, move up and down relatively to one another with almost every
improvement in the various processes which are used in those industries; and
every change in those prices affects the prices of many other goods, for the
various products of the salt industries are more or less important factors in
many branches of manufacture.
Again, cotton and cotton-seed oil are joint products, and the recent fall in the
price of cotton is largely due to the improved manufacture and uses of
cotton-seed oil: and further, as the history of the cotton famine shows, the
price of cotton largely affects that of wool, linen and other things of its own
class; while cotton-seed oil is ever opening up new rivalries with things of its
own class. Again, many new uses have been found for straw in manufacture; and
these inventions are giving value to straw that used to be burnt in the West of
America, and tend to hinder the rise in the marginal cost of producing
wheat.(20*)
NOTES:
1. Compare III, III, section 6. It will be recollected that the things in a form
ready for immediate use have been called goods of the first order, or consumers'
goods; and that things used as factors of production of other goods have been
called producers' goods, or goods of the second and higher orders or
intermediate goods: also that it is difficult to say when goods are really
finished; that many things are commonly treated as finished consumers' goods
before they are really ready for consumption, e.g. flour. See II, iii, section
I. The vagueness of the notion of instrumental goods, regarded as things the
value of which is derived from that of their products, is indicated in Appendix
E, section 3.
2. This is at any rate true under all ordinary conditions: there will be less
extra charges for overtime; and the price of the labour of carpenters,
bricklayers and others is likely rather to go down than to go up, and the same
is true of brick and other building materials.
3. The broad account given in the text may suffice for most purposes; and the
general reader should perhaps omit the remaining footnotes to this chapter.
It must be remembered that this Derived schedule has no validity except on the
suppositions that we are isolating this one factor for separate study; that its
own conditions of supply are disturbed; that there is at the time no independent
disturbance affecting any other element in the problem; and that therefore in
the case of each of the other factors of production the selling price may be
taken to coincide always with the supply price.
In illustrating this by a diagram, it will be well, for the sake of shortness of
wording, to divide the expenses of production of a commodity into the supply
prices of two things of which it is made; let us then regard the supply price of
a knife as the sum of the supply prices of its blade and handle, and neglect the
expense of putting the two together. Let ss' be the supply curve for handles and
SS' that for knives; so that M being any point on Ox, and MqQ being drawn
vertically to cut ss'. in q and SS' in Q, Mq is the supply price for OM handles,
qQ is the supply price for OM blades and MQ the supply price for OM knives. Let
DD' the demand curve for knives cut SS' in A, and AaB be drawn vertically as in
the figure. Then in equilibrium OB knives are sold at a price BA of which Ba
goes for the handle and aA for the blade.
(In this illustration we may suppose that sufficient time is allowed to enable
the forces which govern supply price to work themselves out fully; and we are at
liberty therefore to make our supply curves inclined negatively. This change
will not affect the argument; but on the whole it is best to take our typical
instance with the supply curve inclined positively.)
Now let us suppose that we want to isolate for separate study the demand for
knife handles. Accordingly we suppose that the demand for knives and the supply
of blades conform to the laws indicated by their respective curves: also that
the supply curve for handles still remains in force and represents the
circumstances of normal supply for handles, although the supply of handles is
temporarily disturbed. Let MQ cut DD' in P, then MP is the demand price for OM
knives and Qq is the supply price for OM blades. Take a point p in MP such that
Pp is equal to Qq, and therefore Mp is the excess of MP over Qq; then Mp is the
demand price for OM handles. Let dd' be the locus of p obtained by giving M
successive positions along Ox and finding the corresponding positions of p; then
dd' is the derived demand curve for handles. Of course it passes through a. We
may now neglect all the rest of the figure except the curves dd', ss'; and
regard them as representing the relations of demand for and supply of handles,
other things being equal, that is to say, in the absence of any disturbing cause
which affects the law of supply of blades and the law of demand for knives. Ba
is then the equilibrium price of handles, about which the market price
oscillates, in the manner investigated in the preceding chapter, under the
influence of demand and supply, of which the schedules are represented by dd'
and ss' It has already been remarked that the ordinary demand and supply curves
have no practical value except in the immediate neighbourhood of the point of
equilibrium. And the same remark applies with even greater force to the equation
of derived demand.
[Since Mp Mq = MP - MQ; therefore A being a point of stable equilibrium, the
equilibrium at a also is stable. But this statement needs to be somewhat
qualified if the supply curves are negatively inclined: see Appendix H.]
In the illustration that has just been worked out the unit of each of the
factors remains unchanged whatever be the amount of the commodity produced; for
one blade and one handle are always required for each knife; but when a change
in the amount of the commodity produced occasions a change in the amount of each
factor that is required for the production of a unit of the commodity, the
demand and supply curves for the factor got by the above process are not
expressed in terms of fixed units of the factor. They must be translated back
into fixed units before they are available for general use. (See Mathematical
Note XIV bis.)
4. We have to inquire under what conditions the ratio pM to aB will be the
greatest, pM being the demand price for the factor in question corresponding to
a supply reduced from OB to OM, that is reduced by the given amount BM. The
second condition is that PM should be large; and since the elasticity of demand
is measured by the ratio which BM bears to the excess of PM over AB, the greater
PM is, the smaller, other things being equal, is the elasticity of demand.
5. The third condition is that when PM exceeds AB in a given ratio, pM shall be
caused to exceed Ba in a large ratio: and other things being equal, that
requires Ba to be but a small part of BA.
6. That is, if Qq had been smaller than it is, Pp would have been smaller and Mp
would have been larger. See also Mathematical Note XV .
7. It is shown in Böhm Bawerk's excellent Grundzüge der Theorie des
wirtschaftlichen Güterwerts (Jahrbuch für Natoonaiökonomie und Statistik, vol.
XIII, p. 59) that if all but one of the factors of production of a commodity
have available substitutes in unlimited supply, by which their own price is
rigidly fixed, the derived demand price for the remaining factor will be the
excess of the demand price for the finished product over the sum of the supply
prices thus fixed for the remaining factors. This is an interesting special case
of the law given in the text .
8. See Mathematical Note XVI.
9. See above, III, IV, sections 2, 4.
10. See III, v.
11. Thus, let a factor of production have three uses. Let d1d1' be the demand
curve for it in its first use. From N any point on Oy draw Np1 horizontally to
cut d1d1' in p1; then Np1 is the amount that is demanded for the first use at
price ON . Produce Np1 to p2, and further on to P making p1p2 and p2P of such
lengths as to represent the amounts of the factor demanded at price ON for the
second and third uses respectively. As N moves along Oy let p2 trace out the
curve d2d2' and let P trace out the curve DD'. Thus d2d2' would be the demand
curve for the factor if it had only its first and second uses. DD' is its demand
curve for all three uses. It is immaterial in what order we take the several
uses. In the case represented, the demand for the second use begins at a lower
price and that for the third use begins at a higher price than does the demand
for the first use. (See Mathematical Note XVII.)
12. Professor Dewsnup (American Economic Review, Supplement 1914, p. 89)
suggests that things should be described as joint products, when their "total
costs of production by a single plant are less than the sum of the costs of
their production by separate plants." This definition is less general than that
reached at the end of this section; but it is convenient for some special uses.
13. If it is desired to isolate the relations of demand and supply for a joint
product, the derived supply price is found in just the same way as the derived
demand price for a factor of production was found in the parallel case of
demand. Other things must be assumed to be equal (that is, the supply schedule
for the whole process of production must be assumed to remain in force and so
must the demand schedule for each of the joint products except that to be
isolated). The derived supply price is then found by the rule that it must equal
the excess of the supply price for the whole process of production over the sum
of the demand prices of all the other joint products; the prices being taken
throughout with reference to corresponding amounts.
We must again illustrate by a simple example in which it is assumed that the
relative amounts of the two joint products are unalterable. Let SS' be the
supply curve for bullocks which yield meat and leather in fixed quantities; dd'
the demand curve for their carcases, that is, for the meat derived from them. M
being any point on Ox draw Mp vertically to cut dd' in p, and produce it to P so
that pP represents the demand price for OM hides. Then MP is the demand price
for OM bullocks, and DD' the locus of P is the demand curve for bullocks: it may
be called the total demand curve. Let DD' cut SS' in A; and draw AaB as in the
figure. Then in equilibrium OB bullocks are produced and sold at the price BA of
which Ba goes for the carcase and aA for the hide.
Let MP cut SS' in Q. From QM cut off Qq equal to Pp; then q is a point on the
derived supply curve for carcases. For if we assume that the selling price of OM
hides is always equal to the corresponding demand price Pp, it follows that
since it costs QM to produce each of OM bullocks there remains a price QM Pp,
that is qM, to be borne by each of the OM carcases. Then ss' the locus of q, and
yy' are the supply and demand curves for carcases. (See Mathematical Note
XVIII.)
14. See Mathematical Note XIX.
15. A little more is said on this subject in the next chapter: it is discussed
fully in the forthcoming work on Industry and Trade.
16. The latter phrase "competing commodities" is used by Prof. Fisher in his
brilliant Mathematical Investigations in the Theory of Value and Prices, which
throw much light on the subjects discussed in the present chapter.
17. Comp. Jevons, l. c. pp. 145-6. See also above, footnotes on pp. 100, 105.
18. The want which all the rivals tend to satisfy is met by a composite supply,
the total supply at any price being the sum of the partial supplies at that
price.
Thus, for instance, N being any point on Oy draw Nq1q2Q parallel to Ox such that
Nq1' q1q2 and q2Q are respectively the amounts of the irst, second and third of
those rivals which can be supplied at the price ON. Then NQ is the total
composite supply at that price, and the locus of Q is the total supply curve of
the means of satisfying the want in question. Of course the units of the several
things which are rivals must be so taken that each of them satisfies the same
amount of the want. In the case represented in the figure small quantities of
the first rival can be put on the market at a price too low to call forth any
supply of the other two, and small quantities of the second at a price too low
to call forth any of the third. (See Mathematical Note XX.)
Continued rivalry is as a rule possible only when none of the rivals has its
supply governed by the law of increasing return. The equilibrium is stable only
when none of them is able to drive the others out; and this is the case when all
of them conform to the law of diminishing return; because then if one did obtain
a temporary advantage and its use increased, its supply price would rise, and
then the others would begin to undersell it. But if one of them conformed to the
law of increasing return, the rivalry would soon cease; for whenever it happened
to gain a temporary advantage over its rivals its increased use would lower its
supply price and therefore increase its saleits supply price would then be
further lowered, and so on: thus its advantage over its rivals would be
continually increased until it had driven them out of the field. It is true that
there are apparent exceptions to this rule; and things which conform to the law
of increasing return do sometimes seem to remain for a long time in the field as
rivals: such is the case perhaps with different kinds of sewing machines and of
electric lights. But in these cases the things do not really satisfy the same
wants, they appeal to slightly different needs or tastes; there is still some
difference of opinion as to their relative merits; or else perhaps some of them
are patented or in some other way have become the monopoly of particular firms.
In such cases custom and the force of advertising may keep many rivals in the
field for a long time; particularly if the producers of those things which are
really the best in proportion to their expenses of production are not able
effectively to advertise and push their wares by travellers and other agencies.
19. Toynbee (Industrial Revolution, p. 80).
20. Again, since sheep and oxen compete for the use of land, leather and cloth
compete in indirect demand for the use of a factor of production. But also in
the upholsterer's shop they compete as supplying means for meeting the same
want. There is thus a composite demand on the part of upholsterer and shoemaker
for leather. and also for cloth when the upper part of a shoe is made of cloth:
the shoe offers a joint demand for cloth and leather, they offering
complementary supplies: and so on, in endless complications. See Mathematical
Note XXI. The Austrian doctrine of "imputed value" has something in common with
that of derived value given in this chapter. Whichever phrase be used, it is
important that we should recognize the continuity between the old doctrine of
value and the new; and that we should treat imputed or derived values merely as
elements which take their place with many others in the broad problem of
distribution and exchange. The new phrases merely give the means of applying to
the ordinary affairs of life, some of that precision of _expression which is the
special property of mathematical language. Producers have alw.ays to consider
how the demand for any raw material in which they are interested is dependent on
the demand for the things in making which it is used, and how it is influenced
by every change that affects them; and this is really a special case of the
problem of ascertaining the efficient strength of any one of the forces, which
contribute to a common result. In mathematical language this common result is
called a function of the various forces: and the (marginal) contribution, which
any of them is making to it, is represented by the (small) change in the result
which would result from a (small) change in that force; that is by the
differential coefficient of the result with regard to that force. In other
words, the imputed value, or the derived value of a factor of production, if
used for only one product, is the differential coefficient of that product with
regard to that factor; and so on in successive complications, as indicated in
Notes XIV-XXI of the Mathematical Appendix. (Some objections to parts of Prof.
Wieser's doctrine of imputed values are well urged by Prof. Edgeworth, Economic
Journal, Vol. v, pp. 279-85.)
CHAPTER 7
PRIME AND TOTAL COST IN RELATION TO JOINT PRODUCTS.
COST OF MARKETING.
INSURANCE AGAINST RISK.
COST OF PRODUCTION
1. We may now return to the consideration of prime and supplementary costs, with
special reference to the proper distribution of the latter between the joint
products of a business.
It often happens that a thing made in one branch of a business is used as a raw
material in another, and then the question of the relative profitableness of the
two branches can be accurately ascertained only by an elaborate system of
book-keeping by double entry; though in practice it is more common to rely on
rough estimates made by an almost instinctive guess. Some of the best
illustrations of this difficulty are found in agriculture, especially when the
same farm combines permanent pasture and arable land worked on long
rotation.(1*)
Another difficult case is that of the shipowner who has to apportion the
expenses of his ship between heavy goods and goods that are bulky but not heavy.
He tries, as far as may be, to get a mixed cargo of both kinds; and an important
element in the struggle for existence of rival ports is the disadvantage under
which those ports lie which are able to offer a cargo only of bulky or only of
heavy goods: while a port whose chief exports are weighty but not bulky,
attracts to its neighbourhood industries which make for export goods that can be
shipped from it at low freights. The Staffordshire Potteries, for example, owe
part of their success to the low freights at which their goods are carried by
ships sailing from the Mersey with iron and other heavy cargoes.
But there is free competition in the shipowning trade, and it has great powers
of variation as regards the size and shape of ships, the routes which they take,
and the whole method of trading; and thus in many ways the general principle can
be applied, that the relative proportions of the joint products of a business
should be so modified that the marginal expenses of production of either product
should be equal to its marginal demand price.(2*) Or, in other words, the amount
of carrying power for each kind of cargo has a constant tendency to move towards
equilibrium at a point at which the demand price for that amount in a normal
state of trade is just sufficient to cover the expenses of providing it; these
expenses being reckoned so as to include not only its (money) prime cost, but
also all those general expenses of the business which are in the long run
incurred on its account, whether directly or indirectly.(3*)
In some branches of manufacture it is customary to make a first approximation to
the total cost of producing any class of goods, by assuming that their share of
the general expenses of the business is proportionate either to their prime
cost, or to the special labour bill that is incurred in making them. Corrections
can then be made to meet such cases as those of goods which require either more
or less than an average share of space or light, or of the use of expensive
machinery; and so on.
2. There are two elements of the general a business, the sharing of which
between the different requires some special attention. They are the expense
marketing and that of insurance against risk. Some kinds of goods are easily
marketed; there is steady demand for them, and it is always safe to make them
for stock. But for that very reason competition cuts their price "very fine,"
and does not allow a large margin above the direct cost of making them.
Sometimes the tasks of making and selling them can be rendered almost automatic,
so as to require very little to be charged on their account under the heads of
the expenses of management and marketing. But in practice it is not uncommon to
charge such goods with even less than the small share that would properly fall
to them, and to use them as a means of obtaining and maintaining a business
connection, that will facilitate the marketing of other classes of goods, the
production of which cannot so well be reduced to routine; for as to these there
is not so close a competition. Manufacturers, especially in trades connected
with furniture and dress, and retailers in almost all trades, frequently find it
best to use certain of their goods as a means of advertising others, and to
charge the first with less and the second with more than their proportionate
share of supplementary expenses. In the former class they put those goods which
are so uniform in character and so largely consumed that nearly all purchasers
know their value well, in the second those with regard to which purchasers think
more of consulting their fancy than of buying at the lowest possible price.
All difficulties of this kind are much increased by that instability of supply
price, which results whenever the tendency to increasing return is acting
strongly. We have seen that in seeking the normal supply price in such cases we
must select as representative a business which is managed with normal ability
and so as to get its fair share of the economies, both internal and external,
resulting from industrial organization: also that these economies, though they
fluctuate with the fortunes of particular businesses, yet increase generally
when the aggregate production increases. Now it is obvious that if a
manufacturer makes a commodity the increased production of which would put
largely increased internal economies within his reach, it is worth his while to
sacrifice a great deal in order to push its sales in a new market. If he has a
large capital, and the commodity is one in much demand, his expenditure for this
purpose may be very great, even exceeding that which he devotes directly to the
manufacture: and if, as is likely, he is pushing at the same time several other
commodities, nothing more than a very rough guess can be made as to what share
of this expenditure should be charged to the sales of each of them in the
current year, and what share should be charged to the connection which he is
endeavouring to build up for them in the future.
In fact when the production of a commodity conforms to the law of increasing
return in such a way as to give a very great advantage to large producers, it is
apt to fall almost entirely into the hands of a few large firms; and then the
normal marginal supply price cannot be isolated on the plan just referred to,
because that plan assumes the existence of a great many competitors with
businesses of all sizes, some of them being young and some old, some in the
ascending and some in the descending phase. The production of such a commodity
really partakes in a great measure of the nature of a monopoly; and its price is
likely to be so much influenced by the incidents of the campaign between rival
producers, each struggling for an extension of territory, as scarcely to have a
true normal level.
Economic progress is constantly offering new facilities for marketing goods at a
distance: it not only lowers cost of carriage, but what is often more important,
it enables producers and consumers in distant places to get in touch with one
another. In spite of this, the advantages of the producer who lives on the spot
are very great in many trades; they often enable him to hold his own against
competitors at a distance whose methods of production are more economical. He
can sell in his own neighbourhood as cheaply as they can, because though the
cost of making is greater for his goods than for theirs, he escapes much of the
cost which they incur for marketing. But time is on the side of the more
economic methods of production; his distant competitors will gradually get a
stronger footing in the place, unless he or some new man adopts their improved
methods.
It remains to make a closer study of the relation in which insurance against the
risks of a business stands to the supply price of any particular commodity
produced in it.
3. The manufacturer and the trader commonly insure against injury by fire and
loss at sea; and the premiums which they pay are among the general expenses, a
share of which has to be added to the prime cost in order to determine the total
cost of their goods. But no insurance can be effected against the great majority
of business risks.
Even as regards losses by fire and sea, insurance companies have to allow for
possible carelessness and fraud; and must therefore, independently of all
allowances for their own expenses and profits, charge premiums considerably
higher than the true equivalent of the risks run by the buildings or the ships
of those who manage their affairs well. The injury done by fire or sea however
is likely, if it occurs at all, to be so very great that it is generally worth
while to pay this extra charge; partly for special trade reasons, but chiefly
because the total utility of increasing wealth increases less than in proportion
to its amount. But the greater part of business risks are so inseparably
connected with the general management of the business that an insurance company
which undertook them would really make itself responsible for the business: and
in consequence every firm has to act as its own insurance office with regard to
them. The charges to which it is put under this head are part of its general
expenses, and a share of them has to be added to the prime cost of each of its
products.
But here there are two difficulties. In some cases insurance against risk is apt
to be left out of account altogether, in others it is apt to be counted twice
over. Thus a large shipowner sometimes declines to insure his ships with the
underwriters: and sets aside part at least of the premiums that he might have
paid to them, to build up an insurance fund of his own. But he must still, when
calculating the total cost of working a ship, add to its prime cost a charge on
account of insurance. And he must do the same thing, in some form or other, with
regard to those risks against which he could not buy an insurance policy on
reasonable terms even if he wanted to. At times, for instance, some of his ships
will be idle in port, or will earn only nominal freights: and to make his
business remunerative in the long run he must, in some form or other, charge his
successful voyages with an insurance premium to make up for his losses on those
which are unsuccessful.
In general, however, he does this, not by making a formal entry in his accounts
under a separate head, but by the simple plan of taking the average of
successful and unsuccessful voyages together; and when that has once been done,
insurance against these risks cannot be entered as a separate item in cost of
production, without counting the same thing twice over. Having decided to run
these risks himself, he is likely to spend a little more than the average of his
competitors, in providing against their occurrence; and this extra expense
enters in the ordinary way into his balance-sheet. It is really an insurance
premium in another form; and therefore he must not count insurance against this
part of the risk separately, for then he would be counting it twice over.(4*)
When a manufacturer has taken the average of his sales of dress materials over a
long time, and bases his future action on the results of his past experience, he
has already allowed for the risk that the machinery will be depreciated by new
inventions rendering it nearly obsolete, and for the risk that his goods will be
depreciated by changes in fashion. If he were to allow separately for insurance
against these risks, he would be counting the same thin twice over.(5*)
4. Thus, though when we have counted up the average receipts of a risky trade,
we must not make a separate full allowance for insurance against risk; though
there may be something to be allowed as a charge on account of uncertainty. It
is true that an adventurous occupation, such as gold mining, has special
attractions for some people: the deterrent force of risks of loss in it is less
than the attractive force of chances of great gain, even when the value of the
latter estimated on the actuarial principle is much less than that of the
former; and as Adam Smith pointed out, a risky trade, in which there is an
element of romance, often becomes so overcrowded that the average earnings in it
are lower than if there were no risks to be run.(6*) But in the large majority
of cases the influence of risk is in the opposite direction; a railway stock
that is certain to pay four per cent. will sell for a higher price than one
which is equally likely to pay one or seven per cent. or any intermediate
amount.
Every trade then has its own peculiarities, but in most cases the evils of
uncertainty count for something, though not very much: in some cases a slightly
higher average price is required to induce a given outlay, if that average is
the mean of widely divergent and uncertain results, than if the adventurer may
reckon confidently on a return that differs but little from that average. To the
average price therefore we must add a recompense for uncertainty, if that is
unusually great; though if we added insurance against risk we should be counting
the greater part of that twice over.(7*)
5. This discussion of the risks of trade has again brought before us the fact
that the value of a thing, though it tends to equal its normal (money) cost of
production, does not coincide with it at any particular time, save by accident.
Carey, observing this, suggested that we should speak of value in relation to
(money) cost of reproduction instead of in relation to cost of production.
The suggestion has, however, no significance so far as normal values are
concerned. For normal cost of production and normal cost of reproduction are
convertible terms; and no real change is made by saying that the normal value of
a thing tends to equal its normal (money) cost of reproduction instead of its
normal (money) cost of production. The former phrase is less simple than the
latter, but means the same thing.
And no valid argument for the change can be founded on the fact, which may be
readily admitted, that there are some few cases in which the market value of a
thing is nearer its cost of reproduction than the cost that was actually
incurred in producing that particular thing. The present price of an iron ship
for instance, made before the great recent improvements in the manufacture of
iron, might diverge less from the cost of reproducing it, that is of producing
another just like it by modern methods, than from that which was actually
incurred in producing it. But the price of the old ship would be less than the
cost of reproduction of the ship, because the art of designing ships has
improved as fast as that of manufacturing iron; and moreover steel has displaced
iron as the material of shipbuilding. It may still be urged that the price of
the ship is equal to that of producing a ship, which would be equally
serviceable, on a modern plan and by modern methods. But that would not be the
same thing as saying that the value of the ship is equal to its cost of
reproduction; and, as a matter of fact, when, as often happens, an unexpected
scarcity of ships causes freights to increase very rapidly, those who are
anxious to reap the harvest of profitable trade, will pay for a ship in sailing
order a price much above that for which a shipbuilding firm would contract to
produce another equally good and deliver it some time hence. Cost of
reproduction influence on value, save when purchasers can wait for the
production of new supplies.
Again, there is no connection between cost of reproduction and price in the
cases of food in a beleaguered city, of quinine the supply of which has run
short in a fever-stricken island, of a picture by Raphael, of a book that nobody
cares to read, of an armour-clad ship of obsolete pattern, of fish when the
market is glutted, of fish when the market is nearly empty, of a cracked bell,
of a dress material that has gone out of fashion, or of a house in a deserted
mining village.
####
The reader, unless already experienced in economic analysis, is recommended to
omit the next seven chapters, and pass at once to Chapter XV, which contains a
brief summary of this Book. It is true that the four chapters on marginal costs
in relation to values, and especially Chapters VIII and IX, bear upon some
difficulties which are latent in the phrase "the net product of labour"; and
that this phrase is used in Book VI. But the broad explanation of it given there
will suffice provisionally for most purposes; and the intricacies connected with
it may be best appreciated at a somewhat advanced stage of economic studies.
NOTES:
1. There is scope for applications of mathematical or semi-mathematical
analyses, such as are indicated in the last chapter, to some of the chief
practical difficulties of book-keeping by double entry in different trades.
2. Compare VI, section 4.
3. Of course this does not apply to railway rates. For a railway company having
little elasticity as to its methods of working, and often not much competition
from outside, has no inducement to endeavour to adjust the charges which it
makes for different kinds of traffic to their cost to itself. In fact though it
may ascertain the prime cost in each case easily enough, it cannot determine
accUrately what are the relative total costs of fast and slow traffic, of short
and long distance traffic, of light and heavy traffic; nor again of extra
traffic when its lines and its trains are crowded and when they are nearly
empty.
4. Again, certain insurance companies in America take risks against fire in
factories at very much less than the ordinary rates, on condition that some
prescribed precautions are taken, such as providing automatic sprinklers and
making the walls and floor solid. The expense incurred in these arrangements is
really an insurance premium; and care must be taken not to count it twice over.
A factory which undertakes its own risks against fire will have to add to the
prime cost of its goods an allowance for insurance at a lower rate, if it is
arranged on this plan, than if built in the ordinary way.
5. Again, when a farmer has calculated the expenses of raising any particular
crop with reference to an average year, he must not count in addition insurance
against the risk that the season may be bad, and the crop a failure: for in
taking an average year, he has already set of the chances of exceptionally good
and bad seasons against one another. When the earnings of a ferryman have been
calculated on the average of a year, allowance has already been made for the
risk that he may sometimes have to cross the stream with an empty boat.
6. Wealth of Nations, Book I, ch. x.
7. The evils resulting from the uncertainty involved in great business risks are
well shown by von Thünen (Der isolierte Staat, II, I, p. 82).
CHAPTER 8
MARGINAL COSTS IN RELATION TO VALUES. GENERAL PRINCIPLES
1. This Chapter and the three following are given to a study of the marginal
costs of products in relation to the values of those products on the one hand,
and on the other hand to the values of the land, machinery, and other appliances
used in making them. The study relates to normal conditions and long period
results. This fact must ever be borne in mind. The market value of anything may
be much above or much below the normal cost of production and the marginal costs
of a particular producer at any time may stand in no close relation to marginal
costs under normal conditions.(1*)
It was indicated at the end of Chapter VI that no one part of the problem can be
isolated from the rest. There are comparatively few things the demand for which
is not greatly affected by the demand for other things to the usefulness of
which they contribute; and it may even be said that the demand for the majority
of articles of commerce is not direct but is derived from the demand for those
commodities to the making of which they contribute, as materials or as
implements. And again this demand, because it is so derived, is largely
dependent on the supply of other things which will work with them in making
those commodities. And again the supply of anything available for use in making
any commodity is apt to be greatly influenced by the demand for that thing
derived from its uses in making other commodities: and so on. These
inter-relations can be and must be ignored in rapid and popular discussions on
the business affairs of the world. But no study that makes any claim to
thoroughness can escape from a close investigation of them. This requires many
things to be borne in mind at the same time: and for that reason economics can
never become a simple science.(2*)
The contribution which this group of chapters aims at making covers little
ground: but that ground is difficult and we shall need to work over it
carefully, and from more than one point of view; for it is thickly strewn with
pitfalls and stumbling blocks. It deals primarily with the earnings of land,
machinery, and other material agents of production. Its main argument applies to
the earnings of human beings; but they are influenced by some causes which do
not Affect the earnings of material agents of production: and the matter in hand
is sufficiently difficult without further complicating it by side issues.
2. Let us begin by recalling the action of the principle of substitution. In the
modern world nearly all the means of production pass through the hands of
employers and other business men, who specialize themselves in organizing the
economic forces of the population. Each of them chooses in every case those
factors of production which seem best for his purpose. And the sum of the prices
which he pays for those factors which he uses is, as a rule, less than the sum
of the prices which he would have to pay for any other set of factors which
could be substituted for them: for, whenever it appears that this is not the
case, he will, as a rule, set to work to substitute the less expensive
arrangement or process.(3*)
This statement is in close harmony with such common sayings of every-day life,
as that "everything tends to find its own level," that "most men earn just about
what they are worth," that "if one man can earn twice as much as another, that
shows that his work is worth twice as much," that "machinery will displace
manual labour whenever it can do the work cheaper." The principle does not
indeed without hindrance. It may be restricted by custom or act law, by
professional etiquette or trade-union regulation: it may be weakened by want of
enterprise, or it may be softened by a generous unwillingness to part with old
associates. But it never ceases to act, and it permeates all the economic
adjustments of the modern world.
Thus there are some kinds of field work for which horsePower is clearly more
suitable than steam-power, and vice versa. If we may now suppose that there have
been no great recent improvements in horse or steam machinery, and that
therefore the experience of the past has enabled farmers gradually to apply the
law of substitution; then, on this supposition the application of steam-power
will have been pushed just so far that any further use of it in the place of
horse-power would bring no net advantage. There will however remain a margin on
which they could be indifferently applied (as Jevons would have said); and on
that margin the net efficiency of either in adding to the money value of the
total product will be proportionate to the cost of applying it.(4*)
Similarly, if there are two methods of obtaining the same result, one by skilled
and the other by unskilled labour, that one will be adopted which is the more
efficient in proportion to its cost. There will be a margin on which either will
be indifferently applied.(5*) On that line the efficiency of each will be in
proportion to the price paid for it, account being taken of the special
circumstances of different districts and of different workshops in the same
district. In other words, the wages of skilled and unskilled labour will bear to
one another the same ratio that their efficiencies do at the margin of
indifference.
Again, there will be a rivalry between hand-power and machine-power similar to
that between two different kinds of hand-power or two different kinds of
machine-power. Thus hand-power has the advantage for some operations, as, for
instance, for weeding out valuable crops that have an irregular growth;
horse-power in its turn has a cleat advantage for weeding an ordinary turnip
field; and the application of each of them will be pushed in each district till
any further use of it would bring no net advantage there. On the margin of
indifference between hand-power and horse-power their prices must be
proportionate to their efficiency; and thus the influence of substitution will
tend to establish a direct relation between the wages of labour and the price
that has to be paid for horse-power.
3. As a rule many kinds of labour, of raw material, of machinery and other
plant, and of business organization, both internal and external, go to the
production of a commodity: and the advantages of economic freedom are never more
strikingly manifest than when a business man endowed with genius is trying
experiments, at his own risk, to see whether some new method, or combination of
old methods, will be more efficient than the old. Every business man indeed,
according to his energy and ability, is constantly endeavouring to obtain a
notion of the relative efficiency of every agent of production that he employs;
as well as of others that might possibly be substituted for some of them. He
estimates as best he can how much net product (i.e. net addition to the value of
his total product) will be caused by a certain extra use of any one agent; net
that is after deducting for any extra expenses that may be indirectly caused by
the change, and adding for any incidental savings. He endeavours to employ each
agent up to that margin at which its net product would no longer exceed the
price he would have to pay for it. He works generally by trained instinct rather
than formal calculation; but his processes are substantially similar to those
indicated in our study of derived demand; and, from another point of view, they
may be described as those which might be reaped by a complex and refined system
of book-keeping by double entry.(6*)
We have already followed some simple estimates of this sort. We have noticed,
for instance, how the proportion of hops and malt in ale can be varied, how the
extra price which can be got for ale by increasing the quantity of hops in it is
a representative of the causes which govern the demand price for hops. Assuming
that no further trouble or expense of any kind is involved by this additional
use of hops, and that the expediency of using this extra amount is doubtful, the
extra value thus given to the ale is the marginal net product of the hops of
which we are in search. In this case, as in most others, the net product is an
improvement in quality or a general contribution to the value of the product; it
is not a definite part of the produce which can be separated from the rest. But
in exceptional instances that can be done.(7*)
4. The notion of the marginal employment of any agent of production implies a
possible tendency to diminishing return from its increased employment.
Excessive applications of any means to the attainment of any end are indeed sure
to yield diminishing. returns in every branch of business; and, one may say, in
all the affairs of life. We may take some additional examples of a principle
that has already been illustrated.(8*) In the manufacture of sewing machines
some parts may well be made of cast iron; for others a common kind of steel will
suffice; there are yet others for which a specially expensive steel-compound is
needed; and all parts should be finished off more or less smoothly, so that the
machine may work easily. Now if any one devoted a disproportionate care and
expense to th selection of materials for the less important uses, it might truly
be said that that expenditure was yielding a rapidly diminishing return; and
that he would have done better to give some of it to making his machines work
smoothly, or even to producing more machines: and the case might be even worse
if he devoted an excessive expenditure to mere brilliancy of finish, and put low
grade metal to work for which a higher grade was needed.
This consideration seems at first to simplify economic problems; but on the
contrary it is a chief source of difficulty and confusion. For though there is
some analogy between all these various tendencies to diminishing return, they
yet are not identical. Thus the diminishing return which arises from an
ill-proportioned application of the various agents of production into a
particular task has little in common with that broad tendency to the pressure of
a crowded and growing population on the means of subsistence. The great
classical Law of Diminishing Return has its chief application, not to any one
particular crop, but to all the chief food crops. It takes for granted that
farmers raise, as a rule, those crops for which their land and other resources
are best adapted, account being taken of the relative demands for the several
crops; and that they distribute their resources appropriately between different
routes. It does not attribute to them unlimited intelligence and wisdom, but it
assumes that, taking one with another, they have shown a reasonable amount of
care and discretion in the distribution of these resources. It refers to a
country the whole land of which is already in the hands of active business men,
who can supplement their own capital by loans from banks wherever they can show
it is likely to be well applied; and asserts that an increase in the total
amount of capital applied to agriculture in that country will yield diminishing
returns of produce in general. This statement is akin to, but yet quite distinct
from, the statement that if any farmer makes a bad distribution of his resources
between different plans of cultivation, he will get a markedly diminishing
return from those elements of expenditure which he has driven to excess.
For instance, in any given case, there is a certain proportion between the
amounts which may with best advantage be spent on ploughing and harrowing, or
manuring. There might be some differences of opinion on the matter, but only
within narrow limits. An inexperienced person who ploughed many times over land,
which was already in fairly good mechanical condition, while he gave it little
or none of the manure which it was craving, would be generally condemned as
having so over applied ploughing as to make it yield a rapidly diminishing
return. But this result of the misapplication of resources has no very close
connection with the tendency of agriculture in an old country to yield a
diminishing return to a general increase of resources well applied in
cultivation: and indeed exactly parallel cases can be found of a diminishing
return to particular resources when applied in undue proportion, even in
industries which yield an increasing return to increased applications of capital
and labour when appropriately distributed.(9*)
5. The part played by the net product at of production in the modern doctrine of
Distribution is to be misunderstood. In particular many able writers have
supposed that it represents the marginal use of a thing as governing the value
of the whole. It is not so; the doctrine says we must go to the margin to study
the action of those forces which govern the value of the whole: and that is a
very different affair. Of course the withdrawal of (say) iron from any of its
necessary uses would have just the same influence on its value as its withdrawal
from its marginal uses; in the same way as the pressure in a boiler for cooking
under high pressure would be affected by the escape of any other steam just as
it would by the escape of the steam in one of the safety valves: but in fact the
steam does not escape except through the safety valves. In like manner iron, or
any other agent of production, is not (under ordinary circumstances) thrown out
of use except at points at which its use yields no clear surplus of profit; that
is, it is thrown out from its marginal uses only.
Again, the finger of an automatic weighing machine determines, in the sense of
indicating, the weight sought for. So the escape of steam from a safety valve,
governed by a spring representing a pressure of a hundred pounds to the square
inch, determines the pressure of steam in the boiler, in the sense of indicating
that it has reached a hundred pounds to the inch. The pressure is caused by the
heat; the spring in the valve governs the pressure by yielding and letting out
some of the steam when its amount is so great, at the existing heat, as to
overbear the resistance of the spring.
Similarly, with regard to machinery and other appliances of production made by
man, there is a margin through which additional supplies come in after
overcoming the resistance of a spring, called "cost of production," For when the
supply of those appliances is so small relatively to the demand that the
earnings expected from new supplies are more than sufficient to yield normal
interest (or profits, if earnings of management are reckoned in) on their cost
of production, besides allowing for depreciation, etc., then the valve opens,
and the new supplies come in. When the earnings are less than this, the valve
remains shut: and as anyhow the existing supply is always in process of slow
destruction by use and the lapse of time, the supply is always shrinking when
the valve is closed. The valve is that part of the machinery by which the
general relations of demand and supply govern value. But marginal uses do not
govern value; because they, together with value, are themselves governed by
those general relations.
6. Thus, so long as the resources of an individual producer are in the form of
general purchasing power, he will push every investment up to the margin at
which he no longer expects from it a higher net return than he could get by
investing in some other material, or machine, or advertisement, or in the hire
of some additional labour every investment will, as it were, be driven up to a
valve which offers to it a resistance equal to its own expanding force. If he
invests in material or in labour, that is soon embodied in some saleable
product: the sale replenishes his fluid capital, and that again is invested up
to the margin at which any further investment would yield a return so diminished
as not to be profitable.
But if he invests in land, or in a durable building or machine, the return which
he gets from his investment may vary widely from his expectation. It will be
governed by the market for his products, which may change its character largely
through new inventions, changes in fashion, etc., during the life of a machine,
to say nothing of the perpetual life of land. The incomes which he thus may
derive from investments in land and in machinery differ from his individual
point of view mainly in the longer life of the land. But in regard to production
in general, a dominant difference between the two lies in the fact that the
supply of land is fixed (though in a new country, the supply of land utilized in
man's service may be increased); while the supply of machines may be increased
without limit. And this difference reacts on the individual producer. For if no
great new invention renders his machines obsolete, while there is a steady
demand for the things made by them, they will be constantly on sale at about
their cost of production; and his machines will generally yield him normal
profits on that cost of production, with deductions corresponding to their wear
and tear.
Thus the rate of interest is a ratio: and the two things which it connects are
both sums of money. So long as capital is "free," and the sum of money or
general purchasing power over which it gives command is known, the net money
income, expected to be derived from it, can be represented at once as bearing a
given ratio (four or five or ten per cent) to that sum. But when the free
capital has been invested in a particular thing, its money value cannot as a
rule be ascertained except by capitalizing the net income which it will yield:
and therefore the causes which govern it are likely to be akin in a greater or
less degree to those which govern rents.
We are thus brought to the central doctrine of this part of economics, viz.: --
"That which is rightly regarded as interest on 'free' or 'floating' capital, or
on new investments of capital, is more properly treated as a sort of rent -- a
Quasi-rent -- On old investments of capital. And there is no sharp line of
division between floating capital and that which has been 'sunk' for a special
branch of production, nor between new and old investments of capital; each group
shades into the other gradually. And thus even the rent of land is seen, not as
a thing by itself, but as the leading species of a large genus; though indeed it
has peculiarities of its own which are of vital importance from the point of
view of theory as well as of practice."(10*)
NOTES:
1. Numerous objections have been urged against the important place assigned to
marginal costs in modern analysis. But it will be found that most of them rely
on arguments, in which statements referring to normal conditions and normal
value are controverted by statements relating to abnormal or particular
conditions.
2. The reader is referred to the footnote on p. 393 with special reference to
the compressed mathematical version of the central problem of value which begins
in Note XIV in the Mathematical Appendix and culminates in Note XXI.
3. Compare V, III, section 3; and V, IV, sections 3, 4; and Note XIV in the
Mathematical Appendix.
4. This margin will vary with local circumstances, as well as with the habits,
inclinations, and resources of individual farmers. The difficulty of applying
steam machinery in small fields and on rugged ground is overcome more generally
in those districts in which labour is scarce than in those in which it is
plentiful; especially if, as is probable, coal is cheaper, and the feed of
horses dearer in the former than the latter.
5. Skilled manual labour being generally used for special orders and for things
of which not many are required of the same pattern; and unskilled labour aided
by specialized machinery being used for others. The two methods are to be seen
side by side on similar work in every large workshop: but the position of the
line between them will vary a little from one workshop to another.
6. The changes, which he desires, may be such as could only be made on a large
scale; as for instance the substitution of steam-power for hand-power in a
certain factory; and in that case there would be a certain element of
uncertainty and risk in the change. Such breaches of continuity are however
inevitable both in production and consumption if we regard the action of single
individuals. But as there is a continuous demand in a large market for hats and
watches and wedding cakes, though no individual buys many of them (see III, III,
section 5), so there will always be trades in which small businesses are most
economically conducted without steam power, and larger businesses with; while
businesses of intermediate size are on the margin. Again, even in large
establishments in which steam is already in use, there will always be some
things done by hand-power which are done by steam power elsewhere; and so on .
7. See p. 387, and Mathematical Note XVI. See also other illustrations in, VI,
VII. A further illustration of the relation between the wages of the marginal
shepherd, and the net product of his labour will be worked out in detail in VI,
I, section 7 .
8. See V, IV, section 4; see also the note on von Thünen, below, p. 523.
9. See above IV, iii, section 8; and Carver, Distribution of Wealth, ch. ii, and
above footnotes on pp. 319, 320. Mr J. A. Hobson is a vigorous and suggestive
writer on the realistic and social sides of economics: but, as a critic of
Ricardian doctrines, he is perhaps apt to underrate the difficulty of the
problems which he discusses. He argues that if the marginal application of any
agent of production be curtailed, that will so disorganize production that every
other agent will be working to less effect than before; and that therefore the
total resulting loss will include not only the true marginal product of that
agent, but also a part of the products due to the other agents: but he appears
to have overlooked the following points: -- (1) There are forces constantly at
work tending so to readjust the distribution of resources between their
different uses, that any maladjustment will be arrested before it has gone far:
and the argument does not profess to apply to exceptional cases of violent
maladjustment. (2) When the adjustment is such as to give the best results, a
slight change in the proportions in which they are applied diminishes the
efficiency of that adjustment by a quantity which is very small relatively to
that change in technical language it is of "the second order of smalls" --; and
it may therefore be neglected relatively to that change. (In pure mathematical
phrase, efficiency being regarded as a function of the proportions of the
agents; when the efficiency is at its maximum, its differential coefficient with
regard to any one of these proportions is zero.) A grave error would therefore
have been involved, if any allowance had been made for those elements which Mr
Hobson asserts to have been overlooked. (3) In economics, as in physics, changes
are generally continuous. Convulsive changes may indeed occur, but they must be
dealt with separately: and an illustration drawn from a convulsive change can
throw no true light on the processes of normal steady evolution. In the
particular problem before us, this precaution is of special importance: for a
violent check to the supply of any one agent of production, may easily render
the work of all other agents practically useless; and therefore it may inflict a
loss out of all proportion to the harm done by a small check to the supply of
that agent when applied up to that margin, at which there was doubt whether the
extra net product due to a small additional application of it would be
remunerative. The study of changes in complex quantitative relations is often
vitiated by a neglect of this consideration, to which Mr Hobson seems to be
prone; as indeed is instanced by his remarks on a "marginal shepherd" in The
Industrial System, p. i 10. See Professor Edgeworth's masterly analyses of the
two instances mentioned in this note, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 1904, p.
167; and Scientia, 1910, pp. 95-100.
10. This statement is reproduced from the Preface to the first edition of the
present volume.
CHAPTER 9
MARGINAL COSTS IN RELATION TO VALUES.
GENERAL PRINCIPLES, CONTINUED
1. The incidents of the tenure of land are so complex: and so many practical
issues connected with them have raised controversies on side issues of the
problem of value, that it will be well to supplement our previous illustration
from land. We may take another from an imaginary commodity so chosen that sharp
outlines can be assigned to each stage of the problem, without inviting the
objection that such sharp outlines are not found in the actual relations between
landlord and tenant.
But before entering on this, we may prepare the way for using, as we go,
illustrations drawn from the incidence of taxation to throw side-lights on the
problem of value. For indeed a great part of economic science is occupied with
the diffusion throughout the community of economic changes which primarily
affect some particular branch of production or consumption; and there is
scarcely any economic principle which cannot be aptly illustrated by a
discussion of the shifting of the effects of some tax "forwards," i.e. towards
the ultimate consumer, and away from the producer of raw material and implements
of production; or else in the opposite direction, "backwards." But especially is
this true of the class of problems now under discussion.(1*)
It is a general principle that if a tax impinges on anything used by one set of
persons in the production of goods or services to be disposed of to other
persons, the tax tends to check production. This tends to shift a large part of
the burden of the tax forwards on to consumers, and a small part backwards on to
those who supply the requirements of this set of producers. Similarly, a tax on
the consumption of anything is shifted in a greater or less degree backwards on
to its producer.
For instance, an unexpected and heavy tax upon printing would strike hard upon
those engaged in the trade, for if they attempted to raise prices much, demand
would fall off quickly: but the blow would bear unevenly on various classes
engaged in the trade. Since printing machines and compositors cannot easily find
employment out of the trade, the prices of printing machines and wages of
compositors would be kept low for some time. On the other hand, the buildings
and steam engines, the porters, engineers, and clerks would not wait for their
numbers to be adjusted by the slow process of natural decay to the diminished
demand; some of them would be quickly at work in other trades, and very little
of the burden would stay long on those of them who remained in the trade. A
considerable part of the burden, again, would fall on subsidiary industries,
such as those engaged in making paper and type; because the market for their
products would be curtailed. Authors and publishers would also suffer a little;
because they would be forced either to raise the price of books, with a
consequent diminution of sales, or to see a greater proportion of their gross
receipts swallowed up by costs. Finally, the total turnover of the booksellers
would diminish, and they would suffer a little.
So far it has been assumed that the tax spreads its net very wide, and covers
every place to which the printing industry in question could be easily
transferred. But, if the tax were only local, the compositors would migrate
beyond its reach; and the owners of printing houses might bear a larger and not
a smaller proportionate share of the burden than those whose resources were more
specialized but more mobile. If the local tax were uncompensated by any effect
which tended to attract population, part of the burden would be thrown on local
bakers, grocers, etc., whose sales would be diminished.
Next suppose the tax to be levied on printing presses instead of on printed
matter. In that case, if the printers had no semi-obsolete presses which they
were inclined to destroy or to leave idle, the tax would not strike marginal
production: it would not immediately affect the output of printing, nor
therefore its price. It would merely intercept some of the earnings of the
presses on the way to the owners, and lower the quasi-rents of the presses. But
it would not affect the rate of net profits which was needed to induce people to
invest fluid capital in presses: and therefore, as the old presses wore out, the
tax would add to marginal expenses, that is to expenses which the producer was
free to incur or not as he liked, and which he was in doubt whether to incur.
Therefore the supply of printing would be curtailed; its price would rise: and
new presses would be introduced only up to the margin at which they would be
able, in the judgment of printers generally, to pay the tax and yet yield normal
profits on the outlay. When this stage had been reached the distribution of the
burden of a tax upon presses would henceforth be nearly the same as that of a
tax upon printing: excepting only that there would be more inducement to get a
great deal of work out of each press. For instance more of the presses might be
made to work double shifts; in spite of the fact that night work involves
special expenses.
We now pass to apply these principles of shifting of taxes to our main
illustration.
2. Let us suppose that a meteoric shower of a few thousand large stones harder
than diamonds fell all in one place; so that they were all picked up at once,
and no amount of search could find any more. These stones, able to cut every
material, would revolutionize many branches of industry; and the owners of them
would have a differential advantage in production, that would afford a large
producer's surplus. This surplus would be governed wholly by the urgency and
volume of the demand for their services on the one hand and the number of the
stones on the other hand: it could not be affected by the cost of obtaining a
further supply, because none could be had at any price. A cost of production
might indeed influence their value indirectly: but it would be the cost of tools
made of hard steel and other materials of which the supply can be increased to
keep pace with demand. So long as any of the stones were habitually used by
intelligent producers for work which could be done equally well by such tools,
the value of a stone could not much exceed the cost of producing tools
(allowance being made for wear and tear) equally efficient with it in these
inferior uses.
The stones, being so hard as not to be affected by wear, would probably be kept
in operation during all the working hours of the day. And if their services were
very valuable, it might be worth while to keep people working overtime, or even
in double or triple shifts, in order to extract the utmost service from them.
But the more intensively they were applied, the less net return would be reaped
from each additional service forced from them; thus illustrating the law that
the intensive working not only of land, but of every other appliance of
production is likely to yield a diminishing return if pressed far enough.
The total supply of stones is fixed. But of course any particular manufacturer
might obtain almost as many as he liked to pay for: and in the long run he would
expect his outlay on them to be returned with interest (or profits, if the
remuneration for his own work were not reckoned separately), just in the same
way as if he were buying machinery, the total stock of which could be increased
indefinitely, so that its price conformed pretty closely to its cost of
production.
But when he had once bought the stones, changes in the processes of production
or of demand for the things made by their aid, might cause the income yielded by
them to become twice as great or only half as great as he had expected. In the
latter case it would resemble the income derived from a machine, which had not
the latest improvements and could earn only half as much as a new machine of
equal cost. The values of the stone and of the machine alike would be reached by
capitalizing the income which they were capable of earning, and that income
would be governed by the net value of the services rendered by them. The income
earning power and therefore the value of each would be independent of its own
costs of production, but would be governed by the general demand for its
products in relation to the general supply of those products. But in the case of
the machine that supply would be controlled by the cost of supply of new
machines equally efficient with it; and in the case of the stone there would be
no such limit, so long as all the stones in existence were employed on work that
could not be done by anything else.
This argument may be put in another way. Since any one, who bought stones, would
take them from other producers, his purchase would not materially affect the
general relations of demand for the services of the stones to the supply of
those services. It would not therefore affect the price of the stones; which
would still be the capitalized value of the services which they rendered in
those uses, in which the need for them was the least urgent: and to say that the
purchaser expected normal interest on the price which represented the
capitalized value of the services, would be a circular statement that the value
of the services rendered by stones is governed by the value of those very
services.(2*)
Next let us suppose that the stones were not all found at once but were
scattered over the surface of the earth on public ground, and that a laborious
search might expect to be rewarded by finding one here and there. Then people
would hunt for the stones only up to that point, or margin, at which the
probable gain of so doing would in the long run just reward the outlay of labour
and capital involved; and in the long run, the normal value of the stones would
be such as to maintain equilibrium between demand and supply, the number of the
stones gathered annually being in the long run just that for which the normal
demand price was equal to the normal supply price.
Finally, let us bring the case of the stones into accord with that of the
lighter machinery and other plant ordinarily used in manufacture, by supposing
that the stones were brittle, and were soon destroyed; and that an inexhaustible
store existed from which additional supplies could be obtained quickly and
certainly at a nearly uniform cost. In this case the value of the stones would
always correspond closely to that cost: variations in demand would have but
little influence on their price, because even a slight change in price would
quickly effect a great change in the stock of them in the market. In this case
the income derived from a stone (allowance being made for wear-and-tear) would
always adhere closely to interest on its cost of production.
3. This series of hypotheses stretches continuously from the one extreme in
which the income derived from the stones is a rent in the strictest sense of the
term, to the other extreme in which it is to be classed rather with interest on
free or floating capital. In the first extreme case the stones cannot be worn
out or destroyed, and no more can be found. They of course tend to be
distributed among the various uses to which they are applicable in such a way
that there is no use to which an increased supply of them could be applied,
without taking them away from some other use in which they were rendering net
services at least as valuable. These margins of application of the several uses
are thus governed by the relation in which the fixed stock of stones stands to
the aggregate of demands for them in different uses. And the margins being thus
governed, the prices that will be paid for their use are indicated by the value
of the services which they render at any one of those margins.
A uniform tax on them, collected from the user, will lower their net service in
each use by the same amount: it will not affect their distribution between
several uses; and it will fall wholly on the owner, after perhaps some little
delay caused by a frictional resistance to readjustments.
At the opposite extreme of our chain of hypotheses, the stones perish so
quickly, and are so quickly reproduced at about a uniform cost, that variations
in the urgency and volume of the uses to which the stones can be put will be
followed so promptly by changes in the stock of them available, that those
services can never yield much more or much less than normal interest on the
money cost of obtaining additional stones. In this case a business man, when
making his estimates for the cost of any undertaking in which stones will be
used, may enter interest (or if he is counting his own work in, profits), for
the time during which those stones will be used (together with wear-and-tear),
as part of the prime, special, or direct expenses of his undertaking. A tax on
the stones under these conditions would fall entirely on any one who even a
little while after the tax had come into force, gave out a contract for anything
in making which the stones would be used.
Taking an intermediate hypothesis as to the length of life of the stones and the
rapidity with which new supplies could be obtained; we find that the charges
which the borrower of stones must expect to pay, and the revenue which the owner
of the stones could reckon on deriving from them at any time, might temporarily
diverge some way from interest (or profits) on their cost. For changes in the
urgency and volume of the uses to which they could be applied, might have caused
the value of the services rendered by them in their marginal uses to rise or
fall a great deal, even though there had been no considerable change in the
difficulty of obtaining them. And if this rise or fall, arising from variations
in demand, and not from variations in the cost of the stones, is likely to be
great during the period of any particular enterprise, or any particular problem
of value that is under discussion; then for that discussion the income yielded
by the stones is to be regarded as more nearly akin to a rent than to interest
on the cost of producing the stones. A tax upon the stones in such a case would
tend to diminish the rental which people would pay for their use, and therefore
to diminish the inducements towards investing capital and effort in obtaining
additional supplies. It would therefore check the supply, and compel those who
needed the stones to pay gradually increasing rentals for their use, up to the
point at which the rentals fully covered the costs of producing the stones. But
the time needed for this readjustment might be long: and in the interval a great
part of the tax would fall upon the owners of the stones.
If the life of the stones was long relatively to that process of production in
which the stones were used which was under discussion, the stock of stones might
be in excess of that needed to do all the work for which they were specially
fitted. Some of them might be lying almost idle, and the owner of these stones
might make up his estimate of the marginal price for which he was just willing
to work without entering in that estimate interest on the value of the stones.
That is to say, some costs which would have been classed as prime costs in
relation to contracts, or other affairs, which lasted over a long period, would
be classed as supplementary costs in relation to a particular affair which would
last but a short time, and which came under consideration when business was
slack.
It is of course just as essential in the long run that the price obtained should
cover general or supplementary costs as that it should cover prime costs. An
industry will be driven out of existence in the long run as certainly by failing
to return even a moderate interest on capital invested in steam engines, as by
failing to replace the price of the coal or the raw material used up from day to
day: just as a man's work will be stopped as certainly by depriving him of food
as by putting him in chains. But the man can go on working fairly well for a day
without food; while if he is put in chains the check to his work comes at once.
So an industry may, and often does, keep tolerably active during a whole year or
even more, in which very little is earned beyond prime costs, and the fixed
plant has "to work for nothing." But when the price falls so low that it does
not pay for the out of pocket expenses during the yea r for wages and raw
material, for coal and for lighting, etc., then the production is likely to come
to a sharp stop.
This is the fundamental difference between those incomes yielded by agents of
production which are to be regarded as rents or quasi-rents and those which
(after allowing for the replacement of wear-and-tear and other destruction) may
be regarded as interest (or profits) on current investments. The difference is
fundamental, but it is only one of degree. Biology tends to show that the animal
and vegetable kingdoms have a common origin. But yet there are fundamental
differences between mammals and trees; while in a narrower sense the differences
between an oak tree and an apple tree are fundamental; and so are in a still
narrower sense those between an apple tree and a rose bush, though they are both
classed as rosaceae. Thus our central doctrine is that interest on free capital
and quasi-rent on an old investment of capital shade into one another gradually;
even the rent of land being not a thing by itself, but the leading species of a
large genus.(3*)
4. Again, pure elements are seldom isolated from all others by nature either in
the physical or moral world. Pure rent in the strict sense of the term is
scarcely ever met with: nearly all income from land contains more or less
important elements which are derived from efforts invested in building houses
and sheds, in draining the land and so on. But economists have learnt to
recognize diversity of nature in those composite things to which the names of
rent, profits, wages etc. are given in popular language; they have learnt that
there is an element of true rent in the composite product that is commonly
called wages, an element of true earnings in what is commonly called rent and so
on. They have learnt in short to follow the example of the chemist who seeks for
the true properties of each element; and who is thus prepared to deal with the
common oxygen or soda of commerce, though containing admixtures of other
elements.(4*)
They recognize that nearly all land in actual use contains an element of
capital; that separate reasonings are required for those parts of its value
which are, and those which are not, due to efforts of man invested in the land
for the purposes of production; and that the results of these reasonings must be
combined in dealing with any particular case of that income which commonly goes
by the name "rent," but not all of which is rent in the narrower sense of the
term. The manner in which the reasonings are to be combined depends on the
nature of the problem. Sometimes the mere mechanical "composition of forces"
suffices; more often allowance must be made for a quasi-chemical interaction of
the various forces; while in nearly all problems of large scope and importance,
regard must be had to biological conceptions of growth.
5. Finally a little may be said on a distinction that is sometimes made between
"scarcity rents" and "differential rents." In a sense all rents are scarcity
rents, and all rents are differential rents. But in some cases it is convenient
to estimate the rent of a particular agent by comparing its yield to that of an
inferior (perhaps a marginal) agent, when similarly worked with appropriate
appliances. And in other cases it is best to go straight to the fundamental
relations of demand to the scarcity or abundance of the means for the production
of those commodities for making which the agent is serviceable.
Suppose for instance that all the meteoric stones in existence were equally hard
and imperishable; and that they were in the hands of a single authority: further
that this authority decided, not to make use of its monopolistic power to
restrict production so as to raise the price of its services artificially, but
to work each of the stones to the full extent it could be profitably worked
(that is up to the margin of pressure so intensive that the resulting product
could barely be marketed at a price which covered, with profits, its expenses
without allowing anything for the use of the stone). Then the price of the
services rendered by the stones would have been governed by the natural scarcity
of the aggregate output of their services in relation to the demand for those
services; and the aggregate surplus or rent would most easily be reckoned as the
excess of this scarcity price over the aggregate expenses of working the stones.
It would therefore generally be regarded as a scarcity rent. But on the other
hand it could have been reckoned as the differential excess of the aggregate
value of the net services of the stones over that which would have been reached
if all their uses had been as unproductive as their marginal uses. And exactly
the same would be true if the stones were in the hands of different producers,
impelled by competition with one another to work each stone up to the margin at
which its further use ceased to be profitable.
This last instance has been so chosen as to bring out the fact that the
"differential" as well as the "scarcity" routes for estimating rent are
independent of the existence of inferior agents of production: for the
differential comparison in favour of the more advantageous uses of the stones
can be made by reference to the marginal uses of good stones, as clearly as by
reference to the use of inferior stones which are on the margin of not being
worth using at all.
In this connection it may be noted that the opinion that the existence of
inferior land, or other agents of production, tends to raise the rents of the
better agents is not merely untrue. It is the reverse of the truth. For, if the
bad land were to be flooded and rendered incapable of producing anything at all,
the cultivation of other land would need to be more intensive; and therefore the
price of the product would be higher, and rents generally would be higher, than
if that land had been a poor contributor to the total stock of produce.(5*)
NOTES:
1. The substance of this section is reproduced from answers to questions
proposed by the Royal Commission on Local Taxation. See [C. 9528], 1899, pp.
112-26.
2. Such circular reasonings are sometimes nearly harmless: but they always tend
to overlay and hide the real issues. And they are sometimes applied to
illegitimate uses by company promoters; and by advocates of special interests,
who desire to influence the course of legislation in their own favour. For
instance a semi monopolistic business aggregation or trust is often
"over-capitalized." To effect this a time is chosen, at which the branch of
production with which it is concerned is abnormally prosperous: when perhaps
some solid firms are earning fifty per cent. net on their capital in a single
year, and thus making up for lean years past and to come in which their receipts
will do little more than cover prime costs. Financiers connected with the
flotation sometimes even arrange that the businesses to be offered to the public
shall have a good many orders to fill at specially favourable prices: the loss
falling on themselves, or on other companies which they control. The gains to be
secured by semi-monopolistic selling, and possibly by some further economies in
production are emphasized: and the stock of the trust is absorbed by the public.
If ultimately objection to the conduct of the trust is raised, and especially to
the strengthening of its semi-monopolistic position by a high tariff or any
other public favour, the answer is given that the shareholders are receiving but
a moderate return on their investments. Such cases are not uncommon in America.
In this country a more moderate watering of the stock of some railways has been
occasionally used indirectly as a defence of the shareholders against a lowering
of rates, that threatens to reduce dividends on inflated capital below what
would be a fair return on solid capital.
3. See above, p. 412.
4. Professor Fetter seems to ignore this lesson in an article on "The Passing of
the Concept of Rent" in the Quarterly Journal of Economics, May 1901, p. 419;
where he argues that "if only those things which owe nothing to labour are
classed as land, and if it is then shown that there is no material thing in
settled countries of which this can be said, it follows that everything must be
classed as capital." Again he appears to have missed the true import of the
doctrines which he assails, when he argues (ib. pp. 423-9) against "Extension as
the fundamental attribute of land, and the basis of rent." The fact is that its
extension (or rather the aggregate of "its space relations") is the chief,
though not the only property ofland, which causes the income derived from it (in
an old country) to contain a large element of true rent: and that the element of
true rent, which exists in the income derived from land, or the "rent of land"
in the popular use of the term, is in practice so much more important than any
others that it has given a special character to the historical development of
the Theory of Rent (see above, p. 147). If meteoric stones of absolute hardness,
in high demand and incapable of increase, had played a more important part in
the economic history of the world than land, then the elements of true rent
which attracted the chief attention of students, would have been associated with
the property of hardness; and this would have given a special tone and character
to the development of the Theory of Rent. But neither extension nor hardness is
a fundamental attribute of all things which yield a true rent. Professor Fetter
seems also to have missed the point of the central doctrine as to rents,
quasi-rents and interest, given above.
5. Compare Cassel, Das Recht auf den vollen Arbeitsertrag, p. 81.
The many misconceptions, that have appeared in the writings even of able
economists, as to the nature of a quasi-rent, seem to arise from an inadequate
attention to the differences between short periods and long in regard to value
and costs. Thus it has been said that a quasi-rent is an "unnecessary profit,"
and that it is "no part of cost" Quasi-rent is correctly described as an
unnecessary profit in regard to short periods, because no "special" or "prime"
costs have to be incurred for the production of a machine that, by hypothesis,
is already made and waiting for its work. But it is a necessary profit in regard
to those other (supplementary) costs which must be incurred in the long run in
addition to prime costs; and which in some industries, as for instance sub
marine telegraphy, are very much more important than prime costs. It is no part
of cost under any conditions: but the confident expectation of coming
quasi-rents is a necessary condition for the investment of capital in machinery,
and for the incurring of supplementary costs generally.
Again a quasi-rent has been described as a sort of "conjuncture" or
"opportunity" profit; and, almost in the same breath, as no profit or interest
at all, but only a rent. For the time being, it is a conjuncture or opportunity
income: while in the long run it is expected to, and it generally does, yield a
normal rate of interest (or if earnings of management are counted in, of profit)
on the free capital, represented by a definite sum of money that was invested in
producing it. By definition the rate of interest is a percentage; that is a
relation between two numbers (see above, p. 412). A machine is not a number: its
value may be a certain number of pounds or dollars: but that value is estimated,
unless the machine be a new one, as the aggregate of its (discounted) earnings,
or quasi-rents. If the machine is new, its makers have calculated that this
aggregate will appear to probable purchasers as the equivalent of a price which
will repay the makers for it: in that case therefore it is as a rule, both a
cost price, and a price which represents an aggregate of (discounted) future
incomes. But when the machine is old and partially obsolete in pattern, there is
no close relation between its value and its cost of production: its value is
then simply the aggregate of the discounted values of the future quasi-rents,
which it is expected to earn.
CHAPTER X
MARGINAL COSTS IN RELATION TO AGRICULTURAL VALUES
1. We now pass from general considerations to those relating to land; and we
begin with those specially applicable to agricultural land in an old country.
Suppose, that a war, which was not expected to last long, were to cut off part
of the food supplies of England. Englishmen would set themselves to raise
heavier crops by such extra application of capital or labour as was likely to
yield a speedy return; they would consider the results of artificial manures, of
the use of clod-crushing machines, and so on; and the more favourable these
results were, the less would be the rise in the price of produce in the coming
year which they regarded as necessary to make it worth their while to incur
additional outlay in these directions. But the war would have very little effect
on their action as to those improvements which would not bear fruit till it was
over. In any inquiry then as to the causes that will determine the prices of
corn during a short period, that fertility which the soil derives from slowly
made improvements has to be taken for granted as it then is, almost in the same
way as if it had been made by nature. Thus, the income derived from these
permanent improvements gives a surplus above the prime or special costs needed
for raising extra produce. But it is not a true surplus, in the same sense that
the rent proper is, i.e. it is not a surplus above the total costs of the
produce: it is needed to cover the general expenses of the business.
To speak more exactly: -- If the extra income derived from improvements that
have been made in the land by its individual owner is so reckoned as not to
include any benefit which would have been conferred on the land by the general
progress of society independently of his efforts and sacrifices; then, as a
rule, the whole of it is required to remunerate him for those efforts and
sacrifices. He may have underestimated the gains which will result from them;
but he is about equally likely to have made an overestimate. If he has estimated
them rightly, his interest has urged him to make the investment as soon as it
showed signs of being profitable: and in the absence of any special reason to
the contrary we may suppose him to have done this. In the long run, then, the
net returns to the investment of capital in the land, taking successful and
unsuccessful returns together, do not afford more than an adequate motive to
such investment. If poorer returns had been expected than those on which people
actually based their calculations, fewer improvements would have been made.
That is to say: -- for periods which are long in comparison with the time needed
to make improvements of any kind, and bring them into full operation, the net
incomes derived from them are but the price required to be paid for the efforts
and sacrifices of those who make them: the expenses of making them thus directly
enter into marginal expenses of production, and take a direct part in governing
long-period supply price. But in short periods, that is, in periods short
relatively to the time required to make and bring into full bearing improvements
of the class in question, no such direct influence on supply price is exercised
by the necessity that such improvements should in the long run yield net incomes
sufficient to give normal profits on their cost. And therefore when we are
dealing with such periods, these incomes may be regarded as quasi-rents which
depend on the price of the produce.(1*)
We may conclude then: -- (1) The amount of produce raised, and therefore the
position of the margin of cultivation (i.e. the margin of the profitable
application of capital and labour to good and bad land alike) are both governed
by the general conditions of demand and supply. They are governed on the one
hand by demand; that is, by the numbers of the population who consume the
produce, the intensity of their need for it, and their means of paying for it;
and on the other hand by supply; that is, by the extent and fertility of the
available land, and the numbers and resources of those ready to cultivate it.
Thus cost of production, eagerness of demand, margin of production, and price of
the produce mutually govern one another: and no circular reasoning is involved
in speaking of any one as in part governed by the others. (2) That part of the
produce which goes as rent is of course thrown on the market, and acts on
prices, in just the same way as any other part. But the general conditions of
demand and supply, or their relations to one another, are not affected by the
division of the produce into the share of rent and the share needed to render
the farmer's expenditure profitable. The amount of that rent is not a governing
cause; but is itself governed by the fertility of land, the price of the
produce, and the position of the margin: it is the excess of the value of the
total returns which capital and labour applied to land do obtain, over those
which they would have obtained under circumstances as unfavourable as those on
the margin of cultivation. (3) If the cost of production were estimated for
parts of the produce which do not come from the margin, a charge on account of
rent would of course need to be entered in this estimate; and if this estimate
were used in an account of the causes which govern the price of the produce;
then the reasoning would be circular. For that, which is wholly an effect, would
be reckoned up as part of the cause of those things of which it is an effect.
(4) The cost of production of the marginal produce can be ascertained without
reasoning in a circle. The cost of production of other parts of the produce
cannot. The cost of production on the margin of the profitable application of
capital and labour is that to which the price of the whole produce tends, under
the control of the general conditions of demand and supply: it does not govern
price, but it focusses the causes which do govern price.
2. It has sometimes been suggested that if all land were equally advantageous
and all were occupied, the income derived from it would partake of the nature of
a monopoly rent: but this seems to be an error. Of course the landowners might
conceivably combine to stint production, whether their properties were of equal
fertility or not; the raised prices which would thus be obtained for the produce
would be monopoly prices; and the incomes of the owners would be monopoly
revenues rather than rents. But, with a free market, the revenues from land
would be rents, governed by the same causes and in the same way in a country
where the land was all of equal advantage, as in those where good and bad land
were intermingled.(2*)
It is, indeed, true that if there were more than enough land, all of about the
same fertility, to enable everyone to have as much of it as was needed to give
full scope to the capital he was prepared to apply to it, then it could yield no
rent. But that merely illustrates the old paradox that water, when abundant, has
no market value: for though the services of some part of it are essential to
support life, yet everyone can get without effort to that margin of satiety at
which any further supplies would be of no service to him. When every cottager
has a well from which he can draw as much water as he needs, with no more labour
than is required at his neighbour's well, the water in the well has no market
value. But let a drought set in, so that the shallow wells are exhausted, and
even the deeper wells are threatened, then the owners of those wells can exact a
charge for every bucket which they allow anyone to draw for his own use. The
denser population becomes, the more numerous will be the occasions on which such
charges can be made (it being supposed that no new wells are developed): and at
last every owner of a well may find in it a permanent source of revenue.
In the same way the scarcity value of land in a new country gradually emerges.
The early settler exercises no exclusive privilege, for he only does what anyone
else is at liberty to do. He undergoes many hardships, if not personal dangers;
and perhaps he runs some risks that the land may turn out badly, and that he may
have to abandon his improvements. On the other hand, his venture may turn out
well; the flow of population may trend his way, and the value of his land may
soon give as large a surplus over the normal remuneration of his outlay on it as
the fishermen's haul does when they come home with their boat full. But in this
there is no surplus above the rewards needed for his venture. He has engaged in
a risky business which was open to all, and his energy and good fortune have
given him an exceptionally high reward: anyone else might have taken the same
chance as he did. Thus the income which he expects the land to afford in the
future enters into the calculations of the settler, and adds to the motives
which determine his action when in doubt as to how far to carry his enterprise.
He regards its "discounted value"(3*) as profits on his capital, and as earnings
of his own labour, in so far as his improvements are made with his own hands.
A settler often takes up land with the expectation that the produce which it
affords while in his possession, will fall short of an adequate reward for his
hardships, his labour and his expenditure. He looks for part of his reward to
the value of the land itself, which he may perhaps after a while sell to some
new-comer who has no turn for the life of a pioneer. Sometimes even, as the
British farmer learns to his cost, the new settler regards his wheat almost as a
by-product; the main product for which he works is a farm, the title-deeds to
which he will earn by improving the land: he reckons that its value will
steadily rise, not through his own efforts so much as through the growth of
those comforts and resources, and of those markets in which to buy and in which
to sell, that are the product of the growing public prosperity.
This may be put in another way. People are generally unwilling to face the
hardships and isolation of pioneer agriculture, unless they can look forward
with some confidence to much higher earnings, measured in terms of the
necessaries of life, than they could get at home. Miners cannot be attracted to
a rich mine, isolated from other conveniences and varied social opportunities of
civilization, except by the promise of high wages: and those who superintend the
investment of their own capital in such mines expect very high profits. For
similar reasons pioneer farmers require high aggregate gains made up of receipts
for the sale of their produce, together with the acquisition of valuable
title-deeds, to remunerate them for their labour and endurance of hardships. And
the land is peopled up to that margin at which it just yields gains adequate for
this purpose, without leaving any surplus for rent, when no charge is made for
the land. When a charge is made, immigration spreads only up to that margin, at
which the gains will leave a surplus, of the nature of rent, to cover such
charges, in addition to rewarding the pioneer's endurance.
3. With all this it is to be remembered that land is but a particular form of
capital from the point of view of the individual producer. The question whether
a farmer has carried his cultivation of a particular piece of land as far as he
profitably can; and whether he should try to force more from it, or to take in
another piece of land; is of the same kind as the question whether he should buy
a new plough, or try to get a little more work out of his present stock of
ploughs, using them sometimes when the soil is not in a very favourable
condition, and feeding his horses a little more lavishly. He weighs the net
product of a little more land against the other uses to which he could put the
capital sum that he would have to expend in order to obtain it: and in like
manner he weighs the net product, to be got by working his ploughs under
unfavourable circumstances, against that got by increasing his stock of ploughs,
and thus working under more favourable conditions. That part of his produce
which he is in doubt whether to raise by extra use of his existing ploughs, or
by introducing a new plough, may be said to be derived from a marginal use of
the plough. It pays nothing net (i.e. nothing beyond a charge for actual
wear-and-tear) towards the net income earned by the plough.
So again a manufacturer or trader, owning both land and buildings, regards the
two as bearing similar relations to his business. Either will afford him aid and
accommodation at first liberally; and afterwards with diminishing return, as he
endeavours to force more and more from them: till at last he will doubt whether
the overcrowding of his workshops or his storerooms is not so great a source of
trouble, that it would answer his purpose to obtain more space. And when he
comes to decide whether to obtain that space by taking in an extra piece of land
or by building his factory a floor higher, he weighs the net income to be
derived from further investments in the one against that to be derived from the
other. That part of his production which he just forces out of his existing
appliances (being in doubt whether it would not be better worth his while to
increase those appliances than to work so intensively those which he has), does
not contribute to the net income which those appliances yield him. This argument
says nothing as to whether the appliances were made by man, or part of a stock
given by nature; it applies to rents and quasi-rents alike.
But there is this difference from the point of view of society. If one person
has possession of a farm, there is less land for others to have. His use of it
is not in addition to, but in lieu of the use of a farm by other people: whereas
if he invests in improvements of land or in buildings on it, he will not
appreciably curtail the opportunities of others to invest capital in like
improvements. Thus there is likeness amid unlikeness between land and appliances
made by man. There is unlikeness because land in an old country is approximately
(and in some senses absolutely) a permanent and fixed stock: while appliances
made by man, whether improvements in land, or in buildings, or machinery, etc.,
are a flow capable of being increased or diminished according to variations in
the effective demand for the products which they help in raising. So far there
is unlikeness. But on the other hand there is likeness, in that, since some of
them cannot be produced quickly, they are a practically fixed stock for short
periods: and for those periods the incomes derived from them stand in the same
relation to the value of the products raised by them, as do true rents.(4*)
4. Let us apply these considerations to the supposition that a permanent tax is
to be levied on "corn," in the sense in which it was used by the classical
economists as short for all agricultural produce. It is obvious that the farmer
would try to make the consumer pay some part at least of the tax. But any rise
in the price charged to the consumer would check demand, and thus react on the
farmer. In order to decide how much of this tax would be shifted on to the
consumer, we must study the margin of profitable expenditure, whether that be
the margin of a little expenditure applied to poor land and land far removed
from good markets, or the margin of a large expenditure applied to rich land,
and land near to dense industrial districts.
If only a little corn had been raised near the margin, a moderate fall in the
net price received by the farmer would not cause a great check to the supply of
corn. There would therefore be no great rise in the price paid for it by the
consumer; and the consumer would bear very little of the tax. But the surplus
value of the corn over its expenses of production would fall considerably. The
farmer, if cultivating his own land, would bear the greater part of the tax.
And, if he were renting the land, he could demand a great reduction of his rent.
If, on the other hand, a great deal of corn had been raised near the margin of
cultivation, the tax would tend to cause a great shrinkage of production. The
consequent rise of price would arrest that shrinkage, leaving the farmer in a
position to cultivate nearly as intensively as before: and the landlord's rent
would suffer but little.(5*)
Thus, on the one hand, a tax which is so levied as to discourage the cultivation
of land or the erection of farm buildings on it, tends to be shifted forward on
to the consumers of the produce of land. But, on the other hand, a tax on that
part of the (annual) value of land, which arises from its position, its
extension, its yearly income of sunlight and heat and rain and air, cannot
settle anywhere except on the landlord; a lessee being, of course, landlord for
the time. This (annual) value of the land is commonly called its "original
value" or its "inherent value"; but much of that value is the result of the
action of men, though not of its individual holders. For instance, barren heath
land may suddenly acquire a high value from the growth of an industrial
population near it; though its owners have left it untouched as it was made by
nature. It is, therefore, perhaps more correct to call this part of the annual
value of land its "public value"; while that part which can be traced to the
work and outlay of its individual holders may be called its "private value." The
old terms "inherent value" and "original value" may however be retained for
general use, with a note of caution as to their partial inaccuracy. And, using
another term that has precedent in its favour, we may speak of this annual
public value of the land as "true rent."
A tax on the public value of land does not greatly diminish the inducements to
cultivate the land highly, nor to erect farm buildings on it. Such a tax
therefore does not greatly diminish the supply of agricultural produce offered
on the market, nor raise the price of produce; and it is not therefore shifted
away from the owners of land.
This assumes that the true rent of land on which the tax is levied is assessed
with reference to its general capabilities, and not to the special use which the
owner makes of it: its net product is supposed to be that which could be got by
a cultivator of normal ability and enterprise, turning it to good account to the
best of his judgment. If an improved method of cultivation develops latent
resources of the soil, so as to yield an increased return much in excess of what
is required to remunerate the outlay with a good rate of profits; this excess of
net return above normal profits belongs properly to true rent: and yet, if it is
known, or even expected, that a very heavy special tax on true rent will be made
to apply to this excess income, that expectation may deter the owner from making
the improvement.(6*)
5. A little has been said incidentally of the competition between different
branches of industry for the same raw material or appliances for production. But
now we have to consider the competition between various branches of agriculture
for the same land. This case is simpler than that of urban land, because farming
is a single business so far as the main crops are concerned; though the rearing
of choice trees (including vines), flowers, vegetables etc. affords scope for
various kinds of specialized business ability. The classical economists were
therefore justified in provisionally supposing that all kinds of agricultural
produce can be regarded as equivalent to certain quantities of corn; and that
all the land will be used for agricultural purposes, with the exception of
building sites which are a small and nearly fixed part of the whole. But when we
concentrate our attention on any one product, as for instance, hops, it may seem
that a new principle is introduced. That is however not the case. Let us look
into this.
Hops are grown in varying rotations with other crops; and the farmer is often in
doubt whether he shall grow hops or something else on one of his fields. Thus
each crop strives against others for the possession of the land; and if any one
crop shows signs of being more remunerative than before relatively to others,
the cultivators will devote more of their land and resources to it. The change
may be retarded by habit, or diffidence, or obstinacy, or limitations of the
cultivator's knowledge; or by the terms of his lease. But it will still be true
in the main that each cultivator -- to recall once more the dominant principle
of substitution -- "taking account of his own means, will push the investment of
capital in his business in each several direction until what appears in his
judgment to be the margin of profitableness is reached; that is, until there
seems to him no good reason for thinking that the gains resulting from any
further investment in that particular direction would compensate him for his
outlay."
Thus in equilibrium, oats and hops and every other crop will yield the same net
return to that outlay of capital and labour, which the cultivator is only just
induced to apply. For otherwise he would have miscalculated; he would have
failed to get the maximum reward which his outlay can be made to yield: and it
would still be open to him to increase his gains by redistributing his crops, by
increasing or diminishing his cultivation of oats or some other crop.(7*)
This brings us to consider taxation in reference to the competition of different
crops for the use of the same land. Let us suppose that a tax is imposed on
hops, wherever grown; it is not to be a mere local rate or tax. The farmer can
evade a part of the pressure of the tax by lessening the intensity of his
cultivation of the land which he plants with hops; and a yet further part by
substituting another crop on land which he had proposed to devote to hops. He
will have recourse to this second plan in so far as he considers that he would
get a better result by growing another crop, and selling it free from the tax,
than by growing hops and selling them in spite of the tax. In this case the
surplus which he could obtain from the land by growing, say, oats upon it would
come into his mind when deciding where to set the limit to his production of
hops. But even here there would be no simple numerical relation between the
surplus, or rent, which the land would yield under oats, and the marginal costs
which the price of hops must cover. And a farmer whose land produced hops of
exceptionally high quality, and which happened to be in good condition at the
time for hops, would have no doubt at all that it was best to grow hops on the
land; though in consequence of the tax he might decide to curtail a little his
expenditure on it.(8*)
Meanwhile the tendency towards a general restriction in the supply of hops would
tend to raise their price. If the demand for them were very rigid, and hops of
adequate quality could not easily be imported from beyond the range of this
special tax, the price might rise by nearly the full amount of the tax. In that
case the tendency would be checked, and very nearly as much hops would be grown
as before the tax had been levied. And here, as in the case of a tax on
printing, recently discussed, the effect of a local tax is in strong contrast to
that of a general tax. For unless the local tax covered most of the ground in
the country on which good hops could be grown, its effect would be to drive them
beyond its boundary: very little revenue would be got from it, local farmers
would suffer a good deal, and the public would pay a rather higher price for
their hops.
6. The argument of the last section applies, so far as short periods are
concerned, to the earning power of farmbuildings and to other quasi-rents. When
existing farmbuildings, or other appliances which could be used in producing one
commodity are diverted to producing another because the demand for that is such
as to enable them to earn a higher income by producing it, then for the time the
supply of the first will be less, and its price higher than if the appliances
had not been able to earn a higher income by another use. Thus, when appliances
are capable of being used in more than one branch of agriculture, the marginal
cost in each branch will be affected by the extent to which these appliances are
called off for work in other branches. Other agents of production will be pushed
to more intensive uses in the first branch, in spite of a diminishing return;
and the value of its product will rise, because only at a higher value will the
price be in equilibrium. The increased earning power of the appliances due to
the external demand will appear to be the cause of this increase in value: for
it will cause a relative scarcity of the appliances in that branch of
production, and therefore raise marginal costs. And from this statement it
appears superficially to be a simple transition to the statement that the
increased earning power of the appliances enter into those costs which govern
value. But the transition is illegitimate. There will be no direct or numerical
relation between the increase in the price of the first commodity and the income
that the appliances can earn when they have been transferred to the second
industry and adapted for service in it.
Similarly, if a tax be put on factories used in one industry, some of them will
be diverted to other industries; and consequently the marginal costs and
therefore the values of the products in those industries will fall;
simultaneously with a temporary fall in net rental values of factories in all
uses. But these falls will vary in amount, and there will be no numerical
relation between the fall in the prices of the product and in these rents, or
rather quasi-rents.
These principles are not applicable to mines, whether for short periods or for
long. A royalty is not a rent, though often so called. For, except when mines,
quarries, etc., are practically inexhaustible, the excess of their income over
their direct outgoings has to be regarded, in part at least, as the price got by
the sale of stored-up goods -- stored up by nature indeed, but now treated as
private property; and therefore the marginal supply price of minerals includes a
royalty in addition to the marginal expenses of working the mine. Of course the
owner desires to receive the royalty without undue delay; and the contract
between him and the lessee often provides, partly for this reason, for the
payment of a rent as well as a royalty. But the royalty itself on a ton of coal,
when accurately adjusted, represents that diminution in the value of the mine,
regarded as a source of wealth in the future, which is caused by taking the ton
out of nature's storehouse.(9*)
NOTES:
1. Of course the character and extent of the improvements depends partly on the
conditions of land tenure, and the enterprise and ability and command over
capital on the part of landlords and tenants which existed at the time and place
in question. In this connection we shall find, when we come to study land
tenure, that there are large allowances to be made for the special conditions of
different places.
It may be noted, however, that rent proper is estimated on the understanding
that the original properties of the soil are unimpaired. And when the income
derived from improvements is regarded as a quasi-rent, it is to be understood
that they are kept up in full efficiency: if they are being deteriorated, the
equivalent of the injury done to them must be deducted from the income they are
made to yield before we can arrive at that Net income which is to be regarded as
their quasi rent.
That part of the income which is required to cover wear-and-tear bears some
resemblance to a royalty, which does no more than cover the injury done to a
mine by taking ore out of it.
2. Compare V, IX, section 5.
3. Compare III, V, section 3 and V, IV, section 2.
4. The relations between rent and profits engaged the attention of the
economists of the last generation; among whom may be specially mentioned Senior
and Mill, Hermann and Mangoldt. Senior seemed almost on the point of perceiving
that the key of the difficulty was held by the element of time: but here as
elsewhere he contented himself with suggestions; he did not work them out. He
says (Political Economy, p. 1 29), "for all useful purposes the distinction of
profits from rent ceases as soon as the capital from which a given revenue
arises has become, whether by gift or by inheritance, the property of a person
to whose abstinence and exertions it did not owe its creation." Again, Mill
says, Political Economy, Book III, ch. v, §4, "Any difference in favour of
certain producers or in favour of production in certain circumstances is the
source of a gain, which though not called rent unless paid periodically by one
person to another, is governed by laws entirely the same with it."
It has been well observed that a speculator, who, without manipulating prices by
false intelligence or otherwise, anticipates the future correctly; and who makes
his gains by shrewd purchases and sales on the Stock Exchange or in Produce
Markets, generally renders a public service by pushing forward production where
it is wanted, and repressing it where it is not: but that a speculator in land
in an old country can render no such public service, because the stock of land
is fixed. At the best he can prevent a site with great possibilities from being
devoted to inferior uses in consequence of the haste, ignorance, or
impecuniosity of those in control of it.
5. Of course the adjustments of rent to the true economic surplus from the land
are in practice slow and irregular. These matters are discussed in VI, sections
IX and X, and the incidence of a tax on grain under certain rather arbitrary
assumptions is studied in some detail in Appendix K.
6. The exemption of vacant building land from taxes on its full value retards
building. See Appendix G.
7. In so far as the farmer is producing raw material, or even human food, for
market, his distribution of resources between different uses is a problem of
business economy: in so far as he is producing for his own domestic consumption,
it is, in part at least, a problem of domestic economy. Compare above V, iv, §4.
It may be added that Note XIV in the Mathematical Appendix emphasizes the fact
that that distribution of outlay between different enterprises, which will give
a maximum aggregate return, is fixed by the same set of equations as that for
the similar problem in domestic economy.
Mill (Principles, III, XVI, 2), when discussing "joint products," observed that
all questions relating to the competition of crops for the possession of
particular soils are complicated by the rotation of crops and similar causes; an
intricate debit and credit account by double entry needs to be kept between the
various members of the rotation. Practice and shrewd instinct enable the farmer
to do this fairly well. The whole problem might be expressed in simple
mathematical phrases. But they would be tedious, and perhaps unfruitful. They
would therefore not be serviceable, so long as they remained abstract; though
they belong to a class which may ultimately be of good use in the higher science
of agriculture, when that has advanced far enough to fill in realistic details.
8. If for instance he reckoned that he could get a surplus of £30 above his
expenses (other than rent) in spite of the tax by growing hops, and a surplus of
only £20 above similar expenses by growing any other crop, it could not be trulv
said that the rent which the field could be made to yield by growing other
crops, "entered into" the marginal price of hops. But it is easier to interpret
the classical doctrine that "Rent does not enter into cost of production" in a
sense in which it is not true, and to scoff at it, than in the sense in which it
was intended and is true. It seems best therefore to avoid the phrase.
The ordinary man is offended by the old phrase that rent does not enter into the
price of oats; when he sees that an increase in the demand for land for other
uses, manifests itself in a rise of the rental value of all land in the
neighbourhood; leaves less land free for growing oats; consequently makes it
worth while to force larger crops of oats out of the remaining oat-land, and
thus raises the marginal expenses of oats and their price. A rise in rent does
serve as a medium through which the growing scarcity of land available for hops
and other produce obtrudes itself on his notice; and it is not worth while to
try to force him to go behind these symptoms of the change in conditions to the
truly operative causes. It is therefore inexpedient to say that the rent of land
does not enter into their price. But it is worse than inexpedient to say that
the rent of the land does enter into their price: that is false.
Jevons asks (Preface to Theory of Political Economy, p. liv): "If land which has
been yielding £2 per acre rent, as pasture, be ploughed up and used for raising
wheat, must not £2 per acre be debited against the expenses of production of
wheat;" The answer is in the negative. For there is no connection between this
particular sum of £2 and the expenses of production of that wheat which only
just pays its way. What should be said is: "When land capable of being used for
producing one commodity is used for producing another, the price of the first is
raised bv the consequent limitation of its field of production. The price of the
second will be the expenses of production (wages and profits) of that part of it
which only just pays its way, that which is produced on the margin of profitable
expenditure. And if for the purposes of any particular argument we take together
the whole expenses of the production on that land, and divide these among the
whole of the commodity produced; then the rent which we ought to count in is not
that which the land would pay if used for producing the first commodity, but
that which it does pay when used for producing the second."
9. See above, Book IV, chapter 3, note. Adam Smith is attacked by Ricardo for
putting rent on the same footing with wages and profits as parts of (money) cost
of production; and no doubt he does this sometimes. But yet he says elsewhere,
"Rent it is to be observed enters into the composition of the price of
commodities in a different way from wages and profit. High or low wages and
profit are the causes of high or low price: high or low rent is the effect of
it. It is because high or low wages and profit must be paid in order to bring a
particular commodity to market that its price is high or low. But it is because
its price is high or low a great deal more, or very little more, or no more than
what is sufficient to pay those wages and profits, that it affords a high rent,
or a low rent, or no rent at all." (Wealth of Nations, I, XI.) In this, as in
many other instances, he anticipated in one part of his writings truths which in
other parts he has seemed to deny.
Adam Smith discusses the "price at which coals can be sold for any considerable
time"; and contends that "the most fertile mine regulates the price of coals at
all other mines in the neighbourhood." His meaning is not clear; but he does not
appear to be referring to any temporary underselling; and he seems to imply that
the mines are leased at so much a year. Ricardo, following on apparently the
same lines, comes to the opposite conclusion that it "is the least fertile mine
which regulates price"; which is perhaps nearer the truth than Adam Smith's
doctrine. But in fact when the charge for the use of a mine is mainly in the
form of a royalty, neither proposition seems to be applicable. Ricardo was
technically right (or at all events not definitely wrong) when he said that rent
does not enter into the marginal cost of production of mineral produce. But he
ought to have added that if a mine is not practically inexhaustible, the income
derived from it is partly rent and partly royalty; and that though the rent does
not, the minimum royalty does enter directly into the expenses incurred on
behalf of every part of the produce, whether marginal or not.
The royalty is of course calculated in regard to those seams in the mine, which
are neither exceptionally rich and easy of working, nor exceptionally poor and
difficult. Some seams barely pay the expenses of working them; and some which
run short, or have a bad fault, do not even nearlv pav the wages of the labour
spent on them. The whole argument however implicitly assumes the conditions of
an old country. Professor Taussig is probably right when, having in view the
circumstances of a new country (Principles, II, p. 96), he "doubts whether any
payment at all can be secured by the owner of the very poorest mine, assuming he
has done nothing to develop it."
CHAPTER XI
MARGINAL COSTS IN RELATION TO URBAN VALUE
1. The last three chapters examined the relation in which cost of production
stands to the income derived from the ownership of the "original powers" of land
and other free gifts of nature, and also to that which is directly due to the
investment of private capital. There is a third class, holding an intermediate
position between these two, which consists of those incomes, or rather those
parts of incomes which are the indirect result of the general progress of
society, rather than the direct result of the investment of capital and labour
by individuals for the sake of gain. This class has to be studied now, with
special reference to the value of urban sites.
We have already noted that, though nature nearly always gives a less than
proportionate return, when measured by the amount of the produce raised, to
increasing applications of capital and labour in the cultivation of land; yet,
on the other hand, if the more intensive cultivation is the result of the growth
of a non-agricultural population in the neighbourhood, this very concourse of
people is likely to raise the value of produce. We have seen how this influence
opposes, and usually outweighs the action of the law of diminishing return when
the produce is measured according to its value to the producer and not according
to its amount; the cultivator gets good markets in which to supply his wants, as
well as good markets in which to sell, he buys more cheaply while he sells more
dearly, and the conveniences and enjoyments of social life are ever being
brought more within his reach.(1*)
Again, we have seen how the economies which result from a high industrial
organization(2*) often depend only to a small extent on the resources of
individual firms. Those internal economies which each establishment has to
arrange for itself are frequently very small as compared with those external
economies which result from the general progress of the industrial environment;
the situation of a business nearly always plays a great part in determining the
extent to which it can avail itself of external economies; and the situation
value which a site derives from the grow of a a rich and active population close
to it, or from the opening up of railways and other good means of communication
with existing markets, is the most striking of all the influences which changes
in the industrial environment exert on cost of production.
If in any industry, whether agricultural or not, two producers have equal
facilities in all respects, except that one has a more convenient situation than
the other, and can buy or sell in the same markets with less cost of carriage,
the differential advantage which his situation gives him is the aggregate of the
excess charges for cost of carriage to which his rival is put. And we may
suppose that other advantages of situation, such for instance as the near access
to a labour market specially adapted to his trade, can be translated in like
manner into money values. When this is done, and all are added together we have
the money value of the advantages of situation which the first business has over
the second: and this becomes its special situation value, if the second has no
situation value and its site is reckoned merely at agricultural value. The extra
income which can be earned on the more favoured site gives rise to what may be
called a special situation rent: and the aggregate site value of any piece of
building land is that which it would have if cleared of buildings and sold in a
free market. The "annual site value" -- to use a convenient, though not strictly
correct form of speaking -- is the income which that price would yield at the
current rate of interest. It obviously exceeds the special situation value,
merely by agricultural value; which is often an almost negligible quantity in
comparison.(3*)
2. It is obvious that the greater part of situation value is "public value."
There are however exceptional cases, which call for notice. Sometimes the
settlement of a whole town, or even district is planned on business principles,
and carried out as an investment at the expense and risk of a single person or
company. The movement may be partly due to philanthropic or religious motives,
but its financial basis will in any case be found in the fact that the concourse
of numbers is itself a cause of increased economic efficiency. Under ordinary
circumstances the chief gains arising from this efficiency would accrue to those
who are already in possession of the place: but the chief hopes of commercial
success, by those who undertake to colonize a new district or build a new town,
are usually founded on securing these gains for themselves.
When, for instance, Mr Salt and Mr Pullman determined to take their factories
into the country and to found Saltaire and Pullman City, they foresaw that the
land, which they could purchase at its value for agricultural purposes, would
obtain the special situation value which town property derives from the
immediate neighbourhood of a dense population. And similar considerations have
influenced those, who, having fixed upon a site adapted by nature to become a
favourite watering-place, have bought the land and spent large sums in
developing its resources: they have been willing to wait long for any net income
from their investment in the hope that ultimately their land would derive a high
situation value from the concourse of people attracted to it.(4*)
In all such cases the yearly income derived from the land (or at all events that
part of it which is in excess of the agricultural rent) is for many purposes to
be regarded as profits rather than rent. And this is equally true, whether the
land is that on which the factory itself at Saltaire or Pullman City is built,
or that which affords a high "ground-rent" as the site of a shop or store, whose
situation will enable it to do a brisk trade with those who work in the factory.
For in such cases great risks have to be run; and in all undertakings in which
there are risks of great losses, there must also be hopes of great gains. The
normal expenses of production of a commodity must include payment for the
ventures required for producing it, sufficient to cause those who are on the
margin of doubt whether to venture or not, to regard the probable net amount of
their gains net, that is, after deducting the probable amount of their losses as
compensating them for their trouble and their outlay. And that the gains
resulting from such ventures are not much more than sufficient for this purpose
is shown by the fact that they are not as yet very common. They are however
likely to be more frequent in those industries which are in the hands of very
powerful corporations. A large railway company, for instance, can found a Crewe
or a New Swindon for manufacturing railway plant without running any great
risk.(5*)
Some what similar instances are those of a group of landowners who combine to
make a railway, the net traffic receipts of which are not expected to pay any
considerable interest on the capital invested in making it; but which will
greatly raise the value of their land. In such cases part of the increase of
their incomes as landowners ought to be regarded as profits on capital which
they have invested in the improvement of their land: though the capital has gone
towards making a railway instead of being applied directly to their own
property.
Other cases of like nature are main drainage schemes, and other plans for
improving the general condition of agricultural or town property, in so far as
they are carried out by the landowners at their own expense, whether by private
agreement or by the levying of special rates on themselves. Similar cases again
are found in the investment of capital by a nation in building up its own social
and political organization as well as in promoting the education of the people
and in developing its sources of material wealth.
Thus that improvement of the environment, which adds to the value of land and of
other free gifts of nature, is in a good many cases partly due to the deliberate
investment of capital by the owners of the land for the purpose of raising its
value; and therefore a portion of the consequent increase of income may be
regarded as profits when we are considering long periods. But in many cases it
is not so; and any increase in the net income derived from the free gifts of
nature which was not brought about by, and did not supply the direct motive to,
any special outlay on the part of the landowners, is to be regarded as rent for
all purposes.
Cases somewhat analogous to these arise when the owner of a score or more of
acres in the neighbourhood of a growing town "develops" them for building. He
probably lays out the roads, decides where houses are to be continuous, and
where detached; and prescribes the general style of architecture, and perhaps
the minimum expenditure on each house; for the beauty of each adds to the
general value of all. This collective value, thus created by him, is of the
nature of public value; and it is dependent, for the greater part, on that
dormant public value, which the site as a whole derived from the growth of a
prosperous town in its neighbourhood. But yet that share of it which results
from his forethought, constructive faculty and outlay, is to be regarded as the
reward of business enterprise, rather than as the appropriation of public value
by a private person.
These exceptional cases must be reckoned with. But the general rule holds that
the amount and character of the building put upon each plot of land is, in the
main (subject to the local building bylaws), that from which the most profitable
results are anticipated, with little or no reference to its reaction on the
situation value of the neighbourhood. In other words the site value of the plot
is governed by causes which are mostly beyond the control of him who determines
what buildings shall be put on it: and he adjusts his expenditure on it to his
estimates of the income to be derived from various descriptions of buildings on
it.
3. The owner of building land sometimes builds on it himself: sometimes he sells
it outright: very often he lets it at a fixed ground-rent for ninety-nine years,
after which the land and the buildings on it (which by covenant must be kept in
good repair) revert to his successor in title. Let us consider what governs the
value at which he can sell the land and the ground-rent at which he can let it.
The capitalized value of any plot of land is the actuarial "discounted" value of
all the net incomes which it is likely to afford, allowance being made on the
one hand for all incidental expenses, including those of collecting the rents,
and on the other for its mineral wealth, its capabilities of development for any
kind of business, and its advantages, material, social and aesthetic, for the
purposes of residence. The money equivalent of that social status and those
other personal gratifications which the ownership of land affords, does not
appear in the returns of the money income derived from it, but does enter into
its capital money value.(6*)
Next let us consider what governs the "ground-rent" which the owner can obtain
for a plot which he lets on, say, a ninety-nine years' building lease. The
present discounted value of all the fixed money payments under that lease tends
to be equal to the present capital value of the land; after deducting, firstly,
for the obligation to return the land with the buildings on it to the successor
in title of the present owner at the end of the lease, and secondly for the
possible inconvenience of any restrictions on the use of the land contained in
the lease. In consequence of these deductions the ground-rent would be rather
less than the "annual site value" of the land, if that site value were expected
to remain fixed throughout. But in fact the site value is expected to rise in
consequence of the growth of population, and other causes: and therefore the
ground-rent is generally a little above the annual site value at the beginning
of the lease, and much below it towards the end.(7*)
Among the estimated outgoings on account of any building, which have to be
deducted from its estimated gross yield before deciding what is the value of the
privilege of erecting it on any given plot of land, are the taxes (central and
local) which may be expected to be levied on the property, and to be paid by the
owner of the property. But this raises difficult side-issues, which are
postponed to Appendix G.
4. Let us revert to the fact that the law of diminishing return applies to the
use of land for the purposes of living and working on it in all trades.(8*) Of
course in the trade of building, as in agriculture, it is possible to apply
capital too thinly. Just as a homesteader may find that he can raise more
produce by cultivating only a half of the 160 acres allotted to him than by
spreading his labour over the whole, so even when ground has scarcely any value,
a very low house may be dear in proportion to its accommodation. But, as in
agriculture, there is a certain application of capital and labour to the acre
which gives the highest return, and further applications after this give a less
return, so it is in building. The amount of capital per acre which gives the
maximum return varies in agriculture with the nature of the crops, with the
state of the arts of production, and with the character of the markets to be
supplied; and similarly in building, the capital per square foot which would
give the maximum return, if the site had no scarcity value, varies with the
purpose for which the building is wanted. But when the site has a scarcity
value, it is worth while to go on applying capital beyond this maximum rather
than pay the extra cost of land required for extending the site. In places where
the value of land is high, each square foot is made to yield perhaps twice the
accommodation, at more than twice the cost, that it would be made to give, if
used for similar purposes where the value of land is low.
We may apply the phrase the margin of building to that accommodation which it is
only just worth while to get from a given site, and which would not be got from
it if land were less scarce. To fix the ideas, we may suppose this accommodation
to be given by the top floor of the building.(9*)
By erecting this floor, instead of spreading the building over more ground, a
saving in the cost of land is effected, which just compensates for the extra
expense and inconvenience of the plan. The accommodation given by this floor,
when allowance has been made for its incidental disadvantages, is only just
enough to be worth what it costs without allowing anything for the rent of land;
and the expenses of production of the things raised on this floor, if it is part
of a factory, are just covered by their price; there is no surplus for the rent
of land. The expenses of production of manufactures may then be reckoned as
those of the goods which are made on the margin of building, so as to pay no
rent for land. That is to say the rent of the land does not enter into that set
of expenses at the margin at which the action of the forces of demand and supply
in governing value may be most clearly seen.
Suppose, for instance, that a person is planning a hotel or a factory; and
considering how much land to take for the purpose. If land is cheap he will take
much of it; if it is dear he will take less and build high. Suppose him to
calculate the expenses of building and working his establishment with frontages
of 100 and 110 feet respectively, in ways equally convenient on the whole to
himself, his customers and employees, and therefore equally profitable to
himself. Let him find that the difference between the two plans, after
capitalizing future expenditure, shows an advantage of £500 in favour of the
larger area; he will then be inclined to take the larger if the land is to be
got at less than £50 per foot of frontage, but not otherwise; and £50 will be
the marginal value of land to him. He might have reached this result by
calculating the increased value of the business that could be done with the same
outlay in other respects on the larger site as compared with the smaller, or
again by building on less expensive ground instead of in a more favourable
situation. But, by whatever route he makes his calculation, its character is
similar to that by which he decides whether it is worth his while to buy
business plant of any other kind: and he regards the net income (allowance being
made for depreciation) which he expects to get from either investment as
standing in the same general relation to his business; and if the advantages of
the situation are such, that all the land available on it can find employments
of different kinds in each of which its marginal use is represented by a capital
value of £50 per foot of frontage, then that will be the current value of the
land.
5. This assumes that the competition for land for various uses will cause
building in each locality and for each use to be carried up to that margin, at
which it is no longer profitable to apply any more capital to the same site. As
the demand for residential and business accommodation in a district increases,
it becomes worth while to pay a higher and higher price for land, in order to
avoid the expense and inconvenience of forcing more accommodation from the same
ground area.
For instance, if the value of land in, say, Leeds rises because of the increased
competition for it by shops, ware. then a woollen manufacturer finding houses,
iron works, etc., his expenses of production increased, may move to another town
or into the country; and thus leave the land on which he used to work to be
built over with shops and warehouses, for which a town situation is more
valuable than it is for factories. For he may think that the saving in the cost
of land that he will make by moving into the country, together with other
advantages of the change, will more than counterbalance its disadvantages. In a
discussion as to whether it was worth while to do so, the rental value of the
site of his factory would be reckoned among the expenses of production of his
cloth; and rightly.
But we have to go behind that fact. The general relations of demand and supply
cause production to be carried up to a margin at which the expenses of
production (nothing being entered for rent) are so high that people are willing
to pay a high value for additional land in order to avoid the inconvenience and
expense of crowding their work on to a narrow site. These causes govern site
value; and site value is therefore not properly regarded as governing marginal
costs.
Thus the industrial demand for land is in all respects parallel to the
agricultural. The expenses of production of oats are increased by the fact that
land, which could yield good crops of oats, is in great demand for growing other
crops that enable it to yield a higher rent: and in the same way the
printing-presses, which may be seen at work in London some sixty feet above the
ground, could afford to do their work a little cheaper if the demand for ground
for other uses did not push the margin of building up so high. Again a
hop-grower may find that on account of the high rent which he pays for his land,
the price of his hops will not cover their expenses of production where he is,
and he may abandon hop-growing, or seek other land for it; while the land that
he leaves may perhaps be let to a market-gardener. After a while the demand for
land in the neighbourhood may again become so great that the aggregate price
which the market-gardener obtains for his produce will not pay its expenses of
production, including rent; and so he in his turn makes room for, say, a
building compa