The
Relevance of John Locke’s View
on Personal Identity Over Time to
Edwards
and Adamic Imputation
Adam C. Parker
Introduction
Orthodox and classic
Christianity always will have its opponents.
This is due to the nature of humanity, which tends to reject the
sovereign God in every possible way.
Thus, it is not surprising when men choose to deify themselves and
denigrate the God who made them. In the
18th Century, Jonathan Edwards fought off such enemies of the
faith. At this particular time, these
people attacked the concept of original sin.
Particularly – they asked – is it fair that I am responsible for
a sin that Adam (the first man) committed?
It is within Edwards’ answer to this incredible challenge that we find
the thought of John Locke. Though in
the final analysis we will see that Edwards’ answer trods its own path never
before followed. We will find that his
answer actually stems from an eventual rejection of Locke’s view
of personal identity. It is nonetheless
crucial to grasp how this intellectual giant answered the challenges he
encountered.
Attacks by Dr. John Taylor,
a liberal Arminian scholar from England, prompted the writings of perhaps the
two greatest Reformed writings of the 18th Century: The Freedom of
the Will and Original Sin.
Both of these were written while Edwards ministered among the Indians in
Stockbridge, Massachusetts. It has been
said by Notre Dame scholar George Marsden that The Freedom of the Will,
in and of itself, prevented and even diminished the spread of Arminianism in
the American colonies for well over a hundred years. Further, he says, “its power…was a significant factor in the
intellectual resilience and influence of Calvinism in America well into the
nineteenth century” (Marsden 446).
In Dr. Taylor’s Attack, he charged that the imputation of Adam’s sin to his posterity is unjust and unreasonable for the rather simple reason that Adam and his posterity are not one and the same.
For the purposes of our present discussion,
let us define the word “impute.” Romans
5:13 says, “For until the law sin was in the world, but sin is not imputed
where there is no law.” The Greek word,
which Paul uses in this particular passage, is ellogeo, which is
translated “to reckon, attribute, impute, put on account.” In light of this, let us define imputation
of sin as “that by which God regards an individual as a sinner.” The Christian church has held many different
views of how or why Adamic sin is imputed to his offspring. Briefly, let us examine the different
possible theories of imputation offered throughout church history.
Pelagians
and Socinians
By Berkhof’s estimation, the
Pelagians, as well as the Socians deny any real connection between Adam’s sin
and our own. For them, the only
connection between Adam’s sin and the sin of the remainder of humanity is that
of an evil example, which we all emulate, though we are free to stop sinning,
if only we would choose to stop. Each
individual is regarded as sinful as soon as they commit an actual sin in
practice.
The Semi-Pelagians and some
early Arminians believe that all human beings have inherited a natural
inability from Adam, but that these human beings are not responsible for their
inability, and thus, no guilt attaches to it.
It may even be said, under this view, that God is in a way under
obligation to provide a cure for it.
The Wesleyan Arminians admit that this inborn corruption also
involves guilt.
1)
God
ordained that in the pre-fall covenant, Adam would stand in, not only for
himself, but also for his offspring.
Thus, he was head of the race, not only in a physical/parental role, but
also in a federal role.
2)
The
covenant commanded obedience, yet guaranteed that persistent perseverance for a
certain period of time would be rewarded with a fixation of Adam’s state in one
of permanent holiness and perfect happiness.
3)
Obedience
to the covenant would have resulted in a just claim to life eternal, not only
for Adam, but also for his descendants.
Thus, there were many benefits to the covenant, but there were also many
risks which were involved.
4)
Transgression
of the covenant would (and did) result in the opposite of eternal life: eternal
death. Just as the arrangement would result
in life for his offspring, it also would (and did) result in eternal death to
his offspring.
5)
“In
his right judgment, God imputes the guilt of the first sin, committed by the
head of the covenant, to all those that are federally related to him. As a result, they are born in a depraved and
sinful condition as well, and this inherent corruption also involves guilt.”
6)
Only
the “first sin of Adam, and not his following sins nor the sins of our other
forefathers is imputed to us. Also,
this teaching safeguards the sinlessness of Jesus” (Paraphrased & Quoted;
Berkhof 241-243).
The Federal Head view tells us that God constituted humanity with one man as the “stand-in” or leader, upon whose decision humanity would rise or fall. Essentially, the Federal Head view says, God chose Adam to represent all of us. This view appeals to God’s right to constitute nature in whatever way He pleases.
The Edwardsian assessment of
Adamic Imputation can only be properly seen in light of 1) the previously
discussed apologetic challenges from which his view arose, and 2) the Lockian
view of personal identity, which Edwards rejected. The reason for Locke’s importance will become clearer once a
brief investigation has been completed.
However, it is helpful to have an understanding of the fact that Edwards
looks, and sounds just like his predecessors within the Reformed tradition,
with regard to imputation. In an
unpublished sermon on Romans 5:12-21, we read:
As
this place in general is plain and full, so the doctrine of the corruption of
nature, as derived from Adam, and also the imputation of his first sin, are
both clearly taught in it. The
imputation of Adam’s one transgression is indeed most directly and frequently
asserted.
In another unpublished
manuscript on Luke 13:5, Edwards refers to Adam’s sin, saying that Adam was our
“representative who stood in our room.”
Here, we see in Edwards’ writings, a strong tendency to use the language
of the traditional Reformed view of imputation. It is only when pressed about the unfairness of God’s so
constituting the nature of humanity, that Edwards elaborates, and thus,
distinguishes his views – in a sense – from his predecessors.
It is perhaps impossible for
us to gauge the immense influence of John Locke upon the thought of the great
Puritan genius, Jonathan Edwards. In
order to do so, we would have to read, not only the hundreds of published
sermons and books which we have available, but it would be best if we could
also read the hundreds (perhaps thousands) of unpublished manuscripts which
are, to this day, being compiled and transcripted by Edwardsian scholars at
Yale.
One who is well versed in
the writings of Edwards is aware of a strong influence that came in the form of
the philosophical writings of John Locke, who died two years before Edwards was
born. According to one of Edwards’
journals, he was so excited when he picked up An Inquiry Concerning Human
Understanding that as a teenager he read it through several times. As an empiricist, Locke did not believe in
pre-existing notions or innate ideas.
For Locke, all ideas are obtained either through the senses, or by
reflection upon ideas – which still arrive via the sensory organs. This concept, in particular, impressed
itself upon Edwards. Edwardsian
scholars John Gerstner and Perry Miller believe that in many respects, Edwards
“christianized” the somewhat secular thought of the British empiricist.
Locke believed that a
person’s identity consisted in this: continuation of consciousness. As long as a person held preserved memories
of their own past, with no break in consciousness, then that person’s identity
could be established or held certain.
To be sure, there are many other aspects to Lockean identity. For example, Locke believed that
transmigration of the soul was possible.
Transmigration is the idea that a person’s soul could leave their body,
and become united to another body. The
person’s identity would remain the same, however, since the person’s consciousness
never ceases operation. Entire books
could (and probably have been) be written on the subject, but for the present
purposes, this short summary will do nicely.
One of the very first
recorded writings of Edwards was in a writing entitled The Mind. Here, one quite plainly and simply sees the
blunt, unapologetic influence of Locke.
Edwards writes:
Well might Mr. Locke say that
identity of person consisted in identity of consciousness; for he might have
said that identity of spirit, too, consisted in the same consciousness. A mind or spirit is nothing else but
consciousness, and what is included in it.
The same consciousness is to all intents and purposes the very same
spirit or substance, as much as the same particle of matter can be the same
with itself at different times.
In this early writing in On
The Mind, Edwards expresses a sympathetic tendency towards Locke’s view of
personal identity. Here, one finds Edwards’ initial doctrine of personality,
one that – as we shall see – Edwards eventually rejected en toto.
Edwards Rejects Lockean Personality
Before I begin with this next reading of Edwards,
please forgive the length of the chosen quotation. Its contents are wholly relevant and extremely crucial to our
understanding of Edwards’ own edition of personal identity.
Identity
of person is what seems never yet to have been explained. It is a mistake that it consists in sameness
or identity of consciousness, if by sameness of consciousness be meant having
the same ideas hereafter that I have now, with a notion or apprehension that I
had had them before, just in the same manner as I now have the same ideas that
I had in time past by memory.
Here, Edwards has offered us
a somewhat fair representation of the view he is about to reject. The quote continues:
It
is possible without doubt in the nature of things for God to annihilate me, and
after my annihilation to create another being that shall have the same in his
mind that I have, and with the like apprehension that he had had them before in
like manner as a person has by memory; and yet I be in no way concerned in it,
having no reason to fear what that being shall suffer, or to hope for what he
shall enjoy. Can anyone deny that it is
possible, after my annihilation, to create two beings in the universe, both of
them having my ideas communicated to them with such a notion of their having
had them before, after the manner of memory, and yet be ignorant one of
another? And in such case, will anyone
say that both these are one and the same person, as they must be if they are
both the same person with me? It is
possible there may be two such beings, each having all the ideas that are now
in my mind in the same manner that I should have by memory if my own being were
continued, and yet these two beings not only be ignorant one of another, but
also be in a very different state, one in a state of enjoyment and pleasure,
and the other in a state of great suffering and torment…Will anyone say that
[these], in such a case, [are] the same person with me, when I know nothing of
[their] suffering and am never the better for [their] joys? (Gerstner 325-326)
…God’s upholding created
substance, or causing its existence in each successive moment, is altogether
equivalent to an immediate production out of nothing, at each moment…
(193).
But how does this teaching intersect with
personal identity and imputation? Each
person is at each moment being created by God.
This means that the only way that any individual exists is by divine
appointment. “We are constantly being
recreated. God is constantly
constituting our identity. Why be
surprised if God appointed an identity of the human race with a particular
individual? God alone is the Creator
and identifier of men” (197).
Most of Edwards’ statements
of this doctrine appear in his writings in Original Sin, though one can
also find the vein of Edwardsian Personality running through other aspects of
his writing. Primarily, one sees his deviation
from the Reformed tradition with the example of the tree and its roots.
So root and branches being
one, according to God’s wise constitution, the case in fact is, that by virtue
of this oneness answerable changes or effects through all
the branches coexist
with the changes in the root: consequently an evil disposition exists in
the hearts of Adam’s posterity, equivalent to that which was exerted in his own
heart, when he eat the forbidden fruit (Edwards 221).
In the context of this
section of Original Sin, Edwards is stressing the fairness of the
constitution of mankind, placing Adam as the root, and humanity as the tree
that springs from that root. In a
sermon on Revelation 19:2-3, Edwards stresses a person’s guilt, even if he is involved
or has a hand in another’s sin. The
question then arises, “did we have a hand in Adam’s sin?” According to Gerstner, “He goes on to prove
not only that we had a hand in Adam’s sin but that it was our sin; we committed
it.” George Parks Fisher comments
regarding Edwards’ view, “The sin of apostasy is not theirs merely because God imputes
it to them, but because it is truly and properly theirs, and on that ground
God imputes it to them” (Fisher 284-303).
If Fisher’s assessment holds, then Edwards’ view should not be regarded
as a view of imputation but instead as a view of identity.
Listen to the undertones of
Edwardsian Identity in the following quotation from his sermon on Romans 7:14:
Adam’s posterity came by the
corruption of nature by God’s withholding his Spirit and image from them
judicially for their breach of the first covenant. It is not derived down naturally but God withholds his Spirit
from them in judgment for their first sin viz. for their eating the
forbidden fruit…They are looked upon as having eaten the forbidden fruit as
well as Adam. They transgressed
in Adam and therefore are subject to the same judgment (Gerstner 327).
He here refers to us –
Adam’s posterity – as having actually committed the sin of eating the first
fruit. For Edwards, we have all eaten
the forbidden fruit. We all – humanity
as a whole – had our hand in Adam’s first sin. Gerstner comments: “Edwards
[here] is clearly departing from the Reformed tradition fundamentally, and
seems fully aware of it. Here the
problem is not that the reformed tradition tended to be silent about the
subject, but that the solution it offered did not satisfy Edwards.”
We should view and judge Edwards’ perspective
in light of his intention in formulating this view. It would appear that Edwards saw himself as a champion of the
classic Reformed doctrine of imputation.
He did, however, perceive what could be considered a “weak spot” in the
doctrine, which he saw himself as “safeguarding.” In this light, we should look at Edwards’ view as an addition or
addendum to what was already an accurate and biblical perspective on humanity’s
sinful condition. His view was not a
replacement, nor was it challenge, but rather an addition. My primary rationale for adopting this
assessment is based upon the many affirmations, which Edwards makes, favorable
to the traditional view. If Edwards
thought that his view should subvert or replace the traditional view, then
surely he would have spoken against it or challenged its validity, yet one does
not find such offensive statements in Edwards’ published works, to be
sure. As I stated earlier, it would
seem that Edwards saw his contribution as complementing, not subverting classic
orthodox imputation.
With regard to this matter, the words of
Scripture are always our roadmap, and our inerrant guide to knowing truth about
God. As such, I close with the words of
the Apostle Paul, our great theologian and forerunner:
Therefore, just as through
one man sin entered into the world, and death through sin, and thus death
spread to all men, because all sinned…Therefore, as through one man’s
offense judgment came to all men, resulting in condemnation, even so through
one Man’s righteous act the free gift came to all men, resulting in
justification of life. For as by one
man’s disobedience many were made sinners, so also by one Man’s obedience many
will be made righteous (Romans 5:12, 18-19; my emphasis).
Works
Cited
Berkhof, Louis Systematic Theology. (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1977).
Edwards, Jonathan The Works of Jonathan Edwards Volume I (Peabody, MA: Hendrickson, 2003).
Fisher, George, “The Philosophy of Jonathan Edwards.” Discussions in History and Philosophy. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1974).
Gerstner, John H. The Rational Biblical Theology of Jonathan Edwards. Volume 2 (Orlando: Ligonier, 1992).
Marsden, George M. Jonathan Edwards: A Life. (Yale University, 2003).