George Berkeley, in his three
fictitious dialogues between Hylas and Philonous, presents the world with
the disturbing conclusion that there is no material world and that the
term “material” is both absurd and meaningless. In the dialogues,
Berkeley speaks through Philonous and responds to any possible objection
that he can think of. The objections are voiced by the character
called Hylas. All throughout, Hylas is trying to take out immaterialism
by throwing at it every single argument possible from physical evidence
in the world to spiritual issues to the nature of God to the nature of
men. Philonous responds to every objection by either clarifying his
own perspective or calling Hylas’s ridiculous. Is Berkeley correct
though? Did he manage to produce a flawless and undefeatable argument
for immaterialism, or is his back not as covered as he thinks it is?
We shall see.
The initial argument that
Berkeley presents states that the only things that we can know are the
things that we can perceive with our senses and/or reflect upon.
These things are immaterial. Immaterial things can be perceived through
any or all of the following methods: hearing, seeing, tasting, touching
or smelling. Characteristics or qualities that we can perceive immediately
through our senses are known as secondary characteristics. We may argue
that there are aspects or characteristics like extension or motion that
go beyond these five senses. However, Berkeley points out that these
primary characteristics are reducible to any one of the secondary characteristics.
Material things, or matter, are things that we cannot perceive with our
senses. Because we cannot perceive them, we cannot know them, and
because we cannot know them, we cannot reflect on them. Therefore,
because they are unknowable, they don’t exist. To put this all another
way – those things which are immaterial (perceivable) are mind dependent
and those things which are material (not perceivable) are mind independent.
No thing exists that is not mind dependent, therefore mind independent,
or material, things do not exist.
Hylas brings up the question
of what would happen if Philonous were annihilated. Although it is
presented as an argument, it serves as more of a question of clarification.
Is Philonous really so arrogant as to believe that the existence of all
things depends upon any one person perceiving it, or is there some grand
unifying perceiver? Philonous responds with the statement that immaterial
things do not depend upon him perceiving them, but that they are being
perceived by something – and that something must at the bare minimum be
God. God is understood to be omni-benevolent, omniscient, omnipotent
and omnipresent. On these grounds, nothing could exist without him
being aware of it, and therefore, because it couldn’t, it doesn’t.
This also provides the argument that not only do material things not exist,
they can’t. At least not as long as God is who we think He must be.
Stemming from this point,
Hylas brings up another argument in an attempt to take out Philonous’s
immaterialistic claims by attacking what Philonous says God is in contrast
with what he depicts Him as. Philonous states that God is the cause
of all things in nature, and His existence and continued perception of
all creation is the only thing that keeps it around. In a disturbing
observation, Hylas raises the question of evil. If God is the cause
of everything, evil must also be pinned on Him. This defies what
has already been established about God’s character – namely omni-benevolence.
If this characteristic of God can be proved false, other aspects such as
omniscience and omnipresence can possibly fall as well. Without the
omniscience and omnipresence of God, there is no “grand unifying perceiver”,
and without this, there is no assurance that if we, the perceiver are annihilated,
anything will continue to exist. However, if it did (continue to
exist), it would be mind dependent and therefore matter. Such a thing
destroys Philonous’s philosophy completely.
Philonous responds by saying
that God did not create evil, but created the means for it to become a
possibility. It is because of him that it is possible to kill, but
that does not mean that he is direct cause of it – he is simply the cause
of the means. It is we, as humans, who have taken (through Nature)
the amoral things that God created and twisted them into evil. He
implies that although we exist because of and within God, we are not puppets.
His nature accommodates our will, and it is our will that causes evil.
The nature of God within Philonous’s immaterialism is defended and Philonous
is safe on that front.
Hylas doesn’t quite buy
the concept the material things do not exist. It sounds suspicious
to him that just because a thing is mind independent it follows that it
cannot exist. One of his objections to Philonous comes in the form
of the question that he (Hylas) is aware of ideas that he has that he could
neither have produced on his own nor could they have produced themselves.
He claims that it would then follow that because they did not come from
either from him or themselves, they must have come from matter. To
expound – in this argument, Hylas implies a trilemma. All ideas that
he has must have an origin that they are produced from. The options
are that he, himself, produced them, they produced themselves, or they
were formed from a conglomeration of sensations and reflections on a pre-existing
something-or-other. He rules out the possibility that he could have
produced them based on the preexisting supposition that we simply cannot
create ideas and then rules out the possibility of these ideas producing
themselves from nothing due to the fact that ideas are always either causes
or effects and sometimes both, but never simply stand on their own.
The process of elimination leaves us with the third possibility standing.
Because it is neither number one nor number two, it must be number three.
This “pre-existing something-or-other” is what Hylas deems “matter.”
Philonous’s response to
this is simply to deny that what Hylas is referring to is matter.
He acknowledges that the argument is valid, but he doesn’t like the definition
of one of the words in the conclusion. He simply says that matter
is inactive, and because something that is inactive cannot be a cause,
matter is not what Hylas is referring to. A point that he makes but
Hylas fails to push him on is the concept of something inactive not being
able to produce an effect. Philonous’s very words are “How can something
unthinking be a cause of thought?” This point is very weak.
I see a chair in front of me – it’s not thinking (because, being a purely
physical thing lacking any sort of mind, it is unable to do so), and yet
I’m thinking about it. Based on this counterexample alone, Philonous’s
whole response to Hylas’s objection is nullified. It is true that
a non-thinking thing can be a cause of thought – if it wasn’t there and
never was, we couldn’t think about it.
Sadly, the weakness of
this point has very little observable effect on the overall argument.
It hints that Philonous may not have any idea what he’s talking about in
this regard, but this does little to injure his opinion of the existence
of matter. The most this does is weaken his credibility, but it does
not weaken the actual argument for immaterialism that he presents.
We have failed to produce
any evidence that might discredit the “Grand Unifying Perceiver” (who is
the glue that holds the entire theory together) or prove that there are
mind independent things. Although chopping out either of these pillars
could have completely destroyed immaterialism, neither approach proved
possible. It can be concluded, therefore, that due to a lack of any
debilitating evidence, Berkeley (through Philonous) must be correct. |