. |
Measures
of sterilization should, in my opinion, be very definitely confined to persons who are
mentally defective. I cannot favor laws such as that of Idaho, which allows sterilization
of 'mental defectives, epileptics, habitual criminals, moral degenerates, and sex
perverts.' The last two categories here are very vague, and will be determined differently
in different communities. The law of Idaho would have justified the sterilization of
Socrates, Plato, Julius Caesar, and St. Paul. (M.M.p259/60) In addition to the general argument against faith,
there is something peculiarly odious in the contention that the principles of the Sermon
on the Mount are to be adopted with a view to making atom bombs more effective. If I were
a Christian, I should consider this the absolute extreme of blasphemy. (H.S.E.P.)
If throughout your life you abstain from
murder, theft, fornication, perjury, blasphemy, and disrespect towards your parents, your
Church, and your king, you are conventionally held to deserve moral admiration even if you
have never done a single kind or generous or useful action. This very inadequate notion of
virtue is an outcome of tabu morality, and has done untold harm. (H.S.E.P.p40)
The Russian Government appears to think
that Soviet decrees can change the laws of genetics; the Vatican apparently believes that
ecclesiastical decrees could secure adequate nourishment for all even if there were only
standing room on the planet. Such opinions, to my mind, represent a form of insane
megalomania entirely alien to the scientific spirit. (N.H.C.W.p27)
Christ said 'Thou shalt love thy neighbor
as thyself,' and when asked 'who is thy neighbor?' went on to the parable of the Good
Samaritan. If you wish to understand this parable as it was understood by His hearers, you
should substitute 'German' or 'Japanese' for 'Samaritan.' I fear many present-day
Christians would resent such a substitution, because it would compel them to realize how
far they have departed from the teaching of the Founder of their religion. (U.E.p136)
Suppose atomic bombs had reduced the
population of the world to one brother and sister; should they let the human race die out?
I do not know the answer, but I do not think it can be in the affirmative merely on the
ground that incest is wicked. (H.S.E.P.p47.)
The whole conception of 'sin' is one I find
very puzzling, doubtless owing to my sinful nature. If 'sin' consisted in causing needless
suffering, I could understand, but on the contrary, sin often consists in avoiding
needless suffering. Some years ago, in the English House of Lords, a bill was introduced
to legalize euthanasia in cases of painful and incurable disease. The patient's consent
was to be necessary, as well as several medical certificates. To me, in my simplicity, it
would seem natural to require the patient's consent, but the late Archbishop of
Canterbury, the English official expert on sin, explained the erroneousness of such a
view. The patient's consent turns euthanasia into suicide, and suicide is sin. Their
Lordships listened to the voice of authority and rejected the bill. Consequently, to
please the Archbishop- and his God, if he reports truly victims of cancer still have to
endure months of wholly useless agony, unless their doctors or nurses are sufficiently
humane to risk a charge of murder. I find difficulty in the conception of a God who gets
pleasure from contemplating such tortures; and if there were a God capable of such wanton
cruelty, I should certainly not think Him worthy of worship. But that only proves how sunk
I am in moral depravity. (U.E.p76)
Has civilization taught us to be more
friendly towards one another? The answer is easy. Robins (the English, not the American
species) peck an elderly robin to death, whereas men (the English, not the American
species) give an elderly man an old-age pension. Within the herd we are more friendly to
each other than are many species of animals, but in our attitude towards those outside the
herd, in spite of all that has been done by moralists and religious teachers, our emotions
are as ferocious as those of any animal, and our intelligence enables us to give them a
scope which is denied to even the most savage beast. It may be hoped, though not very
confidently, that the more humane attitude will in time come to prevail, but so far the
omens are not very propitious. (U.E.p126)
There is in Aristotle an almost complete
absence of what may be called benevolence or philanthropy. The sufferings of mankind, in
so far as he is aware of them, do not move him emotionally; he holds them intellectually
to be an evil, but there is no evidence that they cause him unhappiness except when the
sufferers happen to be his friends. (H.W.P.p183/4)
Most stern moralists are in the habit of
thinking of pleasure as only of the senses, and, when they eschew the pleasures of sense,
they do not notice that the pleasures of power, which to men of their temperament are far
more attractive, have not been brought within the ban of their ascetic self-denial. It is
the prevalence of this type of psychology in forceful men which has made the notion of sin
so popular, since it combines so perfectly humility towards heaven with self-assertion
here on earth. The concept of sin has not the hold upon men's imaginations that it had in
the Middle Ages, but still dominates the thoughts of many clergymen, magistrates and
schoolmasters. When the great Dr. Arnold walked on the shores of Lake Como, it was not the
beauty of the scene that occupied his thoughts. He meditated, so he tells us, on moral
evil. I rather fear that it was the moral evil of school-boys rather than schoolmasters
that produced his melancholy reflections. However that may be, he was led to the
unshakable belief that it is good for boys to be flogged. One of the great rewards that a
belief in sin has always offered to the virtuous is the opportunity which it affords of
inflicting pain without compunction. (H.S.E.P.p195/6)
One of the 'grand' conceptions which have
proved scientifically useless is the soul. I do not mean that there is positive evidence
showing that men have no soul; I only mean that the soul, if it exists, plays no part in
any discoverable causal law. There are all kinds of experimental methods of determining
how men and animals behave under various circumstances. You can put rats in mazes and men
in barbed-wire cages, and observe their methods of escape. You can administer drugs and
observe their effect. You can turn a male rat into a female, though so far nothing
analogous has been done with human beings, even at Buchenwald. It appears that socially
undesirable conduct can be dealt with by medical means, or by creating a better
environment, and the conception of sin has thus come to seem quite unscientific, except,
of course, as applied to the Nazis. There is real hope that, by getting to understand the
science of human behavior, governments may be even more able than they are at present to
turn mankind into rabbles of mutually ferocious lunatics. (U.E.p133/4)
Cotton goods (after the industry became
scientific) could find a market in India and Africa: this was a stimulus to British
Imperialism. Africans had to be taught that nudity is wicked; this was done very cheaply
by missionaries. In addition to cotton goods we exported tuberculosis and syphilis, but
for them there was no charge. (I.S.S.p21)
As soon as we abandon our own reason, and
are content to rely upon authority, there is no end to our trouble. Whose authority? The
Old Testament? The New Testament? The Koran? In practice, people choose the book
considered sacred by the community in which they are born, and out of that book they
choose the parts they like, ignoring the others. At one time, the most influential text in
the Bible was: 'Thou shalt not suffer a witch to live.' Nowadays, people pass over this
text, in silence if possible; if not, with an apology. And so, even when we have a sacred
book, we still choose as truth whatever suits our own prejudices. No Catholic, for
instance, takes seriously the text which says that a Bishop should be the husband of one
wife. (U.E.p81/2)
Consider how much brutality has been
justified by the rhyme: "A dog, a wife, and a walnut tree, The more you beat them the
better they be." I have no experience of the moral effect of flagellation on walnut
trees, but no civilized person would now justify the rhyme as regards wives. The
reformative effect of punishment is a belief that dies hard, chiefly, I think, because it
is so satisfying to our sadistic impulses. (U.E.p148)
I had at one time a very bad fever of which
I almost died. In my fever I had a long consistent delirium. I dreamt that I was in Hell,
and that Hell is a place full of all those happenings that are improbable but not
impossible. The effects of this are curious. Some of the damned, when they first arrive
below, imagine that they will beguile the tedium of eternity by games of cards. But they
find this impossible, because, whenever a pack is shuffled, it comes out in perfect order,
beginning with the ace of spades and ending with the king of hearts. There is a special
department of Hell for students of probability. In this department there are many
typewriters and many monkeys. Every time that a monkey walks on a typewriter, it types by
chance one of Shakespeare's sonnets.... There is a peculiarly painful chamber inhabited
solely by philosophers who have refuted Hume. These philosophers, though in Hell, have not
learned wisdom. They continue to be governed by their animal propensity toward induction.
But every time that they have made an induction, the next instance falsifies it. This,
however, happens only during the first hundred years of their damnation. After that, they
learn to expect that an induction will be falsified, and therefore it is not falsified
until another century of logical torment has altered their expectation. Throughout all
eternity surprise continues, but each time at a higher logical level. (N.E.P.p30/1)
When we pass in review the opinions of
former times which are now recognized as absurd, it will be found that nine times out of
ten they were such as to justify the infliction of suffering. Take, for instance, medical
practice. When anesthetics were invented they were thought to be wicked as being an
attempt to thwart God's will. Insanity was thought to be due to diabolic possession, and
it was believed that demons inhabiting a madman could be driven out by inflicting pain
upon him, and so making them uncomfortable. In pursuit of this opinion, lunatics were
treated for years on end with systematic and conscientious brutality. I cannot think of
any instance of an erroneous medical treatment that was agreeable rather than disagreeable
to the patient. (U.E.p148)
The absence of any sharp line between men
and apes is very awkward for theology. When did men get souls? Was the Missing Link
capable of sin and therefore worthy of hell? Did Pithecanthropus Erectus have moral
responsibility? Was Homo Pekiniensis damned? (I.S.S.p15/6)
A man who uses what is called 'bad
language' is not from a rational point of view any worse than a man who does not.
Nevertheless practically everybody in trying to imagine a saint would consider abstinence
from swearing as essential. Considered in the light of reason this is simply silly. The
same applies to alcohol and tobacco. With regard to alcohol the feeling does not exist in
southern countries, and indeed there is an element of impiety about it, since it is known
that Our Lord and the Apostles drank wine. With regard to tobacco it is easier to maintain
a negative position, since all the greatest saints lived before its use was known. But
here also no rational argument is possible. The view that no saint would smoke is based in
the last analysis upon the view that no saint would do anything solely because it gave him
pleasure. (C.H.p99)
When Benjamin Franklin invented the
lightning-rod, the clergy, both in England and America, with enthusiastic support of
George III, condemned it as an impious attempt to defeat the will of God. For, as all
right-thinking people were aware, lightning is sent by God to punish impiety or some other
grave sin and the virtuous are never struck by lightning. Therefore if God wants to strike
anyone, Benjamin Franklin ought not to defeat His design; indeed, to do so is helping
criminals to escape. But God was equal to the occasion, if we are to believe the eminent
Dr. Price, one of the leading divines of Boston. Lightning having been rendered
ineffectual by the 'iron points invented by the sagacious Dr. Franklin,' Massachusetts was
shaken by earthquakes, which Dr. Price perceived to be due to God's wrath at the 'iron
points.' In a sermon on the subject he said, 'In Boston are more erected than elsewhere in
New England, and Boston seems to be more dreadfully shaken. Oh! There is no getting out of
the mighty hand of God.' Apparently, however, Providence gave up all hope of curing Boston
of its wickedness, for, though the lightning-rods became more and more common, earthquakes
in Massachusetts have remained rare. Nevertheless, Dr. Price's point of view, or something
very like it, was still held by one of the most influential men of recent times. When, at
one time, there were several bad earthquakes in India, Mahatma Gandhi solemnly warned his
compatriots that these disasters had been sent as a punishment for their sins. (U.E.p74/5)
There are logical difficulties in the
notion of Sin. We are told that Sin consists in acting contrary to God's commands, but we
are also told that God is omnipotent. If He is, nothing contrary to His will can occur;
therefore when the sinner disobeys His commands, He must have intended this to happen. St
Augustine boldly accepts this view, and asserts that men are led to sin by a blindness
with which God afflicts them. But most theologians, in modern times have felt that, if God
causes men to sin, it is not fair to send them to Hell for what they cannot help. We are
told that sin consists in acting contrary to God's will. This, however, does not get rid
of the difficulty Those who, like Spinoza, take God's omnipotence seriously, deduce that
there can be no such thing as Sin. This leads to frightful results. What! said Spinoza's
contemporaries, was it not wicked of Nero to murder his mother? Was it not wicked of Adam
to eat the apple? Is one action just as good as another? Spinoza wriggles, but does not
find any satisfactory answer If everything happens in accordance with God's will; God must
have wanted Nero to murder his mother; therefore, since God is good, the murder must have
been a good thing. From this argument there is no escape. (U.E.p80/1)
The Roman Catholic Church demands
legislation such that, if a woman becomes pregnant by a syphilitic man, she must not
artificially interrupt her pregnancy, but must allow a probably syphilitic child to be
born, in order that, after a few years of misery on earth, it may spend eternity in limbo
(assuming its parents to be non-Catholics). The British State considers it the duty of an
Englishman to kill people who are not English whenever a collection of elderly gentlemen
in Westminster tells him to do so. Such instances suffice to illustrate the fact that
Church and State are placable enemies of both intelligence and virtue. (E.S.O.p72)
Suppose we wish- as I certainly do- to find
arguments against Nietzsche's ethics and politics, what arguments can we find? . . . The
question is: If Buddha and Nietzsche were confronted, could either produce an argument
that ought to appeal to the impartial listener? I am not thinking of political arguments.
We can imagine them appearing before the Almighty, as in the first chapter of the Book of
Job, and offering advice as to the sort of world He should create. What could either say?
. Buddha would open the argument by speaking of the lepers, outcast and miserable; the
poor, toiling with aching limbs and barely kept alive by scanty nourishment; the wounded
in battle, dying in slow agony; the orphans, ill-treated by cruel guardians; and even the
most successful haunted by the thought of failure and death. From all this load of sorrow,
he would say, a way of salvation must be found, and salvation can only come through love.
. Nietzsche, whom only Omnipotence could restrain from interrupting, would- burst out when
his turn came: 'Good heavens, man, you must learn to be of tougher fiber. Why go about
sniveling because trivial people suffer. Or, for that matter, because great men suffer?
Trivial people suffer trivially, great men suffer greatly, they are noble. Your ideal is a
purely negative one, absence of suffering, which can be completely secured by
non-existence. I, on the other hand, have positive ideals: I admire Alcibiades, and the
Emperor Frederick II, and Napoleon. For the sake of such men, any misery is worth while. I
appeal to You, Lord, as the greatest of creative artists, do not let Your artistic
impulses be curbed by the degenerate, fear-ridden maunderings of this wretched
psychopath.'
. Buddha, who in the courts of Heaven has learnt all history since his death, and has
mastered science with delight in the knowledge and sorrow at the use to which men have put
it, replies with calm urbanity 'You are mistaken, Professor Nietzsche, in thinking my
ideal a purely negative one. True, it includes a negative element, the absence of
suffering; but it has in addition quite as much that is positive as is to be found in your
doctrine. Though I have no special admiration for Alcibiades and Napoleon, I too have my
heroes: My successor Jesus, because he told men to love their enemies; the men who
discovered how to master the forces of nature and secure food with less labor; the medical
men who have shown how to diminish disease; the poets and artists and musicians who have
caught glimpses of the Divine beatitude. Love and knowledge and delight in beauty are not
negations; they are enough to fill the lives of the great men that have ever lived.'
. 'All the same,' Nietzsche replies, 'your world would be insipid. You should study
Heraclitus, whose works survive complete in the celestial library. Your love is
compassion, which is elicited by pain; your truth, if you are honest, is pleasant, and
only to be known through suffering; and as to beauty, what is more beautiful than the
tiger, who owes his splendor to fierceness? No, if the Lord should decide for your world,
I fear we should all die of boredom.'
. 'You might,' Buddha replies, 'because you love pain, and your love of life is a sham.
But those who really love life would be happy as no one can be happy in the world as it
is.' (H.W.P.p770-2)
According to St. Thomas, evil is
unintentional, not as essence, and has an accidental cause which is good. All things tend
to be like God, who is the End of all things. Human happiness does not consist in carnal
pleasures, honor, glory, wealth, worldly power, or goods of the body, and is not seated in
the sense. Man's ultimate happiness does not consist in acts of moral virtue, because
these are means; it consists in the contemplation of God. But the knowledge of God
possessed by the majority does not suffice; nor the knowledge of Him obtained by faith. In
this life, we cannot see God in His essence, or have ultimate happiness; but hereafter we
shall see Him face to face. (Not literally, we are warned, because God has no face.) This
will happen not by our natural power, but by the divine light; and even then, we shall not
see all of Him. (H.W.P.p458/9)
Those who first advocated religious
toleration were thought wicked, and so were the early opponents of slavery. The Gospels
tell how Christ opposed the stricter forms of the Sabbath tabu. It cannot, in view of such
instances, be denied that some actions which we all think highly laudable consist in
criticizing or infringing the moral code of one's own community. Of course this only
applies to past ages or to foreigners; nothing of the sort could occur among ourselves,
since our moral code is perfect. (H.S.E.P.p39/40.)
Protestants tell us, or used to tell us,
that it is contrary to the will of God to work on Sundays. But Jews say that it is on
Saturdays that God objects to work. Disagreement on this point has persisted for nineteen
centuries, and I know no method of putting an end to the disagreement except Hitler's
lethal chambers, which would not generally be regarded as a legitimate method in
scientific controversy. Jews and Mohammedans assure us that God forbids pork, but Hindus
say that it is beef that he forbids. Disagreement on this point has caused hundreds of
thousands to be massacred in recent years. It can hardly be said, therefore, that the Will
of God gives a basis for an objective ethic. (H.S.E.P.p121)
I know men, by no means old, who, when in
infancy they were seen touching a certain portion of their body, were told with the utmost
solemnity: 'I would rather see you dead than doing that.' I regret to say that the effect
in producing virtue in later life has not always been all that conventional moralists
might desire. Not infrequently threats are used. It is perhaps not so common as it used to
be to threaten a child with castration, but it is still thought quite proper to threaten
him with insanity. Indeed, it is illegal in the State of New York to let him know that he
does not run the risk unless he thinks he does. The result of this teaching is that most
children in their earliest years have a profound sense of guilt and terror which is
associated with sexual matters. This association of sex with guilt and fear goes so deep
as to become almost or wholly unconscious. I wish it were possible to institute a
statistical inquiry, among men who believe themselves emancipated from such nursery tales,
as to whether they would be as ready to commit adultery during a thunderstorm as at any
other time. I believe that 90 per cent of them, in their heart of hearts, would think that
if they did so they would be struck by lightning. (M.M.p275/6)
The Platonic Socrates was a pattern to
subsequent Philosophers for many ages. What are we to think of him ethically: (I am
concerned only with the man as Plato portrays him.) His merits are obvious. He is
indifferent to worldly success, so devoid of fear that he remains calm and urbane and
humorous to the last moment, caring more for what he believes to be truth than for
anything else whatever. He has, however, some grave defects. He is dishonest and
sophistical in argument, and in his private thinking he uses intellect to prove
conclusions that are to him agreeable, rather than in a disinterested search for
knowledge. There is something smug and unctuous about him, which reminds one of a bad type
of cleric. His courage in the face of death would have been more remarkable if he had not
believed that he was going to enjoy eternal bliss in the company of the gods. Unlike some
of his predecessors, he was not scientific in his thinking, but was determined to prove
the universe agreeable to his ethical standards. This is treachery to truth, and the worst
of philosophic sins. As a man, we may believe him admitted to the communion of saints; but
as a philosopher he needs a long residence in a scientific purgatory. (H.W.P.p142/3)
Since reason consists in a just adaptation
of means to ends, it can only be opposed by those who think it a good thing that people
should choose means which cannot realize their professed ends. This implies either that
they should be deceived as to how to realize their professed ends, or that their real ends
should not be those that they profess. The first is the case of a populace misled by an
eloquent fuehrer. The second is that of the schoolmaster who enjoys torturing boys, but
wishes to go on thinking himself a benevolent humanitarian. I cannot feel that either of
these grounds for opposing reason is morally respectable. (H.S.E.P.preface,p10)
One critic takes me to task because I say
that only evil passions prevent the realization of a better world, and goes on
triumphantly to ask, 'are all human emotions necessarily evil?' In the very book that
leads my critic to this objection, I say that what the world needs is Christian love, or
compassion. This, surely, is an emotion, and, in saying that this is what the world needs,
I am not suggesting reason as a driving force. I can only suppose that this emotion,
because it is neither cruel nor destructive, is not attractive to the apostles of
unreason. (H.S.E.P.preface,p9)
Intellectually, the effect of mistaken
moral considerations upon philosophy has been to impede progress to an extraordinary
extent. I do not myself believe that philosophy can either prove or disprove the truth of
religious dogmas, but ever since Plato most philosophers have considered it part of their
business to produce 'proofs' of immortality and the existence of God. They have found
fault with the proofs of their predecessors. Thomas rejected St. Anselm's proofs, and Kant
rejected Descartes'- but they have supplied new ones of their own. In order to make their
proofs seem valid, they have had to falsify logic, to make mathematics mystical, and to
pretend that deep-seated prejudices were heaven-sent intuitions. (H.W.P.p835)
All who are not lunatics are agreed about
certain things: That it is better to be alive than dead, better to be adequately fed than
starved, better to be free than a slave. Many people desire those things only for
themselves and their friends; they are quite content that their enemies should suffer.
These people can be refuted by science: Mankind has become so much one family that we
cannot insure our own prosperity- except by insuring that of everyone else. If you wish to
be happy yourself, you must resign yourself to seeing others also happy. (S.S.S.p33)
The Stoic-Christian view requires a
conception of virtue very different from Aristotle's, since it must hold that virtue is as
possible for the slave as for his master. Christian ethics disapproves of pride, which
Aristotle thinks a virtue, and praises humility, which he thinks a vice. The intellectual
virtues, which Plato and Aristotle value above all others, have to be thrust out of the
list altogether, in order that the poor and humble may be able to be as virtuous as anyone
else. Pope Gregory the Great solemnly reproved a bishop for teaching grammar. (H.W.P.p177)
There is no presence of justice, as we
understand it, in the punishment following an act forbidden by a tabu, which is rather to
be conceived as analogous to death as the result of touching a live wire. When David was
transporting the Ark on a cart, it jolted over a rough threshing floor, and Uzzah, who was
in charge, thinking it would fall, stretched up his hand to steady it. For this impiety,
in spite of his laudable motive, he was struck dead (II Samuel vi. 6-7). The same lack of
justice appears in the fact that not only murder, but accidental homicide, calls for
purification. (H.S.E.P.p29)
It must be admitted that there is a certain
type of Christian ethic to which Nietzsche's strictures can be justly applied. Pascal and
Dostoevsky- his own illustrations- have both something abject in their virtue. Pascal
sacrificed his magnificent mathematical intellect to his God, thereby attributing to Him a
barbarity which was a cosmic enlargement of Pascal's morbid mental tortures. Dostoevsky
would have nothing to do with 'proper pride'; he would sin in order to repent and to enjoy
the luxury of confession. (H.W.P.p768.)
Forms of morality based on tabu linger on
into civilized communities to a greater extent than some people realize. Pythagoras
forbade beans, and Empedocles thought it wicked to munch laurel leaves. Hindus shudder at
the thought of eating beef; Mohammedans and orthodox Jews regard the flesh of the pig as
unclean. St. Augustine, the missionary to Britain, wrote to Pope Gregory the Great to know
whether married people might come to church if they had had intercourse the previous
night, and the Pope ruled that they might only do so after a ceremonial washing. There was
a law in Connecticut- I believe it is still formally unrepealed- making it illegal for a
man to kiss his wife on Sunday. (H.S.E.P.p29/30)
It is true that if we ever did stop to
think about the cosmos we might find it uncomfortable. The sun may grow cold or blow up;
the earth may lose its atmosphere and become uninhabitable. Life is a brief, small, and
transitory phenomenon in an obscure corner, not at all the sort of thing that one would
make a fuss about if one were not personally concerned. But it is monkish and futile- so
scientific man will say- to dwell on such cold and unpractical thoughts. Let us get on
with the job of fertilizing the desert, melting Arctic ice, and killing each other with
perpetually improving technique. Some of our activities will do good, some harm, but all
alike will show our power. And so, in this godless universe we shall become gods. (I.S.S.p15)
Law in origin was merely a codification of
the power of dominant groups, and did not aim at anything that to a modern man would
appear to be justice. In many Germanic tribes, for example, if you committed a murder, you
were fined, and the fine depended upon the social stews of your victim. Wherever
aristocracy existed, its members had various privileges which were not accorded to the
plebe. In Japan before the Meiji era began a man who omitted to smile in the presence of a
social superior could legally be killed then and there by the superior in question. This
explains why European travelers find the Japanese a smiling race. (N.H.C.W.p75)
The Christian ethics inevitably, through
the emphasis laid upon sexual virtue, did a great deal to degrade the position of women.
Since the moralists were men, woman appeared as the temptress; if they had been women, man
would have had this role. Since woman was the temptress, it was desirable to curtail her
opportunities for leading men into temptation; consequently respectable women were more
and more hedged about with restrictions, while the women who were not respectable, being
regarded as sinful, were treated with the utmost contumely. It is only in quite modern
times that women have regained the degree of freedom which they enjoyed in the Roman
Empire. The patriarchal system . . . did much to enslave women, but a great deal of this
was undone just before the rise of Christianity. After Constantine, women's freedom was
again curtailed under the presence of protecting them from sin. It is only with the decay
of the notion of sin in modern times that women have begun to regain their freedom. (M.M.p60/1.)
As men begin to grow civilized, they cease
to be satisfied with mere tabus, and substitute divine commands and prohibitions. The
Decalogue begins: 'God spoke these words and said.' Throughout the Books of the Law it is
the Lord who speaks. To do what God forbids is wicked, and will also be punished. Thus the
essence of morality becomes obedience. The fundamental obedience is to the will of God,
but there are many derivation forms which owe their sanction to the fact that social
inequalities have been divinely instituted. Subjects must obey the king, the slaves their
master, wives their husbands, and children their parents. The king owes obedience only to
God, but if he fails in this he or his people will be punished. When David took a census,
the Lord, who disliked statistics, sent a plague, of which many thousands of the children
of Israel died (I Chron. xxi). This shows how important it was for everybody that the king
should be virtuous. The power of priests depended partly upon the fact that they could to
some extent keep the king from sin, at any rate from the grosser sins such as worship of
false gods. (H.S.E.P.p33)
Kant was never tired of pouring scorn on
the view that the good consists of pleasure, or of anything else except virtue. And virtue
consists in acting as the moral law enjoins, because that is what the moral law enjoins. A
right action done from any other motive cannot count as virtuous. If you are kind to your
brother because you are fond of him, you have no merit; but if you can hardly stand him
and are nevertheless kind to him because the moral law says you should be, then you are
the sort of person that Kant thinks you ought to be. But in spite of the total
worthlessness of pleasure Kant thinks it unjust that the good should suffer, and on this
ground alone holds that there is a future life in which they enjoy eternal bliss. If he
really believed what he thinks he believes, he would not regard heaven as a place where
the good are happy, but as a place where they have never-ending opportunities of doing
kindnesses to people whom they dislike. (H.S.E.P.p49)
Kant invented a new moral argument for the
existence of God, and that in varying forms was extremely popular during the nineteenth
century.... The point I am concerned with is that, if you are quite sure there is a
difference between right and wrong, you are then in this situation: Is that difference due
to God's fiat or is it not? If it is due to God's fiat, then for God Himself there is no
difference between right and wrong, and it is no longer a significant statement to say
that God is good. If you are going to say, as theologians do, that God is good, you must
then say that right and wrong have some meaning which is independent of God's fiat,
because God's fiats are good and not bad independently of the mere fact that He made them.
If you are going to say that, you will then have to say that it is not only through God
that right and wrong come into being, but that they are in their essence logically
anterior to God. You could, of course, if you liked, say that there was a superior deity
who gave orders to the God who made this world, or you could take up the line that some of
the gnostics took up- a line which I often thought was a very plausible one, that as a
matter of fact this world that we know was made by the devil at a moment when God was not
looking. There is a good deal to be said for that, and I am not concerned to refute it. (W.N.C.p12)
To a modern mind, it is difficult to feel
enthusiastic about a virtuous life if nothing is going to be achieved by it. We admire a
medical man who risks his life in an epidemic of plague, because we think illness is an
evil, and we hope to diminish its frequency. But if illness is no evil, the medical man
might as well stay comfortably at home. To the Stoic, his virtue is an end in itself, not
something that does good. And when we take a longer view, what is the ultimate outcome? A
destruction of the present world by fire, and then a repetition of the whole process.
Could anything be more devastatingly futile? There may be progress here and there, for a
time, but in the long run there is only recurrence. When we see something unbearably
painful, we hope that in time such things will cease to happen; but the Stoic assures us
that what is happening now will happen over and over again. Providence, which sees the
whole, must, one would think, ultimately grow weary through despair. (H.W.P.p255)
When I was a child the atmosphere in the
house was one of puritan piety and austerity. There were family prayers at eight o'clock
every morning. Although there were eight servants, food was always of Spartan simplicity,
and even what there was, if it was at all nice, was considered too good for children. For
instance, if there was apple tart and rice pudding, I was only allowed the rice pudding.
Cold baths all the year round were insisted upon, and I had to practice the piano from
seven-thirty to eight every morning although the fires were not yet lit. My grandmother
never allowed herself to sit in an armchair until the evening. Alcohol and tobacco were
viewed with disfavor although stern convention compelled them to serve a little wine to
guests. Only virtue was prized, virtue at the expense of intellect, health, happiness, and
every mundane good. (P.F.M.p3)
For over two thousand years it has been the
custom among earnest moralists to decry happiness as something degraded and unworthy. The
Stoics, for centuries, attacked Epicurus, who preached happiness; they said that his was a
pig's philosophy, and showed their superior virtue by inventing scandalous lies about him.
One of them, Cleanthes, wanted Aristarchus persecuted for advocating the Copernican system
of astronomy; another, Marcus Aurelius, persecuted the Christians; one of the most famous
of them, Seneca, abetted Nero's abominations, amassed a vast fortune, and lent money to
Boadicea at such an exorbitant rate of interest that she was driven into rebellion. So
much for antiquity. Skipping the next 2,000 years, we come to the German professors who
invented the disastrous theories that led Germany to its downfall and the rest of the
world to its present perilous state; all these learned men despised happiness, as did
their British imitator, Carlyle, who is never weary of telling us that we ought to eschew
happiness in favor of blessedness. He found blessedness in rather odd places: Cromwell's
Irish massacres, Frederick the Great's bloodthirsty perfidy, and Governor Eyre's Jamaican
brutality. In fact, contempt for happiness is usually contempt for other people's
happiness, and is an elegant disguise for hatred of the human race. (P.F.M.p215)
|
. |