AAVV, Studies on the History of
Logic,
Walter de Gruyter,
Berlin - New York 1996, pp.197-208.
Copulatio
in Peter of Capua (12th Century) and the Nature of the
Proposition
Rafael
Jiménez Cataño
My initial intention for this symposium was
to determine the historical place of the notion of copulatio in Peter
of Capua, but in the process of preparing it I realized that if I
really wanted to offer relevant facts for the history of semantics, I
would have to provide an entire framework for which I do not yet
possess all the elements. For this reason my presentation will be
more thematic than historic. First I will present some basic facts,
which will be the basis of a future elaboration of a properly
historical nature. I will show how the notion of copulatio invokes
other proprietates
terminorum, and how, taken together,
they illuminate the nature of the proposition. The nucleus of this
second part will not focus so much on the historical development of
the thought of Peter of Capua and other authors that I will mention;
rather, based on their works, it will attempt to illuminate the
concept of copulatio. This will be possible considering that their
formulation, insofar as it answers a problem,
reveals in some way the very reality behind the
problem.
I
The aspects that at first sight seem to me
the most relevant are the following:
1. Copulatio appears
strictly bound with the function of the "verbal copula"
(vid. Appendix, nn.1-2)
(1);
2. Copulatio applies to
substantives (and not only to adjectives, participles and verbs)
(2).
I think that it is these two characteristics
that could most probably constitute a contribution to the history of
the notion of copulatio. The
following two are no less important, but in them I find, above all,
suggestions about the nature of a proposition:
3. Copulatio receives a
peculiar use next to the notions of "significatio",
"prædicatio", "appellatio" and
"suppositio" (vid. Appendix,
nn.3-6).
4. Copulatio serves to
clarify the meaning of a term:
a) making explicit
what
(and to what) the term copulates (vid. Appendix,
nn.3-5, 7-12), and
b) making precise how the term copulates it
(vid. Appendix, nn.13-17).
John Malcolm (3)
proposes a hypothesis to explain the disappearance of copulatio by
dividing into four phases the development of the medieval doctrine of
proprietates
terminorum
(4).
The first phase (12th century) is dominated by the term
significatio (connotative) and by appellatio
(denotative). The second phase begins in the 13th century
(5) in
which copulatio appears. This property and suppositio--which
substitutes the earlier appellatio--are the
two parts in which significatio is
divided, the former in the case of adjectives and the latter for
substantives. As the parts of a division (i.e. as subjective parts),
both "are" significatio and
include the connotative and denotative aspect. During the third phase
things changed very rapidly, with Peter of Spain and Lambert of
Auxerre. Significatio is no longer the sum of suppositio and
copulatio; significatio assumes
the connotative function leaving the denotative function to
copulatio. The fourth phase of Malcolm's scheme brings with it
the disappearance of copulatio. "During
the 14th century, however, copulatio is gone
from the list [of proprietates
terminorum]. It does not appear in
Ockham and is used by Burleigh (De
puritate p.54), to signify the
uniting or connecting of a predicate with a subject. But this is to
describe the function of the copula which joins (the subject and
predicate) terms and hence copulatio is no
longer considered as a property of a term"
(6).
If we are to follow this scheme in order to
historically situate the notion of copulatio in Peter
of Capua, we must first make some clarifications. I am principally
interested in the first stage and its relation to the following two,
but Malcolm quickly leaves it behind; I believe this is due to the
fact that the object of his study is, precisely, the disappearance of
copulatio (7).
Moreover, Malcolm takes into account only treatises of logic and not,
as is our case here, texts using the
terminology of logic.
The first characteristic note of the notion
of copulatio in Peter of Capua is its affinity with the function
of the verbal copula, which should not be tied to the fourth phase of
Malcolm's scheme, since this use of the term "copulatio" is common
to the four phases and is already present in Boethius
(8).
Of this first note what is remarkable is its proximity to the thought
of Peter Abelard (9).
However, even though in the presentation of the officium copulandi
and the officium
significandi the two authors
coincide, even terminologically, Peter of Capua's presentation shows
a particularity: in numerous examples the (metalinguistic) subject of
the verb copulare is not the copula (the verb "est"), and not even
a notional verb, but rather the nominal predicate (vid. Appendix,
nn.3-4, 7-8, 18).
That is: copulare is not the action of a term (the copula) which
unites two other terms (subject and predicate), but rather the action
of a term--which is not the copula but
what in the previous scheme we would call "predicate"--which joins
its significatio with the thing being designated by the subject
(10).
I think that this use announces the advent of the notion of
"copulatio" (11)
proper to the 13th century (and appellatio of the
14th), but: a) without a trace of contamination of logic by
metaphysics, which, although considered by some authors
characteristic of the Middle Scholastic Logic
(12),
was present in Abelard (13),
and b) with the particularity that the term that is the nominal
predicate very frequently is the substantive, according to the
procedure of our author in many examples.
This last aspect is the second of the
characteristics mentioned at the outset. Since with it I have entered
into the consideration of the nature of the proposition, I will now
move to the second part, the analysis of the other two
characteristics.
II
As a model of this semantic mechanism, the
following formulation may prove useful: "Hoc nomen 'Pater'
determinate significat
'paternitatem' et eam copulat:
significat etiam et 'Patrem'" (14).
Note that the significatio of the
term ("pater") is made explicit with the corresponding abstract
("paternitas"). This content is "copulated" not by the
copula but by the term itself, "pater". In Peter of
Capua the denotative function ordinarily corresponds to the
suppositio; the appellatio is used
either in the sense of "being the name of", or else as an effective,
real attainment of what is signified (15).
In this context Peter of Capua seems to give the verb
"significare" a denotative sense.
Unfortunately, there is no text in the first
book of the Summa that relates copulatio and
suppositio. For this I will have recourse to Peter of Poitiers,
who in his Sententiarum libri
quinque drafted, probably before
Peter of Capua (16),
three chapters with the following very indicative titles:
XXV: De his que
significant relationes et appellant sed non copulant ("paternitas",
"filiatio", "processio");
XXVI. De his que significant relationes et
copulant sed non appellant et supponunt personas ("Pater", "Filius",
"Spiritus Sanctus");
XXVII: De his que significant relationes et
copulant sed non appellant nec personas supponunt, ut gignens,
genitus, procedens.
In Peter of Poitiers "appellatio" and
"suppositio" have a denotative function, but, as can be observed
in these titles, suppositio is
reserved for persons (17).
In Peter of Capua copulatio and
prædicatio seem to be equivalent (18).
The determination of the mode of copulating
indicates that copulatio is used in
cases for which late scholasticism will use the term "attributio"
(extrinsic and intrinsic) (19).
This brings to mind the definition of appellatio in the
Ars Meliduna, which was contemporaneous with our author: "per
verbum temporis vera attributio sive copulatio"
(20).
Peter of Capua distinguishes the
significatio from the prædicatio
with a curious affirmation: "Non aequis passibus ambulant
significatio vocis et prædicatio, nam significationem semper
retinet, sed prædicationem non" (21).
I wish to call attention to his allusion to steps. Allow me now
to skip over seven centuries. Frege describes the difference between
the semantic of the conceptual term and that of the proper name in
words that are remarkably similar: "In the conceptual term there is
one more step before the object than in the proper name, and the
last step may be omitted (...) and not because of this does
the conceptual term cease to be scientifically useful"
(22).
This is what I once called "disphase" (23).
Frege's text comes immediately after a scheme indicating by arrows
the relationship between term, sense and reference in the
proposition, in the proper name and in the conceptual term. The
"disphase" can be observed graphically by the diverse height at which
the proper name and the conceptual term are situated, although they
coincide in their content. From it comes naturally to speak of steps,
but the remarkable fact is that Peter of Capua, without a spacial and
"vectorial" formulation of the problem, resorts to the same figure
("non aequis passibus..."). Moreover, just like Frege, he immediately adds
that vox always conserves significatio, even
when it cannot in fact be referred to something (i.e. even when it
cannot be predicated): "numquam enim predicat aliquid nisi illud
appellet" (24).
Note, however, that what is "called", the
object of the appellatio (in this
case what is not called), is not the individual to whom the
significatio of the vox is "copulated" but rather the
significatio itself ("numquam predicat aliquid nisi
illud appellet"). That
which is signified and
that which is called are the
same, but significare and
appellare are not the same. For
significatio is possible without appellatio, although
appellatio without significatio is not.
However, this is not yet the notion of appellatio as
suppositio in the present. Rather, what is intended is an
effective signification, the reality of the
signified. The example offered is the following: "Posito ergo quod
Deus nil creet, hoc verbum 'creat' eandem retinet significationem quam
prius, set cum nil appellet, nil de deo
predicat vel ei copulat"
(25).
The equivalence between predicating and
copulating is not, however, total. It cannot be taken further than
the context of this passage. Here is underlined the aspect of
prædicatio that remains outside its value of signification (in
which it coincides with significatio): its
attributive, applicative... copulative value. Prædicatio is:
significatio plus copulatio.
We see then, that to the disphase indicated
by Frege, correspond two complementary distinctions in Peter of
Capua. One alluding also to steps, distinguishes
between significatio and prædicatio.
The other is the point of coincidence beteween Peter of Capua and
Peter Abelard, who called it the "gemina vis" of the
verb (26):
the distinction between "officium
significandi" and "officium copulandi"
(27).
In Frege we have the disphase of two diverse semantic structures,
that of a proper name and that of the conceptual term. The latter
needs three steps to attain what the other reaches in two steps.
Peter of Capua's distinction between significatio and
prædicatio does not relate two different semantics but rather
two moments of the same one. A term--whose nature is not
specified--can signify without predicating. If it predicates, it
also
signifies; moreover, it does so by signifying. The same term can take
one or two steps.
The other distinction made by Peter of Capua
refers specifically to the verb, and here the duality of semantics is
re-established under the form of a bifurcation. The officium significandi distinguishes itself from the significatio of the
earlier distinction only insofar as it limits itself to the verb. The
officium copulandi indicates the encounter of the signification of the
verb with something previously signified (which presupposes
another act of signifying).
As we can see, we are facing exclusively
semantic criteria. This has nothing to do with the notion of
inherence or with the distinction between substantial form and
accidental form. Here at least, the distinction between
suppositio and copulatio does not
follow from any contamination of logic on the part of metaphysics
(28).
Applied semantics, particularly in the field
of theology, does not simply "complement" the studies of medieval
logic (29).
The preceding pages are a proof of this reality. The historiography
of this semantic, in comparison with that of pure logic--namely, that
contained in treatises of
logic--, is still in its early
stages. Within this history, the chapter on Peter of Capua is just
now beginning to be written.
Notes
(1) All the texts come from
the first book.
-^
(2) In contrast with what
is read in the Tractatus de
proprietatibus sermonum (12th
century ex.), the Dialectica
monacensis (13th century
in.), the Introductiones
Parisienses (13th century
in.)
the Logica "Cum sit
nostra" (c.1200), the
Summe metenses (c.1220-1240), the Tractatus of Peter
of Spain (c.1230), the Introductiones
in logicam of William of Sherwood
(Ý 1249), the Royal MSS 8 A
VI (second half of the 13th
century), etc.
-^
(3) Malcolm 1977,
pp.120-138. The specificity of the article is the division of the
four periods in order to explain how copulatio came to be
superfluous. The same historical journey is found with an abundance
of facts in Maierù 1972, pp.195-215. -^
(4) Phase I:
Ars Meliduna, De Rijk 1967, II-I, p.539. Phase II:
Tractatus de proprietatibus
sermonum in De Rijk 1967, II-II,
pp.711-712; Dialectica
monacensis in De Rijk 1967, II-II,
pp.606-607; Introductiones
Parisienses in De Rijk 1967, II-II,
p.317; Logica "Cum sit
nostra" in De Rijk 1967, II-II,
p.451; Summe Metenses in De Rijk 1967, II-II, p.455. Phase III: Peter of
Spain, Tractatus VI (Peter of Spain 1972, p.80); Lambert of Auxerre,
Logica [Summa
Lamberti] (Lambert of Auxerre 1971,
p.207); Royal MSS 8 A
VI, fols.47ra-48vb in in De Rijk
1967, II-I, p.26. Malcolm does not place William of Sherwood in any
specific phase: Introductiones in
Logicam, V (Sherwood 1983,
p.265). -^
(5) Only the
Tractatus de proprietatibus
sermonum seems to remain in the 12th
century. -^
(6) Malcolm 1972, p.120.
"Afterwards, copulation was defined as the union or composition of a predicate with a
subject (W. Burley, De puritate...: longior, p.54 ed. Boehner). From then on the theory of
copulation only concerned the significative function of all
predicate-terms of a proposition and covered adjectives, participles
and verbs when united with a substantive term in a proposition. Since
the distinction of subject-term and predicate-term is of little
relevance in this respect, many logicians abandoned the distinction
between supposition and copulation. As a matter of fact William of
Ockham does not even mention the concept of copulation in his logic
(Cf. Moody, The Logic of William of
Ockham, p.188, n.1)" (De Rijk 1967,
II-I, pp.580-581).
-^
(7) It would have to be
added that his thesis refers to the disappearance of copulatio with
respect to two determinations: a) as proprietas terminorum, because this denomination remains for the verbal
copula, and b) with the name "copulatio": although
it is true that in Burleigh and Ockham things are as Malcolm says
(vid. also De Rijk 1967, II-I, p.581), nonetheless they
continued to speak of the same concept (at least a substantially
identical one) under the name "appellatio" (as if
the term did not already have a sufficiently problematic plurality of
meaning!). This is the case of Buridan in the fourth treatise of his
Summulæ de
dialectica. Already in Ockham
appellatio had been announced as the characteristic property of
the predicate--"prædicatum appellat suam formam"
(Summa logicæ, II,7 and III-1,43)--, although it deals with an
appellatio explicitly subsumed under suppositio (Cf.
I,62). Albert of Saxony will follow this line: "Appellatio est
proprietas prædicati. Solemus enim dicere prædicatum
appelare suam formam in ordine ad verbum quod est copula illius
propositionis" (Perutilis
Logica, II,11); "Subiectum non sic
appellat suam formam" (ibid., II,11). And
with a purely terminological coincidence, Vincent Ferrer: "Et quod
dictum est de significatione, subiectione et suppositione, idem debet
intelligi de significatione, prædicatione et appellatione"
(Tractatus de
suppositionibus, c.I; Ferrer 1977,
p.92). -^
(8) Cf. Maierù 1972,
pp.197-199. -^
(9) Cf. Dialectica, I, III,
in Abelard 1956, pp.129-135. -^
(10) I have not found this
use in Abelard. Peter of Capua can give the impression of identifying
prædicatio and copulatio. In the
examples of Book I, almost all the terms to which he applies this
notion are the predicates of a proposition, and none is the subject.
He also uses the expression "nil de Deo predicat vel ei copulat"
(q.22, T f.15 ra), which although true, insofar as it does not
necessarily indicate synonymy (especially through the repetition of
the subject by the pronoun "ei"), yet it does not resolve the
situation in the other direction. We will return to this point
further on. -^
(11) In the same way the
Ars Meliduna ("per verbum presentis temporis vera attributio sive
copulatio") announces the new notion of appellatio as: "La
définition [de appellatio]
dejà mentionnée la rattache à l'attribution ou
copulation (...). Ainsi sont introduites des relations
intra-propositionnelles. Certes, l'attributio pourrait
être entendue comme attribution d'un nom à une chose,
mais la copulatio, de même que les indications sur le temps du
verbe, attestent que le rapport appellatif est immédiatement
transposé en relation propositionnelle" (Biard 1987,
p.127). -^
(12) Pinborg speaks of the
"embrace of ontology" which logic suffered during this period (Cf.
Pinborg 1972, p.14). "Ich möchte nur noch erwähnen,
daß Sherwood noch eine eigene Eigenschaft, die copulatio,
für Verben und Adjektive als Prädikate aufrechthält.
Das hängt damit zusammen, daß er (im Sinne der
Inhärenztheorie) noch zwischen der Bedeutung von Subjekts- und
Prädikatsterminus unterscheidet" (Pinborg 1972,
p.65). -^
"Da es zwei formæ gibt
(substantialis und accidentalis),
paßt die Analogie zu den zwei Arten von Prädikationen:
per se und per
accidens. Shyreswood (IL, S.82ff.)
behauptet sogar, daß das Subjekt eine suppositio actualis
hat, das Prädikat lediglich eine habitualis! Das ist
natürlich nicht stichhaltig, da er in seinen Beispielen den
Prädikaten suppositio zuspricht
(m.W. hat nur Vincent Ferrer diese Idee tatsächlich befolgt).
Damit aber zeigen sich ganz klar die Verbindungen zwischen den
grammatischen, logischen und ontologischen Ebenen: suppositio, Subjekt,
Substanz und Substantiv werden immer miteinander assoziiert.
Entsprechend stehen als Gegenassoziationen: copulatio,
Prädikat, Akzidens und Adjektiv" (Dufour 1989, p.38; the analogy
referred to at the beginning is: forma materiæ
/ materia = forma
prædicabilis / individua).
Whichever way it took place, I do not
believe this accusation was always done with justice. I must clarify
for example that Vincent Ferrer does not assign suppositio to the
predicate but rather explicitly denies it to it, and as we saw above,
assigns to it appellatio.
(13) Cf. Maierù
1972, pp.204-205. Nonetheless, the type of "contamination" that could
be attributed is, for Maierù, of a different nature: "Nel
secolo XIV (ma solo in Burleigh e Occam), troviamo gli ultimi cenni a
una dottrina della copulatio. Essa,
però, mediante la progressiva sistemazione e chiarificazione
della dottrina della supposizione (tutti i termini della proposizione
hanno supposizione) si è liberata delle incrostazioni di
origine grammaticale che si portava addosso dal tempo di Abelardo ed
è tornata ad essere la dottrina della copula" (Maierù
1972, p.213).
-^
(14) Q.29, V f.15va. There
is another passage almost identical: "Cum dicitur 'iste est pater
istius', hoc nomen 'pater' principaliter significat paternitatem, et
illam ibi copu-lat isti; dat etiam secundario intelligere
filiationem, et ilam nec copulat isti vel illi, set tantum dat
intelligere circa illum. Illa autem copulatur illi cum dicitur 'iste
est filius'" (q.23, T f.15ra). -^
(15) "Posito ergo quod
Deus nil creet, hoc verbum 'creat' eandem retinet significationem
quam prius, set cum nil appellet, nil de Deo predicat vel ei copulat"
(q.23, T f.15rb).
-^
(16) "Written at Paris
certainly before 1176 and probably before 1170" (Moore-Dulong 1943,
p.vi). The Suma theologie of Peter of Capua was written between 1170
and 1190, dates based on the dedication found in it to Gualterio,
Archbishop of Palermo during this period (Cf. Chacón 1988,
p.383). With these facts the work of Peter of Capua can be as early
as five years before that of Peter of Poitiers, or as late as 20
years after (or more).
-^
(17) About the use of the
terms proper to the proprietates terminorum Cf. Lahoz 1992,
pp.54-138, especially pp.68-70 and 134-138. -^
(18) "Nos dicimus quod hoc
nomen 'creator' vel hoc verbum 'creat' et similia, de Deo predicant
essentiam; cum enim dicitur 'Deus est creator' hoc nomen 'creator'
principaliter significat quandam relationem, scilicet increatam sive
di-vinam essentiam et illam ibi copulat Deo" (q.23, T
f.15ra). -^
(19) The text of the
preceding note continues in the following way: "dat etiam secundario
intelligere quandam relationem creatam et illam non copulat Deo, set
nec creature, set tantum dat intelligere circa creaturam. Illa autem
copulatur creature cum dicitur 'creatura creatur'. Sicut cum dicitur
'iste est pater istius', hoc nomen 'pater' principaliter significat
paternitatem, et illam ibi copulat isti; dat etiam secundario
intelligere filiationem, et ilam nec copulat isti vel illi, set
tantum dat intelligere circa illum. Illa autem copulatur illi cum
dicitur 'iste est filius'" (q.23, T f.15ra). -^
(20) De Rijk 1967, II-I,
p.539. -^
(21) Q.23, T
f.15rb. -^
(22) "Beim Begriffsworte
ist ein Schritt mehr bis zum Gegenstande als beim Eigennahmen und der
letzte kann fehlen--d.h. der Begriff kann leer sein--, ohne daß
dadurch das Begriffswort aufhört, wissenschaftlich verwendbar zu
sein" (Letter to Husserl, 24.5.1891, in Frege 1976,
p.96). -^
(23) Cf. Jiménez
Cataño 1991, p.48.
-^
(24) Q.23, T
f.15rb. -^
(25) Ibid. -^
(26) Abelard 1956,
p.135. -^
(27) Cf. q.5, T
f.5ra. -^
(28) I contend that this
can also be said of the appellatio of the 14th century. -^
(29) Supporters of this
thesis include, among others, Alain of Libera and Alfonso
Maierù.
-^
References
Abelard, Peter 1956
Dialectica, ed. L. M. De Rijk. Assen: Van Gorcum.
Albert of Saxony (see Saxony)
Biard, Joël 1987
"Semantique et ontologie dans l''Ars
Meliduna'", in Jolivet and Libera 1987, pp.121-144.
Chacón, Alfonso 1988
"Sobre la autoría de la Summa
theologiæ del cardenal Pedro de Capua (= 1214)", in Saranyana
and Tejero, 1988, pp.379-387.
De Rijk, L. M. 1967
Logica Modernorum. A Contribution to the
History of Early Terminist Logic,
II-I: On the Origin an Early Development of the Theory of
Supposition; II-II: Texts and Indices. Assen: Van Gorcum.
Dufour, Carlos A. 1989
Die Lehre der Proprietates Terminorum.
Sinn und Referenz in mittelalterlicher Logik. München-Hamden-Wien: Philosophia
Verlag.
Ferrer, Vincent 1977
Tractatus de
suppositionibus, critical edition
with an introduction by John A. Trenntman. Stuttgart-BadCanstatt:
Fromman-Holzboog.
Frege, Gottlob 1976
Wissenschaftlicher
Briefwechsel. Hamburg: Felix
Meiner.
Jiménez Cataño, Rafael
1991
Semántica y racionalidad en Frege.
Un estudio desde las operaciones mentales. México: Minos.
Jolivet, Jean and Libera, Alain de (eds.)
1987
Gilbert de Poitiers et ses contemporains.
Aux origines de la Logica Modernorum, Napoli: Bibliopolis.
Lahoz, Carlos 1992
Reglamentación del lenguaje
trinitario en Pedro de Capua. Análisis semiótico y
contextualización histórica. Romæ: Athenæum Romanum Sanctæ
Crucis.
Lambert of Auxerre 1971
Logica [Summa Lamberti], ed. Franco Alessio. Firenze, La Nuova
Italia.
Maierù, Alfonso 1972
Terminologia logica della tarda
scolastica. Roma: Edizioni
dell'Ateneo.
Malcolm, John 1977
"On the Disappearance of 'Copulatio' as a
Property of a Term", in Franciscan
Studies, 37, pp.120-138.
Moore, Philip S. and Dulong, Marthe (eds.)
1943
Sententiæ Petri
Pictaviensis. Notre Dame: The
University of Notre Dame Press.
Ockham, William 1974
Opera philosophica et
theologica, vol.I, eds. Philoteus
Boehner, Gedeon Gál and Stephanus Brown. St. Bonaventure
(N.Y.): Editiones Instituti Franciscani Universitatis S.
Bonaventurae.
Pinborg, Jan 1972
Logik und Semantik im Mittelalter. Ein
Überblick. Suttgart-Bad
Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog.
Saranyana, Josep-Ignasi and Tejero, Eloi
(eds.) 1988
AAVV, Hispania Christiana,
studies in honor of J. Orlandis, Pamplona: EUNSA.
Saxony, Albert of 1988
Perutilis Logica, ed. Angel Muñoz García.
México: Universidad Nacional Autónoma de
México.
Sherwood, William of 1983
Introductiones in Logicam, in Traditio 39, pp.219-299.
T Todi, Bibl. Com. 51.
V Vat. Lat. 4296.
Appendix
1. "Quotiens
hoc verbum 'est' est tertium adiacens, scilicet cum copulat
predicatum subiecto, cadit ab officio
significandi; nec significat
aliquid, set tantum tenet officium
copulandi" (q.5, T
fol.5ra). -^
2. "Item. Queritur an hoc verbum est in
eadem significatione vel in diversis copulet Christo
hec duo predicata: 'Deus', 'homo'. (...) Set huius solutio patet ex
predictis. Cum enim hoc verbum
'est' in predicta locutione sit
copula, nichil ibi significat, set
tantum copulat" (q.5, T
fol.5rb).
3. "Hoc nomen 'Pater'
determinate significat
'paternitatem' et eam copulat:
significat etiam et 'Patrem'" (q.29, V fol.15va). -^
4. "Nos dicimus quod hoc nomen 'creator' vel
hoc verbum 'creat' et similia, de Deo predicant essentiam;
cum enim dicitur 'Deus est creator' hoc nomen 'creator' principaliter
significat quandam relationem, scilicet increatam sive divinam
essentiam et illam ibi copulat Deo; dat
etiam secundario intelligere quandam relationem creatam et illam non
copulat Deo, set nec creature, set tantum dat intelligere
circa creaturam. Illa autem copulatur creature
cum dicitur 'creatura creatur'. Sicut cum dicitur 'iste est pater
istius', hoc nomen 'pater' principaliter significat
paternitatem, et illam ibi copulat isti; dat
etiam secundario intelligere filiationem, et ilam nec copulat isti vel
illi, set tantum dat intelligere circa illum. Illa autem
copulatur illi cum dicitur 'iste est filius'" (q.23, T
fol.15ra).
5. "Posito ergo quod Deus nil creet, hoc
verbum 'creat' eandem retinet significationem quam
prius, set cum nil appellet, nil de Deo
predicat vel ei copulat; et si nil
predicatur in affirmativa, nil removetur in hac negativa 'Deus
non creat'" (q.23, T fol.15rb).
6. We can add the following text which does
not include copulatio: "Hoc nomen 'Deus' convenit persone Filii etiam per
appellationem, et aliquid supponit; ergo
potest supponere illam" (q.2, T fol.2ra). -^
7. "Cum dicitur 'iste homo est iustus',
non copulat ibi hoc nomen 'iustus' qualitatem, set iustitiam quasi confuse, sicut dictum est de verbo
substantivo" (q.6, T fol.5va).
8. "Hoc enim nomen 'Pater' copulat relationem, non qualitatem vel
essentiam" (q.8, T fol.6ra).
9. "Hoc verbum 'predestinor' nulli copulat passionem, quod patet per hoc quod ipsum potest dici de re
etiam non existenti; de eo enim qui cras nascetur potest vere dici
'ille predestinatur'; sicut cum dicitur 'hec res videtur a me', per
hoc verbum 'videtur' nulla passio
copulatur rei in se" (q.19, T
fol.11vb).
10. "Hoc nomen 'unus' in singulari non
copulat unitatem, nisi in neutro genere, /fol. 13rb/ ut 'sunt unum',
set secundum distinctionem; non est enim sensus: 'sunt unus', id est
participant unitate; set 'sunt una persona distincta'. Set hoc homen
'iustus', etiam in singulari, copulat
iustitiam, et est sensus: 'sunt
iustus', id est participant iustitiam; et ideo hanc concedimus, et
non illam; cum vero dicitur: 'sunt unus Deus' et hoc nomen 'unus'
non copulat
distinctionem, set tantum excludit
pluralitatem deorum" (q.27, V 13ra-b).
11. "Set obest. Augustinus dicit: 'cum
ingenitus dicitur, non quid sit, set quid non sit dicitur'; ergo hoc
nomen 'ingenitus' nil ponit set potius removet; set idem prorsus
significat 'ingenitus' et 'innascibilis'; ergo et hoc nomen
'innascibilis' tantum removet; non ergo ipsum copulat innascibilitatem. Respondeo. Potest solvi premissa auctoritas per
supplementum, ut sit sensus: 'non tantum quid sit, set etiam quid non
sit dicitur'. Vel distingue equivocationem huius nominis 'ingenitus',
vel huius 'innascibilis': primo ponitur hoc nomen 'ingenitus' tantum
remotive, ut sit sensus: 'non genitus'; set quod divina essentia est
ingenita, et Spiritus Sanctus est ingenitus, secundum hoc accipitur
in predicta auctoritate Augustini; et dicit quod potest etiam hoc
nomen 'ingenitus' privative et remotive teneri; et privando secundum
hoc copulat
innascibilitatem; et secundum hoc
dicitur de solo Patre; sicut hoc nomen 'iniustus' potest tantum
remotive teneri, id est 'non iustus', secundum quod etiam lapis est
iniustus; potest etiam poni privative, secundum quod copulat iniustitiam
ut: 'hic homo est iniustus'" (q.31, V fol.14ra).
12. "Innascibilitas non est relatio, set
notio quedam qua Pater non refertur ad alium; ipsa tantum
significatur hoc nomine 'innascibilis', quod dicitur relative non
determinate ad aliquam, quia nil esset dictu: Pater est innascibilis
Filii et Spiritus Sancti; set confuse notat respectum, sicut essentia
divina non refertur ad aliquam, ipsa
tamen copulatur per hoc nomen
'similis', quod dicitur relative" (q.31, V fol.14va).
13. "Cum dicitur 'isti duo
ferunt lapidem', hoc verbum 'ferunt' sine distinctione singularitatis vel pluralitatis
copulat lationem lapidis" (q.5, T
fol.5ra). -^
14. "Nos vero dicimus quod omnia adiectiva
adiective retenta possunt in plurali predicari de pluribus personis,
nam nullum adiectivum, nisi sit numerale, copulat rem suam cum distinctione singularitatis vel
pluralitatis" (q.6, T
fol.5va).
15. "Sic intelligenda est premissa
auctoritas 'tota trinitas operata est incarnationem Filii', id est
tota trinitas incarnavit Filium; incarnatio autem Filii potest
intelligi vel passive, que
copulatur ei cum dicitur 'Filius
incarnatur', non quod sit passio predicamentalis, set que modus passionis copulatur: et illa est divina essentia et est solus Filius;
vel active, que
copulatur cum dicitur 'Filius vel
Pater est incarnans'; et illa est divina essentia, et est tam Pater
quam Filius et Spiritus Sanctus" (q.24, T fol.15va).
16. "Secundum hoc non est concedendum:
'Pater et Filius sunt unus', quia per hoc nomen 'unus' in singulari
copularetur una distinctio
confuse; ipsi autem non sunt una
distinctio nec una persona distincta" (q.27, V fol.13ra).
17. "Potest dici quod tres
sunt infusiones passive, id est que
passive copulantur, et infusio qua
infunditur Pater est solus Pater, vel Paternitas; et illa qua
infunditur Filius est solus Filius vel filiatio; illa qua infunditur
Spiritus Sanctus est solus Spiritus Sanctus vel processio. Item.
Divina essentia vel tota Trinitas infundit tres personas active
infusione, id est que active
copulatur; sicut tota Trinitas
incarnavit Filium, vel divina essentia; et potest dici quod ille
/fol.15v2/ tres infusiones que
passive copulantur sunt illa una
essentia que active copulatur, sicut tres notiones sunt una essentia.
Sicut incarnatio, que passive copulatur Filio; cum dicitur Filius
incarnatur, est solus Filius; et est illa que active copulatur
toti Trinitati, cum dicitur: tota Trinitas est incarnans Filium; que
etiam activa est quelibet trium personarum" (q.34, V
fol.15va-b).
18. "Nos vero dicimus quod omnia adiectiva
adiective retenta possunt in plurali predicari de pluribus personis,
nam nullum adiectivum, nisi sit numerale, copulat rem suam cum
distinctione singularitatis vel pluralitatis" (q.6, T
fol.5va). -^