by David Pearce
0. Introduction.
"Happiness is an illusion; only suffering is real."
(Voltaire)
0.1 The Naturalisation of Heaven.
This manifesto combines far-fetched utopian advocacy with cold-headed
social-scientific prediction. The Hedonistic Imperative outlines how nanotechnology
and genetic engineering will eliminate aversive experience from the living
world. Over the next thousand years or so, the biological substrates of
suffering will be eradicated completely. "Physical" and "mental" pain alike
are destined to disappear into evolutionary history. The biochemistry of
everyday discontents will be genetically phased out too. Instead, matter
and energy will be sculpted into perpetually life-loving super-beings.
Their states of mind are likely to be incomprehensibly diverse by comparison
with today. Yet all will share at least one common feature: a sublime and
all-pervasive happiness.
This feeling of absolute
well-being will surpass anything which human neurochemistry and imagination
can presently access, let alone sustain. The story gets better. Post-human
states of quite magical joy will be biologically purified, multiplied and
intensified indefinitely. Notions of what now passes for tolerably good
mental health will be superseded. They will be written off as mood-congruent
cognitive pathologies of the primordial Darwinian psyche. Such ugly thoughts
and feelings will be diagnosed as typical of the tragic lives of emotional
primitives from the previous era. In time, the deliberate re-creation of
today's state-spectrum of normal waking and dreaming consciousness may
be outlawed as cruel and immoral.
Such speculations may currently
sound fantastical. Yet the ideas of this manifesto may one day come to
be regarded as intellectually trite - albeit today morally urgent. For
what might once have been the stuff of millennialist fantasy is set to
become a scientifically feasible research program. Its adoption or rejection
will become, ultimately, a social policy issue. Passively or actively,
we will have to choose just how much unpleasantness we wish to create or
conserve - if any - in eras to come.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
0.2 Saving Vehicles With Bad Drivers.
Blind selective pressures have acted on living organisms over hundreds
of millions of years. Darwinian evolution has powerfully favoured the growth
of ever more diverse, excruciating, but also more adaptive varieties of
psychophysical pain. Its sheer nastiness effectively spurs and punishes
the living vehicles of genetic replicators. Sadness, anxiety and malaise,
too, are frequently good for our genes; they're just psychologically bad
for us. In absolute terms, global suffering is probably still increasing
as the population explosion continues. Human ingenuity has struggled, often
vainly, to rationalise and somehow derive value from the most frightful
anguish. But over the aeons the very anguish which intermittently corrodes
the well-being of the individual organism has differentially promoted the
inclusive fitness of its DNA. Hence it has tended to get inexorably worse.
Of course such doom-and-gloom
isn't the whole picture. The world's horrors can be contrasted with life's
more rewarding experiences. People sometimes have fun. Long-lasting depression
is rarely adaptive. Yet what Michael Eysenck describes as the "hedonic
treadmill" ensures that very few of us can be very happy for very long.
An interplay of cruelly effective negative feedback mechanisms is at work
in the central nervous system. Feedback-inhibition ensures that a majority
of people would be periodically bored, depressed or angst-ridden in a recreated
Garden of Eden.
A small minority of humans do in fact experience states of indefinitely prolonged euphoria. These states of involuntary well-being are usually pathologised as "manic". Unlike unipolar depression, sustained unipolar mania is very rare. Other folk who just have high "hedonic set-points", but who aren't manic or bipolar, are sometimes described as "hyperthymic" instead. This isn't a common mindset either. "Bipolar disorder", on the other hand, is experienced in the course of a lifetime by perhaps one in a hundred people or more. Popularly known as manic-depression, it has several sub-types. Mood characteristically alternates between euphoria and abject despair. Cycles may vary in length. It is a complex genetic condition which runs in families. Typically, bipolarity is marked by a genetic variation in the serotonin transporter as compared to "euthymic" normals. Serotonin is a neurotransmitter involved in sleep, sociability, feeding, activity, mood, and a lot else besides. The serotonin transporter mops up "excess" serotonin released by nerve cells into the synapses. Very crudely, manic states are associated with enhanced dopamine and norepinephrine function; serotonin function is dysregulated or low.
Sadly, in today's "bipolars" manic exuberance can spin out of control. Euphoria may be accompanied by hyperactivity, sleeplessness, chaotically racing ideas, pressure of speech and grandiose thought. Hyper-sexuality, financial excesses and religious delusions are common. So is rampant egomania. Sometimes dysphoria may occur. In dysphoric mania the manic "high" is actually unpleasant. The excited subject may be angry, agitated, panicky, paranoid, and destructive. When in the grip of classic euphoric mania, however, it's hard to recognise that anyone might think anything is wrong. This is because everything feels abundantly all right. To suppose otherwise is like going to Heaven and then being invited to believe there has been a mistake. It's not credible.
Today, euphoric (hypo-)mania is liable to be clinically subdued with drugs. ["Hypomania" denotes simply a milder mania.] Toxic "medication" can depress elevated mood to duller but "normal" levels. Such flatter and supposedly healthier levels of emotion enable otherwise euphoric people to function within contemporary society. Compliance with a medically-dictated treatment-regimen (lithium, sodium valproate, carbamazepine etc.) will be enhanced if the victim can be persuaded that euphoric well-being is pathological. (S)he can then look for warning signs and symptoms. By the norms of our genetically-enriched posterity, however, it is the rest of us who are chronically unwell - if not more so. Contemporary standards of mental health are just pathologically low. Our super-well descendants, by contrast, will enjoy a glorious spectrum of new options. They may opt to combine emotional stability, resilience and "serotonergic" serenity, for instance, with the goal-oriented energy, optimism and initiative of a raw "dopaminergic" high. Post-humans will have discovered that euphoric peak experiences can be channelled, controlled and genetically diversified, not just medically suppressed.
For there is a cruel irony here. Clinically prescribed mood-darkeners would be laughably redundant for the great bulk of humanity. At present, life for billions of genetically "normal" people is often very grim indeed. No amount of piecemeal political and economic reform, nor even radical social engineering, can overcome this biological reality. Today's billion-and-one routes to supposedly lasting happiness are pursued in the guise of innumerable intentional objects. [Intentionality in philosophy-speak is the 'aboutness' or 'object-directedness' of thought]. We convince ourselves that all manner of things would potentially make us happy. All these peripheral routes are not merely vastly circuitous and inefficient. In the main, they just don't, and can't, durably work. At best, they can serve as superficial palliatives of the human predicament. If the mind/brain's emotional thermostat, as it were, is not genetically and pharmacologically reset, then even the greatest triumphs and successes turn to ashes. Lottery winners, cup-final hat-trick scorers and blissful newly-weds are left time and again to discover this fate anew. Even those of us who tend to lead a relatively happy day-to-day existence will, in the course of a lifetime, undergo spells of wretched unhappiness and disappointment.
It would be easy but unwarranted
simply to extrapolate past and present trends into the indefinite future.
Usually, we assume without question that our descendants - however different
from us in other respects - will be biologically prone to suffer negative
states of consciousness. We suppose that future generations will sometimes
feel distress, both subtle and crude, just as we have always done ourselves.
Yet this assumption may be naive. The neurochemical basis of feeling and
emotion is rapidly being unravelled. The human genome is going to get decoded
and rewritten. In ages to come, it will become purely an issue of (post-)human
decision whether unpleasant modes of consciousness are generated in any
form or texture whatsoever. Aversive experience is a sinister anachronism.
We will have to decide if we should inflict suffering on ourselves or on
others. A terrible but once unavoidable fact of organic life then becomes
instead a matter for active moral choice. And that choice can be declined.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
0.3 Humans Are Not Rats.
One possibility, though not an option to be canvassed here, is that
in freeing ourselves from the nightmarish legacy of our genetic past we
might choose to enjoy a lifetime of raw, all-consuming orgasmic bliss.
This bliss needn't be directed at any well-defined intentional objects.
We - or more likely our robot-serviced descendants - wouldn't be ecstatic
about anything in particular. Our nature would be constitutionally ecstatic.
Genetically pre-programmed euphoria would be as natural and inevitable
as breathing. We would simply be happy about being happy.
The defining image here,
perhaps, is the notional human counterpart of the experimenter's lever-pressing
rat. Electrodes can be implanted directly into the mind/brain's pleasure
centres. These lie in the meso-limbic dopamine system, the core of the
brain's reward circuitry. It extends from the ventral tegmentum to the
nucleus accumbens, with projections to the limbic system and orbitofrontal
cortex. Notoriously, the wired rat will indulge in frenzied bouts of intra-cranial
self-stimulation for days on end. The experience is so wonderful that it
takes precedence over food and sleep. It's preferred even to sex. The rat
doesn't need to undergo a contrasting "low" to appreciate the "high". The
little bundle of joy is apparently incapable of becoming bored with, or
physiologically tolerant to, the rodent equivalent of Heaven.
Such animalistic images are unedifying to all but the most unabashed hedonist. Yet more subtly-engineered human counterparts of the euphoric rat are perfectly feasible. Centuries hence, any pleasure-maximising ecstatics will be using their personal freedom to exercise what is, in a utilitarian sense, a legitimate life-style choice.
The "wirehead" option, however,
will be only one item taken from a very large menu. Unfortunately, it is
also the most easily visualised. So the spectre of perpetual intra-cranial
self-stimulation will be taken, wrongly, to symbolise the whole approach
that The Hedonistic Imperative represents. The utterly serious ethical
substance which underlies this manifesto's proposals may thus too easily
be dismissed. For humans, as we are solemnly reminded, are not rats.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
0.4 Life In Dopaminergic Overdrive.
An important point to stress in the discussion to follow is that many
dopamine-driven states of euphoria can actually enhance motivated, goal-directed
behaviour in general. Enhanced dopamine function makes one's motivation
to act stronger, not weaker. Hyper-dopaminergic states tend also to increase
the range of activities an organism finds worth pursuing. Outside the pleasure-laboratory,
such states of necessity focus on countless different intentional objects.
So humanity's future as envisaged in this manifesto is not, or certainly
not just, an eternity spent enraptured on elixirs of super-soma or tanked
up on high-octane pleasure-machines. Nor is it plausible that posterity
will enjoy only the dullish, opiated sensibility of the heroin addict.
Instead, an extraordinarily fertile range of purposeful and productive
activities will most likely be pursued. Better still, our descendants,
and in principle perhaps even our elderly selves, will have the chance
to enjoy modes of experience we primitives cruelly lack. For on offer are
sights more majestically beautiful, music more deeply soul-stirring, sex
more exquisitely erotic, mystical epiphanies more awe-inspiring, and love
more profoundly intense than anything we can now properly comprehend.
I shall first schematically
set out how a naturalistic, secular paradise of effectively everlasting
happiness is biotechnically feasible. Second, I will argue why its realisation
is instrumentally rational and ethically mandatory. Third, I will offer
a sketch of when and why such a scenario is likely to come to pass in some
guise or other. And, finally, I shall try to anticipate some of the most
common if not always cogent objections that the prospect of psychochemical
nirvana is likely to arouse, and attempt to defuse them.
Chapter 1
1. How?
"God's in His Heaven -
All's right with the world!"
(Robert Browning)
1.0 Sabotage at the Mill.
To escape from the hedonic treadmill we must
first sabotage a small but vicious set of negative feedback mechanisms.
These are genetically coded into the mind/brain. Recreational drugs of
abuse do not transcend or subvert such mechanisms. On the contrary, they
actually bring them into play with a vengeance. Today's quick-and-dirty
euphoriants are nonetheless instructive. They give us a tantalising glimpse
of what humanity's natural state of consciousness could become if several
ugly neural metabolic pathways were inhibited or eliminated.
A better clue to organic life's emotional future dates from the early 1950's.
The unlikely guinea-pigs were veterans at a U.S. tuberculosis sanatorium.
Residents prescribed the MAO-inhibiting drug iproniazid were not merely
cured of their tuberculosis. After a few weeks of treatment, many of them
started to feel exceptionally happy. Doctors described their patients,
rather over-colourfully perhaps, as "dancing in the aisles". For the most
part, the veterans had not previously been clinically depressed, as distinct
from rather crotchety. Nor was their new-found euphoria simply an understandable
reaction to restored good health. Moreover, in contrast to most recreational
drugs, tolerance to the MAO-inhibitor's mood-brightening side-effect, and
the consequent danger of uncontrolled dose-escalation, didn't set in. Instead,
it transpires that MAO-inhibitors as a class can induce a benign, long-term
re-regulation of several families of nerve-cell receptor proteins involved
in making us happy or sad. Quite by accident, modern medicine had stumbled
on the sustainably mood-lifting properties of a remarkable and diverse
category of drugs, the monoamine oxidase-inhibitors.
Monoamine oxidase has two main types, uninformatively labelled A and B. It is an enzyme responsible for the deamination of monoamine neurotransmitters such as dopamine, noradrenaline and serotonin. It also deaminates trace amines such as phenylethylamine, found in chocolate and released when one is in love. MAO isoenzyme-A deaminates serotonin, norepinephrine and, to a lesser extent, dopamine. Isoenzyme-B breaks down dopamine and phenylethylamine. The action of monoamine neurotransmitters on the post-synaptic receptors, and the post-transduction intracellular cascade they induce, plays a vital role in mediating mood and emotional experience. Depletion of monoamines in the synaptic vesicles e.g. by the anti-hypertensive drug reserpine, can sometimes precipitate severe and even life-threatening depression. Elevated levels of dopamine, on the other hand, are associated with (hypo-)manic euphoria.
By modulating the synaptic availability, and consequent receptor re-regulation, of simple neurotransmitters on a long-term basis, the MAO-inhibitors were to serve as the first of a disparate group of drugs uninvitingly categorised as "antidepressants". Some of today's mediocre crop of licensed products, such as the tricyclics, are in general unrewarding to people who aren't rated clinically depressed. They tend to be sedating. Their action dulls, however mildly, the intellect and sensibility. Most traditional therapeutic agents - at least until the development of (relatively) selective serotonin re-uptake blockers such as fluoxetine (Prozac) and noradrenaline reuptake blockers such as reboxetine - are "dirty" and unselective drugs. They have lots of troublesome side-effects. They frequently flatten rather than deepen the emotions. Several brands, such as the older, unselective and irreversible MAO-inhibitors, are potentially dangerous if taken in the absence of rigorous dietary restrictions. All of them, thanks to the puritanical ethos of the medical establishment, have been tested and brought to market with the deliberate additional aim of not inducing a euphoric sense of well-being ("abuse-potential") in the user.
It is next century's successors to these unpromising-sounding drugs, however, and not today's fast-acting recreational euphoriants, which promise to deliver the world's supposedly "euthymic" population from the sick psycho-chemical ghetto bequeathed by our genetic past. Potent, long-acting mood-brighteners - but not clinical "psychic anaesthetisers" or "quick-hit" street-drugs - will serve as a life-enriching stop-gap until radical gene-therapies enable us to knock out the Darwinian pathologies of consciousness altogether. Time-delayed designer euphoriants will foreshadow an extended product-line of innovative treatments. Collectively, they will cure what sophisticated post-human posterity will recognise as a gene-driven mood-disorder. A lot of the time at present, we just don't - and can't - conceptualise the extent of how unwell we are. For there are powerful arguments to suggest that everyday consciousness, insofar as it is not transcendentally wonderful, is symptomatic of profound psychological ill-health.
This possibility is not widely acknowledged in public today. Mental illness still carries a stigma. "Of-course-I'm-all-right. There's nothing wrong with me!" one may sometimes snappishly be told. To be depressive is to be fitness-impaired, low-status, a poor choice of mate, and generally uncool. So there are self-protective defence- and denial-mechanisms, as well as a plain failure of the imagination, at work.
Defensiveness and denial won't be needed for ever. A few generations hence,
the intoxicating joy of normal life will be genetically pre-programmed.
Psychoactive drugs will be redundant. Pure well-being can potentially become
a deep and natural presupposition of everyday life. Undiluted existential
happiness will infuse every second of waking and dreaming existence; and
pervade every aspect of one's body and psyche. Sadly, the sort of germ-line
gene-therapy needed to achieve lifelong, high-functioning euphoria for
everyone who thinks they can handle it is still some way off. In the transitional
era, chemical mood-uplifters will be essential too.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
1.1 The Biological Program.
Grand Meta-Narratives aren't very fashionable
at the moment. History can indeed seem like one damn thing after another.
The nearest we get these days to some kind of plot or story about where
life on earth is heading usually adds up to some simple-minded technological
determinism. Nevertheless, a sketch of one possible route by which all
sources of negative value will be purged from the world is set out below.
Other biological strategies for Cosmic Value-Maximisation(!) - or simply
making everyone a great deal happier - are in prospect too. Details and
variations matter. Every family of options for naturalising heaven-on-earth
needs to be exhaustively researched - and not just idly philosophised about.
Yet it is vital to distinguish the overall goal of banishing suffering
from our first faltering blueprints of how to achieve it. The technical
shortcomings of anything proposed here should not be allowed to taint the
overall strategy itself.
This particular biological program, at least, is inspired by an almost
desperate sense of moral urgency, not gung-ho technophilia. For it's worth
pausing and trying to practise, quite literally, a few minutes of systematic
empathy. Quite agonising things are happening to people like you, me and
our loved ones right now. The full horror of some sorts of suffering is
literally unspeakable and unimaginably dreadful. Under a "natural" Darwinian
regime, truly horrible experiences - as well as endemic low-grade malaise
- are both commonplace and inevitable. In Chapter Two, I argue the moral
case that they should be stopped. Since 'ought' implies 'can', however,
it must first be established that scrapping aversive experience really
is a biological option. I argue that the lesson of intracranial self-stimulation
studies - despite their disastrously bad contemporary image - is yes.
The biological blueprint set out below outlines only a cartoonish prototype of a mature post-Darwinian paradise. Its sketch of likely future neuro-scientific breakthroughs may well be wrong both in its few specifics and its projected time-scales. Experts in the relevant specialist fields will doubtless wince, at least in places. For The Hedonistic Imperative consists in a hand-waving, cross-disciplinary romp through dauntingly complex specialist topics. Inevitably, some of the pop neuroscience is simplistic to the point of parody. Eyebrows should be raised, too, at the dogmatic brevity with which various philosophical problems deserving book-length treatment are dispatched in a single sentence. The multitude of practical, medico-legal and socio-political problems which fulfilling our neurochemical Manifest Destiny will entail are largely passed over as well.
These caveats are important. Yet leaving them aside, the biological program may be divided, somewhat arbitrarily, into three stages. They are here ranked in order of difficulty. Luckily, the stages happen to coincide in relative ethical importance, since crude harm-reduction and pain-abolition is easier to accomplish than refining the architectural subtleties of paradise. Less happily, any biochemical description of the mechanics of the sublime just travesties the nature of the experience itself. The sub-academese prose below unavoidably debases what it aims to evoke. This is because of the contaminated associations of any terms associated with drug-abuse, genetic engineering, eugenics, or even the emotionally frigid atmosphere of the laboratory. Our present perspective on utopian biopsychiatry is jaundiced. For our education-system virtually ignores the psychobiological foundations of all emotional life. Happily, that system also provides the formal tools for us to describe and escape from our predicament.
What is really needed, above and beyond mere chemical formulae, is a new
network of concepts - a user's guide to map out the magically alien realms
of consciousness ahead of us. Yet by the time such tools can be developed
as new state-spaces of experience are accessed, the revolutionary conceptual
scheme they embody will be less urgently needed. One day, we may have thoughts
like sunsets. Their brilliance will replace the elusive and phenomenologically
thin series of sad little cognitive tickles which we (apparently) shuffle
around and via which this manifesto is written and read. In the meantime
the sordid, or at best impersonal, vocabulary of chemistry is all we can
rely on for communicating how to get things done. An earthly paradise can
be achieved only by the profane application of science. It won't happen
via the edifying discourses of religion or magic.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
1.2 Pumping Up The Volume.
One crude but effective ingredient of the
initial stage of the biological program will involve modifying the meso(cortico-)limbic
dopamine system. Controversially, and oversimplifying a little since dopamine
is not itself a magic "pleasure molecule", the mesolimbic reward pathways
serve as the final common pathway for pleasure in the brain. Neuronal dopamine-release
may be elicited "naturally" via biochemical transduction-mechanisms. It
is usually triggered by adaptive environmental stimuli. On the other hand,
dopamine-release may also be induced more directly via the use of recreational
drugs. The "rush" of crack cocaine, for instance, falsely signals a huge
Darwinian fitness benefit. Either way, although the central nervous system
has tens of billions of cells, its mesolimbic wellspring of pleasure, motivation
and libido has only some 30-40 thousand; and clearly this isn't nearly
enough.
The axons and dendrites of mesolimbic dopaminergic neurones innervate the
higher cortical regions of the brain. They thereby help mediate the genetically
adaptive "encephalisation of emotion". This neat little trick has served
our DNA, but frequently not us, fiendishly well. Emotional encephalisation
convinces its victims that happiness is inseparable from presence or absence
of variously innervated types of intentional object. We are happy or sad
'about' things. Entirely non-coincidentally, the realisation of our most
emotionally charged types of intentional object tends to promote the inclusive
fitness of our genes. Crudely, we like most what's good for them.
Unfortunately, they don't care about us. Our genes don't look after their vehicles for very long. In adult life, dopaminergic neurons die off at a rate of over 10% per decade. Their death ensures that senescence is marked by a decline in drive, libido, pleasure and the intensity of experience itself. Even in one's youth, the fullest and most beautiful scope for expression of the dopaminergic pleasure-cells is continually frustrated by inhibitory feedback. This derives both from the cells' own pre-synaptic autoreceptors and the processes of other, often less benign, neurons that synapse upon them.
Thus what must be included in any program of systematic life-enrichment
is a strategy of at once multiplying the numbers of, and selectively reducing
feedback inhibition on, mesolimbic dopamine cells. Achieving a modest initial
hundredfold, say, enrichment of an organism's capacity for well-being is
not, needless to add, simply a matter of genetically switching on an uncontrolled
proliferation of dopaminergic neurons; though it has to be said that, as
causes of death go, a tumour of the pleasure cells has got a certain whimsical
appeal. Nor, of course, does a regimen of sustained pleasure-amplification
simply entail enhancing the levels of dopamine in the synapses. Excessive
post-synaptic stimulation of particular dopamine receptor sub-types is
implicated in, for instance, the florid symptoms of schizophrenia. It also
marks the psychotic excesses of that ultimate egoist, the crack addict.
So crude monotherapy surely won't do the job alone.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
1.3 The Civilising Neurotransmitter.
There is a more promising twin-track approach.
This consists of boosting sub-types of both dopaminergic and serotonergic
function.
Serotonin has been described as the "civilising neurotransmitter". Such
a label is a useful piece of mental shorthand. It's still worth noting
that even this simple monoamine has fifteen or more functionally distinct
receptor sub-types. Serotonergic dysfunction is associated with irritability,
explosive anger, violence, sociopathy, and suicide. Conversely, the extraordinarily
deep sense of love, trust and empathy inspired by "the penicillin of the
soul", MDMA, is due primarily to the massive release of serotonin which
its use provokes. It causes only a modest release of dopamine. Both dopamine-
and serotonin-release are needed for the inhibitory effects of MDMA on
glutamate-evoked neuronal excitability in the nucleus accumbens to take
its full magical effect. In any event, the result of casually popping a
pill can be a life-defining revelation. The trouble today is that the magic
doesn't last.
There's no good reason why it shouldn't. A neurobehavioural system evolved to maximise Darwinian fitness can be redesigned to maximise personal well-being instead. On this basis, it would be eminently sensible to develop a delayed-action, non-neurotoxic drug or cocktail-mix of sustainable mood-brighteners. This could make us all very happy and revolutionise our archaic conception of mental health. Day-to-day life in drug-assisted Eden can blend, if we so choose, the most exalted, life-loving euphoria of a potent dopamine agonist with the serene and mystical love of an 'empathogen' or 'entactogen' such as MDMA ("ecstasy"). States of incisive, goal-directed thought can co-exist with a profound love for our fellow beings. If we want, we can make such states biologically natural; and eventually innate. There are good times ahead.
As hedonic engineering develops into a mature discipline, the generic modes of paradise we opt for can be genetically pre-coded. Native-born ecstatics will flourish. All the wonderful models discussed in this section of HI may come to be viewed as simple-minded prototypes. The innovative, high-specification bio-heavens beyond will be far richer. We lack the semantic competence to talk about them sensibly. Yet however inelegantly our goal may be accomplished at first, the ultimate strategic objective should be the neurochemical precision-engineering of happiness for every sentient organism on the planet.
Sounds flaky? Yes, but then so, originally, has almost every radical reform
movement in history; including, of course, the genuinely flaky ones.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
1.4 The Cardinal Importance of Delayed Gratification.
Eventually, well-being will be part of our
very nature. A robust network of homeostatic mechanisms will ensure all
hereditary ecstatics have gene-coded hedonic set-points way beyond today's
puny maxima. In the Transitional Era, however, the widespread use of mind-healing
drugs will in practice be unavoidable. Gene-therapy is still in its infancy;
and germ-line clinical trials are time-consuming in humans. So crucially,
the medically and socially responsible emphasis of the pharmacological
arm of the biological transition strategy must be on the (relatively) long-term
structural and functional effects in nervous tissue which a delayed-reward
euphoriant-mix will induce in the individual mind/brain. Fast-acting recreational
highs are a snare and a delusion. We must master - and educate our children
in - the pharmacological equivalent of the principle of deferred gratification.
The delay in
therapeutic benefit stemming from gene-triggered receptor re-regulation
can actually be very useful. Not merely is the development of tolerance
diminished. Uncontrolled and potentially noxious bingeing on a drug occurs
when there is minimal delay between ingestion and reward. By contrast,
the anticipated gene-switched, up- or down-regulation of the pre- and post-synaptic
neuronal receptors in a regimen of sustainable mood-enhancement will generally
take up to several weeks to complete. Fortunately, the ingredient of enhanced
serotonin function tends to increase patience and impulse-control as well
as mood.
Perhaps a comparison with nicotine can be of use here. In its present setting,
the drug is so addictive, not because of the quite minimal "high" induced,
but because of the sheer speed of onset of its intrinsically mild hit due
to the customary delivery mechanism. The "reward" comes about seven seconds
after inhalation. If the whole-body orgasmic rush of even crack-cocaine
were delayed for ten days or so after its consumption, then the drug would
be far less of a social and medical problem than it is at present. Tragically,
most of its current users seem unacquainted with, or have long since forgotten,
the concept of delayed reward. They might now be unwilling to wait nearly
so long.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
1.5 The Molecular Genetics Of Paradise.
Strategic, species-wide pharmacotherapy of the kind advocated above can
be complemented, and synergistically allied, with genetic engineering as
it matures from mere tinkering. Gene therapy will be targeted both on somatic
cells and, with even greater forethought, the germ-line. If cunningly applied,
a combination of the cellular enlargement of the meso-limbic dopamine system,
selectively enhanced metabolic function of key intra-cellular sub-types
of serotonergic pathway, and the disablement of several countervailing
inhibitory feedback processes will put in place the biomolecular architecture
for a major transition in human evolution - and life itself.
The re-engineering of bits of psycho-neural circuitry sketched above may,
it is true, seem somewhat ambitious. Perhaps it sounds impossibly futuristic.
Comparatively, however, these techniques amount to a primitively inept
form of piecemeal tinkering compared to the revolutionary redesign of the
mind/brain likely to be undertaken in millennia to come.
For it won't just be the quality and quantity of consciousness in the world which will be transformed in the early stages of the post-Darwinian Transition. As humanity emerges from the psychochemical Dark Ages, enriched dopaminergic function in particular will sharpen the sheer intensity of every moment of conscious existence. For a generation whose lifetimes span both modes of awareness, it will be as if they had just woken up after sleep-walking through life in a twilit stupor. Thereafter their former mundane and minimal existence will be recalled only as some kind of zombified trance-state. Our own "ordinary" consciousness may be unmasked as a shallow and uninteresting malaise whose properties we were physiologically incapable of recognising 'from the inside'. At present, however, we lack the neural substrates of a capacity to set archaic consciousness in a pre- and post-Darwinian context. "What does the fish know of the sea in which it swims?", remarked Einstein: homely, cracker-barrel-sounding wisdom, perhaps, but then even cracker-barrels yield the occasional nugget.
Other neurohormones, transcription factors, opioids, tyrosine-hydroxylase
activators, oxytocin-releasers, receptor density-regulators, intra-cellular
second- and third-messengers, phosphorylated proteins, and genetic repressors
and promoters which are implicated in the modulation of mood, emotional
tone and psychophysical pain will be reconfigured too as the biological
program unfolds. The details are messy and complicated. Naturally, neurotransmitter
systems finely interlock. They can be treated in isolation only conceptually
and for purposes of expository convenience. They form a complex and delicate
interplay of feedback loops that defies easy simplification and synopsis.
In centuries to follow, however, they will be collectively enlisted to
re-work the texture of experience. Our happiness will be enhanced with
ever greater artistry and finesse. Conversely, several vicious triggers
of extraordinary nastiness (e.g. bradykinin, substance P) will be banished
from the sensorium, one trusts for ever.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
1.6 The Re-encephalisation Of Emotion.
These procedures will lay the hedonic foundations
for a dizzyingly high ground-state of conscious existence. The most pressing
question to examine next is what will - and what should - be done with
it? How, and why, should emotion be encephalised in an era when intentionality
is no longer tied to furthering the inclusive fitness of self-replicating
DNA? What's worth being happy "about"?
For the real
intellectual challenge won't lie ultimately in sheer happiness-maximisation.
After all, if eternal bliss were the sole objective, then a rat with electrodes
fixed in its pleasure-centres already points the way forward. In fact,
our descendants may find generating generic states of life-long happiness
per se trivially easy. Most of us, however, are intellectually quite snobbish.
We don't want our emotions de-encephalised. We like good moods, but anything
resembling the prospect of a perpetual orgasmic frenzy of delight stirs
more ambivalent feelings. The limbic innervation of the neocortex has been
so adaptive because it allows sophisticated genetic vehicles to feel some
intentional objects are inherently good or bad. We want to feel that we
are happy for good reasons - genetically self-serving as they may so often
be.
We'll soon be in a position to de-fang this dangerous tendency altogether. But we won't want to abolish it. In generations to come, a primary focus of neuroscientific mind-making will be on remapping the axonal and dendritic arborisation of the neo-cortex which makes the rationalisation of emotion possible. The aim of this rational redesign can be to bootstrap our way into fulfilling our second-order desires for who and what we want to become. What we will ultimately turn into is hard to imagine. One may predict merely that it will be utterly sublime.
Using biotechnology to select and fine-tune a personality will partly depend on individual taste. One's choice of identity even in paradise will still be tempered by genetic biases, ancient cultural stereotypes, and the latest vagaries of fashion. The lure of hot-button super-normal stimuli will at first be very potent. Yet we may also be enchanted by ideas and modes of experience that today haven't even been conceptualised. Potentially, there are far more things to be happy "about" than we can possibly grasp.
On a societal level, some form of neuro-architectural planning permission will presumably still be needed for the purposes of orchestrating the multiple microcosms as each designer-heaven takes shape. Yet harmonisation should be more readily accomplished when people are already blissfully and empathetically happy - "all loved up". Neurologically, in fact, there is nothing to stop co-operating with others from being a source of rapturous joy; as alas it isn't always today. When life isn't perceived as an approximation to a zero-sum game, social existence is going to be far easier to co-ordinate.
Initially, it may be tempting for newly-enlightened ecstatics to seek the
idealised realisation of purely traditional objects of delight. Effectively,
we'll be able to have anything we've always wanted and more. This includes
enjoying the substrates of a vivid sense of reality, a sense of heightened
authenticity, and never-ending raw-edged excitement - or intense serenity
and spiritual peace. In these early days, subjects may find the idea of
fulfilling older conceptions of the good life a reassuring prospect. Prior
to their own personal heavenly transition, any paradoxical trepidation
coming from candidates for hedonic enrichment should be laid to rest by
the following reflection. Nothing we have previously enjoyed will afterwards
be unavailable or any less satisfying than before. In fact, we may be motivated
to pursue old goals with far greater gusto once weakness of will becomes
just an evolutionary curiosity. For weak will-power caused by dopamine
hypo-function is one of those neurological deficiencies which effort alone
can't overcome. Happily, in Paradise the frailest spirit can move mountains.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
1.7 How Could Anything Be So Good?
Perhaps a few examples of early post-Darwinian
life are in order.
The Nature-lover, for instance, will be able to contemplate with awe-struck
reverence scenes of overpowering sublimity eclipsing the superficial prettiness
on offer before.
A musician may wish that those of his functional modules which mediate musical appreciation should receive especially rich innervation from his freshly amped-up pleasure system. (S)he might then hear, and have the chance to play, music more exhilarating and numinously beautiful than his or her ancestors ever dreamed of; the celestial music of the spheres heard by privileged medieval mystics will be as a child's toy tin-whistle in comparison.
The sensualist will discover that what had previously passed for passionate sex had been merely a mildly agreeable piece of foreplay. Erotic pleasure of an intoxicating intensity that mortal flesh has never known will thereafter be enjoyable with a whole gamut of friends and lovers. This will be possible because jealousy, already transiently eliminable today under the influence of various serotonin-releasing agents, is not the sort of gene-inspired perversion of consciousness likely to be judged worthy of conservation in the new era.
A painter or connoisseur of the visual arts will be able to behold the secular equivalent of the beatific vision in a million different guises, each of indescribable glory. The toy-town lexical tokens we permute today will by then be an archaic residue of little use in evoking their majesty. As language evolves to reflect and navigate ever more exalted planes of being, fresh taxonomies of pleasure-concepts will be pioneered to help define newly-discovered modes of awareness. It sure beats a nine-til-five job.
As an exercise, the reader may care briefly to summon up the most delightful
fantasy (s)he can personally conceive. Agreeable as this may be, states
of divine happiness orders of magnitude more beautiful than anything the
contemporary mind can access will pervade the very fabric of reality in
generations to come. Even the most virile of imaginations can apprehend
in only the barest and formal sense the ravishing splendour that lies ahead.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
1.8 All We Need Is Love?
Still in a personal vein, fragile self-esteem
and shaky self-images will be beautified and recrystallised afresh. For
the first time in their lives, in many cases, human beings will be able
wholeheartedly to love both themselves and their own bodily self-images.
Bruised and mutilated egos can thus be strengthened. They can be regenerated
anew from the wreckage of the Darwinian past.
Love will take on new aspects and incarnations too. For instance, we will
be able, not just to love everyone, but to be perpetually in love with
everyone, as well; and perhaps we'll be far more worth loving than the
corrupted minds our genes program today. It's been said that when in love
we find it astonishing that it is possible to love someone else so much,
because normally we love each other so little. This indifference, or at
best mere diffuse benevolence, to the rest of the population is easily
taken for granted amid the harsh social realities of competitive consumer
capitalism. Yet our deficiencies in love are only another grim manifestation
of selfish (in the technical sense) DNA. If humans had collectively shared
the greater degree of genetic relatedness common to many of the social
insects (haplodiploidy), then we might already have been "naturally" able
to love each other with greater enthusiasm. Sociobiology explains our relative
coldness of heart.
Happily, in future it will be possible to mimic, and then magnify out of all recognition, the kind of altruistic devotion to each other which might have arisen if were we all 100% genetically-related clones. We'll all be able to love each other to bits. A delicious cocktail mix of oxytocin, phenethylamines and opioids - or potent god's-own wonderbrews not yet genetically-coded - can be automatically triggered whenever anyone one knows is present or recollected. Darwinian man, by contrast, will be seen as a mean-minded crypto-psychopath. Our successors will be far kinder. They'll combine absolute, unconditional and uninhibited love for each other with a celebration of the diversity of genes and cultures. At present this prospect seems some way off.
Another aspect of post-Transition love may be found even more surprising. Individual personal relationships may at last be bonded truly securely, should we so desire. Throughout the ages, dreadful pain has been caused by the soul-destroying cruelties of traditional modes of love. We acknowledge, in the main, that we hurt the most those we love. Yet we often simply can't stop ourselves from doing so. Before very long, if we really care enough, we'll actually be able to do something about it. Whatever their proximate causes, the distal origins of so many relationship break-ups lie, once again, in the competing interests of rival coalitions of genes. Just to take one example, two lovers, perhaps, who years before professed they would rather die than hurt each other, later part in tears and acrimony. The woman may find that with the decline in her reproductive potential over time she is no longer sexually attractive to the man who pledged his undying love. Her partner, quite possibly hating himself for his treachery, finds himself deserting her and their teenage offspring for a younger, sexier woman, and then fathers another family. Lives are destroyed; inclusive genetic fitness is served. Nature is barbarous and futile beyond belief.
After the Transition, on the other hand, one will be able to love somebody
more passionately than ever before. One will be safe in the knowledge that
one will never hurt them, nor be hurt by them in turn. True love really
can last forever, though responsible couples should take precautions. If
one desires a particular relationship to remain uniquely and enduringly
special, then the mutually co-ordinated design of each other's neural weight
spaces can ensure that a distinctively hill-topped plateau in the new hedonic
landscape structurally guarantees that each other's presence is always
uniquely fulfilling. Choosing how big a hit we get off each other's presence
is not an exact science today. Of course, it is possible that, generations
hence, exclusionary pair bonding may seem a quaint anachronism. It may
be regarded as just one more vestige of the genetic past which is fated
one day to pass away. The example above is recounted to show only how ill-defined
worries that anything precious one wants to save will be somehow sacrificed
in the post-Transition epoch can be discounted. We've nothing to lose.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
1.9 The Taste Of Depravity.
Now before considering the prospects for the
more distant future of affective states in the universe, the status of
non-human animals must be addressed. This is because most of the world's
suffering is undergone by members of other species. A convergence of evidence
suggests that the nature and relative extent of organic life's biological
capacity to suffer is mediated by key neuronal firing frequencies; cellular,
synaptic and receptor densities; and a distinctive neurochemical and functional
architecture of the central nervous system. Pain is not rooted in a capacity
for a generative syntax.
Humanity often behaves as though it were. For we presently keep hundreds
of millions of other sentient beings in unimaginably frightful conditions.
We do so for no better reason than to satisfy our culinary tastes. It has
aptly been remarked that if animals had a conception of the Devil, he would
surely have human form. Alas this is no mere rhetorical conceit. Contemporary
humans deliberately incarcerate and butcher our fellow creatures in a vast,
state-sanctioned apparatus of concentration and extermination camps. They
are run with mechanised horror for commercial profit. In retrospect, our
descendants may view them as a defining feature of our age in a way akin
to our own conception of the Third Reich. Analogously, their sheer viciousness
and even existence is usually camouflaged behind a morass of bland euphemism.
Fortunately for our peace of mind, at least, we find it hard properly to
conceive of what we're being spared. Conditions inside the camps and factories
are frequently so gruesome that members of the public have to be barred
from watching the atrocities that go on inside them.
For the most part, however, we are willing accomplices in our own ignorance. By our purchases we pay others to commit acts of extreme violence which might otherwise upset our squeamish sensibilities. Ironically, anybody who practises, or connives in, the maltreatment of a helpless and undeveloped infant of our own species is likely to be demonised and reviled. Ordinary decent people will find it "inconceivable" how such an "inhuman" monster could cause such suffering to the young, innocent and helpless. So (s)he will be prosecuted and locked up.
What we are doing in the death-factories is so vile that a few lines of text can scarcely even hint at its ghastliness. Nevertheless, we are so inured to the notion of exploiting and killing other sentient beings to titillate our palates that many otherwise "sophisticated" people will find the starkness of expression of these paragraphs somehow sensationalistic; or perhaps "emotive", as if the reality of such suffering could properly be otherwise.
Caring about the plight of the non-human victims of our actions is not a case of sentimental bunny-hugging nor of child-like anthropomorphism. Nor is it a matter of caring more about animals than humans; nor even, as is sometimes suggested with all appearance of seriousness, outright misanthropy. "Tender-minded" people who worry about the torture of non-humans are on balance temperamentally more rather than less inclined to act in an effort to minimise human suffering too. Such contrasts and false antitheses are in any case unhelpful. Simply by abstaining from eating meat, for instance, one can still spend just as much time campaigning for exclusively human causes as one did as a practising meat-eater.
There is one real glimmer of hope amid the ongoing carnage. Within the next hundred years or so, and possibly sooner, biotechnology will enable the human species cost-effectively to mass-produce edible cellular protein, and indeed all forms of food, of a flavour and texture indistinguishable from, or tastier than, the sanitised animal products we now eat. As our palates become satisfied by other means, the moral arguments for animal rights will start to seem overwhelmingly compelling. The Western(ised) planetary elite will finally start to award the sentient fellow creatures we torture and kill a moral status akin to human infants and toddlers. Veganism, though not in quite the contemporary sense, will become the global norm. Thanks to genetic engineering, the huge reduction in gratuitous suffering forecast here is likely to take place even if none of the other predictions of HI are borne out. If they are, then the humblest snack will taste more delicious than the ambrosial food of the gods. Today's gourmets might as well be feeding on greasy chips.
Much more seriously, in those traditional eco-systems that we chose to retain, millions of non-human animals will continue periodically to starve, die horribly of thirst and disease, or even get eaten alive. This is commonly viewed as "natural" and hence basically OK. It would indeed be comforting to think that in some sense this ongoing animal holocaust doesn't matter too much. We often find it convenient to act as though the capacity to suffer were somehow inseparably bound up with linguistic ability or ratiocinative prowess. Yet there is absolutely no evidence that this is the case, and a great deal that it isn't.
The functional regions of the brain which subserve physical agony, the
"pain centres", and the mainly limbic substrates of emotion, appear in
phylogenetic terms to be remarkably constant in the vertebrate line. The
neural pathways involving serotonin, the periaquaductal grey matter, bradykinin,
dynorphin, ATP receptors, the major opioid families, substance P etc all
existed long before hominids walked the earth. Not merely is the biochemistry
of suffering disturbingly similar where not effectively type-identical
across a wide spectrum of vertebrate (and even some invertebrate) species.
It is at least possible that members of any species whose members have
more pain cells exhibiting greater synaptic density than humans sometimes
suffer more atrociously than we do, whatever their notional "intelligence".
As a utilitarian [technically, an ethical negative-utilitarian - see below),
I would have to say, counter-intuitively, that were this to be the case,
then such "hyperalgesic" life-forms would intrinsically matter, and they
would themselves find that things intrinsically matter, more so than we
do. This sounds extravagantly overstated. But it is just the ethical yardstick
by which we should be reckoned to matter more than our phenomenologically
impoverished silicon etc intellectual mentors centuries hence. One must
just hope the disquieting notion that anything, anywhere, can suffer more
than humans do is ill-conceived.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
1.10 On The Misguided Romanticisation of Feline
Psychopaths.
In future, anyhow, the life-forms which exist
on this planet will be there purely because we allow them to be so, or
choose to create them. This smacks of hubris; it is also true. Increasingly,
we are able to configure the matter and energy of the world in any way
we so desire consistent with the laws of physics. So the moral and practical
question arises: what other organisms, and therefore what other modes of
experience, are we going either to create or retain "in the wild" outside
the gene-banks and computer software libraries in millennia to come?
One may suspect that most people could bear the possible loss of a few
hundred thousand species of beetle with relative equanimity. Familiar if
eugenically-enhanced herbivores, on the other hand, can be allowed to graze
securely within the confines of a well-regulated natural habitat. They
will best be treated with long-acting depot contraceptives to stop uncontrolled
breeding. Their happiness should prove easier to engineer genetically than
is possible in humans. This is on the assumption that non-humans are less
intellectually fastidious in their pleasures than are, on occasion, some
members of our own kind.
Yet what about the carnivorous species? It is easy to romanticise, say, tigers or lions and cats. We admire their magnificent beauty, strength and agility. But we would regard their notional human counterparts as wanton psychopaths of the worst kind. So just as there is no need to recreate the natural habitat of smart, blond, handsome Nazi storm-troopers who can then prey on their natural victims (and Nazis are a no less natural and noteworthy pattern of matter and energy thrown up in the course of evolution, albeit of a type now fortunately extinct), likewise the practice of continuing to breed pre-programmed feline killing machines in homage to Nature is ethically untenable too. It is not, needless to say, the fault of cats that they are prone to torturing mice; but then, given the equations of physics, it isn't the fault of Nazis they try to persecute Jews. This is no reason to let them continue to do so.
In a triumph of aestheticism over morality, many animal lovers otherwise
sympathetic to the sentiments expressed here will doubtless be aghast at
the very idea of losing such loveable companions and time-honoured killers
as members of the cat family; but then they are unlikely to be hunted down
in terror or physically eaten alive, which lends a rather different perspective
to any issue at all.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
1.11 The Last Twisted Molecule On Earth?
This meditation on the plight of our fellow
species leads to one of the few precise, and potentially falsifiable, predictions
to be hazarded here about the next couple of thousand years.
At some momentous and exactly dateable time, the last unpleasant experience
ever to occur on this planet will take place. Possibly, it will be a (purely
comparatively) minor pain in some (to us) obscure marine invertebrate.
This event will occur well before the end of the fourth millennium. It
may even be technically feasible - though in practice unlikely - for us
to abolish unpleasantness altogether by the end of the third.
Heady stuff. Yet just as the smallpox virus was systematically hunted down to extinction, so the precise molecular signature(s) of aversive experience and its predisposing genes will predictably be hunted down and wiped out as well. The systematic application of nanotechnology, self-reproducing micro-miniaturised robots armed with supercomputer processing power, and ultra-sophisticated genetic engineering, perhaps using retro-viral vectors, will abolish the root of all evil in its naturalistic guise.
Of course, pain and unhappiness apparently take myriad forms. So it might be supposed that an impossibly large hotchpotch of biochemical reactions will have to be eliminated before the emancipatory project can be complete. The difficulty, and more controversially the impossibility, of establishing non-trivial type-type identities between physical and higher mental states would seem to make the task of purging unpleasantness from the world even worse.
In one respect at least, however, the many faces of misery are deceptive.
Like the various nominal sources of happiness, they foster a genetically
adaptive delusion. In this case, the delusion is that [Darwinian] fitness-diminishing
phenomena are inherently bad. It is an "adaptation" born of the mechanisms
by the primary neural processes which mediate emotion physically infiltrate
and infuse the neo-cortex. Millions of years of DNA-driven encephalisation
have obscured emotion's primitive substrates deep in the mind/brain. These
substrates can be coded out. And by striking at the ancient limbic motors
of despair, future paradise-engineering specialists should induce its legion
of cognitive hangers-on to dissipate too. First in humans and, progressing
"down" the phylogenetic tree, eventually in every non-human metazoan as
well, all of the incomprehensibly diverse modes of experience a mind/brain
can undergo should share the property of being generically delightful.
A uniquely vile era in the history of the world will then have drawn to
a close.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
1.12 The Persistence of Hard-Core Porn?
Quite what vestiges of the past will be archived
after nastiness has been purged from our consciousness is hard to guess.
Just as we have retained (but one may trust that we will never use) the
precise information necessary to re-create the smallpox virus - for we
know its entire genome precisely - so records of the phylogeny and molecular
architecture of pain and depression will presumably be preserved too.
It is hard to see why unpleasant types of pattern should ever be physically
revived. Perhaps they will remain largely undeciphered. The interpretation
of their dangerous and quasi-pornographic formalism may be accessible to
our descendants, if at all, only by ill-understood analogy. For post-humans
will know about hedonic gradients. After all, insofar as shifting nuances
of delight will imbue whatever they think about, pleasure differentials
will most plausibly remain the primary motivators to action. So distant
generations should be able, in the abstract at least, to conceptualise
"pain" and "despair". Such states can be imagined as modes of consciousness
far lower in the heavenly hierarchy - a level where a generic property
of experience itself undergoes a kind of mysterious phase change. But beyond
the ill-defined cross-over point, perhaps, our ecstatic posterity will
find the properties of experience on the wrong side of the great divide
elusive.
For their sake, it must be hoped that purebred ecstatics keep any intellectual curiosity about such taboo mysteries in check. They will be in no position to make an informed choice before opting to go slumming in the abyss. Nothing could prepare them for the horror they would find. Fortunately, they will most probably lack our prurient interest in the depraved and obscene.
It might here be objected that states of comparatively diminished pleasure are tantamount to states of unhappiness. So short of promoting a uniform, action-paralysing level of lifetime happiness, then surely aversive states will be endemic even in the mature post-Darwinian regime.
This objection is plausible but ill-conceived. When faced with two painful
alternatives, one's opting for the lesser of two evils doesn't make a still
painful experience somehow pleasurable. Likewise, experiencing the lesser
of two delights isn't somehow really painful; it's just that pleasure cells
are very greedy indeed, and always avid for more of the same.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
1.13 The Growing Pleasures of Homunculi.
On the assumption that they will indeed always ask for more, what else
can be said about the distant future of emotion in the universe? How will
post-humans actually spend their lives, and what will it feel like to exist,
after Heaven has been biologically domesticated?
First, a note of caution. Today most of our futurist fantasies focus on
hard-core hi-tech. We lap up the world of Star-Trek fantasy-physics. Exotic
new emotions, however, are as unimaginable to us as exotic new phenomenal
colours. They are just empty, abstract possibilities we can idly gesture
at, but no more. Implicitly, we assume that our ancient vertebrate repertoire
of fitness-enhancing sentiment will characterise both our post-human descendants
and any alien life-forms they encounter. We're even prone to anthropomorphise
inorganic robots in the same manner. We assume they'll "feel" superior
and "want" to dominate us (shades again of the African savannah!) Yet the
emotional economy of a post-Darwinian psyche may be incommensurable with
anything that's gone before. Indeed the entire inner life of post-Darwinians
may be opaque to our hunter-gatherer minds. The first-person texture of
their modes of experience may be nothing like our own in anything but name.
Even if we could glimpse the future, perhaps we'd be like cats watching
TV. We just wouldn't understand the significance of what was going on.
Unfortunately, there's no way to map out the extent of our cognitive closure from within. This is frustrating. If quantum cosmologists can theorise about the first 10-43 second after the Big Bang, thirteen billion and more years ago, and still, rightly, be counted as practising hard science, it's a shame that conjectures we do make about the living world a few thousand or million years hence have to be treated, not even as soft science, but as science-fiction. There are too many unknown unknowns to predict with any rational confidence. Merely extrapolating present trends is bound to mislead. The projected time-scales of even relatively predictable biomedical triumphs, e.g. the elimination of the ageing process, are vague. HI may veer towards heady speculation; but by the end of third millennium, life and consciousness may be more foreign to the contemporary imagination than even the most extravagant prediction dreamed up here. On the other hand, for all we know, some variant of the pleasure-principle is a universal - and universally intelligible - signature of sentient life; and its apotheosis in some sort of sublime cosmic orgasm is the ultimate destiny of the Universe. [This may overtax one's credulity; the Big Bang indeed!] We simply don't have enough evidence. That said, we may still incautiously proceed.
Once suffering has been abolished, the era of old-fashioned moral choices will come to an end. The physiological mechanisms underlying the mind-brain's value-creation processes will be unravelled during the invention of a pain-free world; but the kind of naturalised, mind-dependent value created (and maximised?) by paradise-engineers after the phenomenology of nastiness has disappeared won't embrace ethical categories in a sense we presently understand. The heroic moral urgency will have gone; indeed there is a risk that truly hedonistic themes as discussed in these sections of HI will divert attention away from the utter moral seriousness of the whole post-Darwinian project as conceived today.
Even so, here's a quick run-down of some of the long-term options.
First, the present dimensions of the human mind and its affective capabilities are limited by the size of the female birth canal. So long as selection pressures favoured the evolution of more potently nasty biological substrates - primed to trigger adaptive bouts of agony and emotional wretchedness - then the birthing constraint has been one small mercy at least.
It won't last; but then it won't need to. After the global application of cross-species genetic engineering has ensured that suffering is physiologically impossible, such a restriction of size would only retard the emotional development and maturation of the living world. For healthy [non-hippocampal] neurons, unfortunately, don't reproduce. We have almost a full complement at birth. They die off somewhat erratically thereafter. Once it becomes feasible to nurture the human embryo and foetus from conception to term in an artificial extra-uterine environment, however, then the number as well as quality and synaptic density of nerve cells can be selectively multiplied with a clear utilitarian conscience. So can receptor density, post-synaptic transduction-mechanisms and vital genetic transcription control-factors in the pleasure-pathways. The serotonin-producing subgenual prefrontal cortex can be enlarged and enriched too. Puzzlingly, today's clinically acknowledged depressives have on average over 40% less brain tissue here than controls. This region seems to be critical for the processing of emotions related to complex personal and social situations. Its role should grow. After we've designed more sophisticated and socially responsible neural circuitry, all of our emotionally pre-literate modes of social life may come to be seen as shallow and rudimentary.
It is unclear quite how many orders of magnitude larger a super-organism's mind/brain could in theory be scaled upwards before running up against insuperable(?) design-constraints. It's unclear, too, whether a "Jupiter brain" could undergo the quantum mechanical coherent states needed to sustain a unitary experiential manifold (cf. Sellars' "grain problem" of consciousness) and thus support a potentially integrated "Jupiter-self". In the meantime, and on a more conservative scale, gigantic societies of hedonistic super-neurons can be grown and self-sculpted to form progressively larger, happier and more richly variegated virtual worlds.
It might be supposed that access to unparalleled states of whole-body orgasmic euphoria fuelled by a vastly hypertrophied and souped-up pleasure apparatus would be quite enough for anyone. Well, perhaps; it depends on one's circle of acquaintance. Two flavours of happiness always worth distinguishing are blissful satiety and euphoric incentive-motivation. If, as predicted, it's the latter dopaminergic engine of progress which will power the post-Transition era, then the delights cited above will be only a foretaste of further millennial Transitions - and whatever mind-wrenching meta-paradigm shifts their advent entails.
For a start, the somato-sensory cortex and its bodily "homunculus" currently occupy only a very modest portion of the brain. Its comparatively small size marks it as another obsolescent relic from Darwinian antiquity. Using the great bulk of the cortex to run data-driven egocentric simulations of the external environment, and not just the egocentric body-image of the host vehicle, tended to maximise genetic fitness on the African savannah. With predatory lions long gone, such states of partial self-alienation become less useful. So in future somato-sensory-style cells can be used to seed the other areas of the cortex and its adjacent structures. They can thereby selectively interpenetrate the rest of each person's experiential manifold. Accordingly, whole-body hyper-orgasmic rapture can be optionally extended to impregnate an entire psycho-neural virtual world. The mystic's dream of becoming one with the universe - albeit unwittingly only with his own neural micro-cosmos - can be realised in a total ecstasy of the senses and neurochemical soul. Cosmic indeed.
Life could get better still. Today the nucleus accumbens and its allied
mesolimbic structures don't consist of raw pleasure circuitry. Certain
biomolecules (e.g. the dynorphin which accumulates during chronic psychostimulant
use and participates in the craving characteristic of cocaine withdrawal),
are unpleasant and dysfunctional. They can be genetically edited out. There
is a much more exciting possibility as well. Most cortical neurons have
no inherent capacity for well-being, let alone autonomous hedonism. As
noted, they rely on innervation from the monoaminergic etc neurons to lend
an affective tone to whatever functional role and flavour of subjectivity
they express. But once the precise molecular signatures of experiential
ecstasy are isolated in the pleasure pathways, then their metabolic reactions
can be transplanted to other types of neuron too: hedonic democracy.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
1.14 Post-Perceptual Consciousness.
Many future intentional foci of delight will
be embedded in types of consciousness qualitatively as well as quantitatively
alien to pre-Transitional humans. It is chastening to reflect that a seemingly
minor variation in structural neuro-protein generates types of experience
as disparate as sight and sound. Heaven knows what further incommensurable
modes of what-it's-like-ness ("qualia") will come to light when much more
far-reaching changes in the architecture of excitable cells are engineered.
For the Darwinian status quo is poised to crumble. All but a trivial volume
of (what one may abstractly conceive as) experiential weight space has
hitherto been physiologically out of bounds. There's nothing unnatural
about it. But until now, DNA coding for the structures that got us there
would have involved crossing genetically maladaptive dips in the fitness
landscape. Desert-hopping across it is a process which neo-Darwinian evolution
precludes. Natural selection has no foresight. Once such new kinds of consciousness
are finally accessed by design, however, they need not be deployed in a
traditional role of tracking, or responding to, extraneous environmental
patterns. They can first be hedonically colonised; and then artistically
explored and reordered, woven into rich narrative structures and wild adventures,
awarded new functional roles in the mind/brain, or perhaps just savoured
for their intrinsic fascination.
Old definitions of self and reality are likely to fall apart in unpredictable ways. It's worth recalling how, at present, occurrent thought-episodes are typically decomposed into their nominally cognitive, affective and volitional aspects. The mysterious trinity may prove just trifling variations, each with their own minor nuances, of a much wider phenomenological family of "serial" streams of consciousness. These new serial modes await discovery or biotechnical invention. Some of the new modes may eventually function computationally as quasi-virtual machines spun from massively parallel cerebral consciousness; but the rest needn't play any distinctive functional role at all. Other than to describe all such subtle kinds of what-it's-like-ness as generically delightful when suitably innervated, their nature can't be intelligently speculated upon here. We're just kidding ourselves when we brag about what a rich language we've got today. For it is easy to be seduced by the indefinitely large productive capacity of the early human language-generating mechanism into making a pardonably false assumption. This is that syntax enables one to think and speak about an unlimited variety of things. Yet lying latent among previously inaccessible and maladaptive neurochemical pathways are bound to be immense reaches of experiential hyper-weirdness which - shallow semantic paradoxes aside - can't be properly thought of at all. Their alien exotica will still be cognitively closed off for a long time to come. In the case of unknown hell-states and worse, it may be hoped they will remain impenetrable for ever.
Such hypothesised new categories of experience will be empirically discovered, generated and decently emotionally encephalised only with the aid of first-personal exploration of their intrinsic properties. Observation without experimentation is not enough. Systematic experimental manipulation of consciousness via psychoactive agents will complement the third-person perspective of physical science. Exploration will be most prudently conducted by ecstatics, native-born or otherwise, rather than by gene-disordered Darwinian minds. This is because genetically undoctored savages like ourselves are liable to go off on worse trips than we're on at present. At any rate, a priori philosophising on psychedelia's possible nature, using our old neurochemical legacy hardware ploughing away in the same old conceptual ruts, simply won't work. Contemporary experience and linguistic description lacks the necessary semantic primitives to do the job. Only semantic primitives drawn from the new modes of experience - not mere inference-churning using our present limited repertoire of concepts - will conceivably allow a theoretical understanding of the psychedelic cosmos. New primitives will be needed as well to understand genuinely novel emotions, sensations, modes of introspection and reflexive self-awareness.
This isn't yet consensus wisdom. In mainstream academia, any study of consciousness as a true experimental discipline rather than as a topic of scholastic disputation is nearly impossible. Accounts of systematic first-personal manipulation of its only accessible instance is generally reckoned unpublishable and discreditable. Ironically, we mock the obtuseness of Galileo's clerical opponents for refusing to look through his telescope. Yet we treasure our own peace of mind no less dearly; so there is little reason for intellectual complacency. In our repressive drug laws we, too, outlaw and penalise forms of knowledge truly disturbing to the established order. Psychedelics trigger changes of mind which are radically subversive of the existing social, political and academic power-structure and its definitions of reality. The severe penalties for publicly advocating and spreading such dangerous knowledge are not notably more merciful than those of the Inquisition - our prisons are brutal places - though likewise public recantation and penance can sometimes mitigate the full rigour of punishment.
The psychedelias of post-human ecstatics are too hard to contemplate. Predictions for the more distant future of even affective states in the universe are liable to get wilder too. Not merely are we ignorant of the newly synthesised and discovered emotions that biotechnology will deliver. We can't possibly know what neo-cortical "cognitive" processes they will saturate and enrich.
Will consciousness in its current guise of phenomenological and quasi-computational mind take on post-cellular or prosthetically enriched forms? Or, in defence of carbon chauvinism, is there a micro-functionalist argument that the unique structure of the carbon atom and its valence properties means that only organic experiential manifolds and their infused emotions are feasible? Will there come, eventually, a post-personal era in which discrete, gene-generated superminds choose progressively to coalesce; or will the fragmented island universes left over from the depths of the Darwinian past continue in semi-autonomous isolation indefinitely? If consciousness is ontologically fundamental to the cosmos, rather than a tacked-on "nomological dangler", do superstrings [M-branes etc] vibrating at energies orders of magnitude higher than ours support modes and intensities of experience correspondingly greater than those of the current low-energy regime? Or do they really lack what-it's-like-ness altogether?
Needless to say, we don't know the answers to such questions one way or
the other. All that will be predicted here with any semblance of confidence
is that one ancient, soul-polluting type of experience, the generically
unpleasant, will soon go the way of the proverbial dodo.
(Chapter Two can safely be skipped or aggressively
skimmed even by the analytic philosophers for whom it was primarily intended.
It contains a defence of HI on the basis of, first, practical means-ends
rationality and, secondly, ethical negative utilitarianism. The instrumental
case from means-ends rationality derives from the broad applicability of
psychological hedonism. This isn't here construed as a universal law. It's
just a trite everyday rule of thumb: we spend a lot of time trying to make
ourselves happy. Often we fail. HI achieves what we're striving for with
unique efficiency and success. The ethical utilitarian case for HI, on
the other hand, rests partly on a conception of how morality can be naturalised
consistently with a recognisably scientific account of the nature of the
world. Value is here construed as a distinctive - and biologically maximisable
- mode of experience. Its subjective texture is coded by a particular type
of biomolecular architecture. That architecture can be enriched and extended.
Positive value can be maximised. Negative value can eventually be eliminated.
Thus HI, it will be claimed, amounts to rather more than one individual's
quirky conjectures and value-judgements. The biological program is also
our natural destiny. The coming of the pain-free post-Darwinian Era will
mark both a major transition in the evolution of life and the moral foundation
of any future civilisation.)
Chapter 2
(Chapter Two can safely be skipped or aggressively skimmed even by the analytic philosophers for whom it was primarily intended. It contains a defence of HI on the basis of, first, practical means-ends rationality and, secondly, ethical negative utilitarianism. The instrumental case from means-ends rationality derives from the broad applicability of psychological hedonism. This isn't here construed as a universal law. It's just a trite everyday rule of thumb: we spend a lot of time trying to make ourselves happy. Often we fail. HI achieves what we're striving for with unique efficiency and success. The ethical utilitarian case for HI, on the other hand, rests partly on a conception of how morality can be naturalised consistently with a recognisably scientific account of the nature of the world. Value is here construed as a distinctive - and biologically maximisable - mode of experience. Its subjective texture is coded by a particular type of biomolecular architecture. That architecture can be enriched and extended. Positive value can be maximised. Negative value can eventually be eliminated. Thus HI, it will be claimed, amounts to rather more than one individual's quirky set of conjectures and value-judgements. The biological program is also our natural destiny. The coming of the pain-free post-Darwinian Era will mark both a major transition in the evolution of life and the moral foundation of any future civilisation.)
2. Why?
"What right have we to be happy?"
(Ibsen)
2.0 The Psychology Of Armchair Hedonism.
So technically, in principle, it can be done.
Paradise can be biologically implemented. Ubiquitous well-being is neurochemically
feasible. Yet is it really worth having? What's wrong with suffering, anyway?
What's so good about happiness? What is the link, if any, between moral
value and maximising personal well-being? Are the transcendentally happy
states advocated here really any more valuable than the Darwinian status
quo? Or are value-judgements intrinsically subjective and truth-valueless?
There are both practical and ethical reasons for planning a global project to abolish aversive experience. The practical reasons will be tackled first. The ethical case will be argued next, followed by a [skippable; life is short] defence of an ontology of objective values designed to redeem the ethical stance adopted here from the charge of idle subjectivism.
The instrumental rationality of the biological program derives from nothing more abstruse than some hard-headed means-ends analysis. This analysis is best introduced via an examination of a biologised variant of the theory of psychological hedonism. We all dance away our lives to the tune of the sovereign pleasure-pain axis. It will be argued that for all the complications and anomalies the theory brings in its wake, psychological hedonism contains a substantial core of truth. The point to be kept in mind throughout the qualifications and elaborations to follow is that even goals found worth pursuing only intermittently or inconsistently are still worth pursuing rationally. As it is at present, we pursue the many faces of happiness avidly but with frighteningly irrational, and not infrequently murderous, levels of ineptitude. Fortunately, all the severely sub-optimal little local minima of ill-being in which genetic vehicles get stuck can be replaced by a global maximum of happiness and well-being.
So what is this alleged inbuilt drive which the biological blueprint finally allows us to achieve?
Psychological hedonism has been variously regarded as a simple truism, an obvious falsehood, and as so completely vacuous as to be not even wrong. Here it is assumed to be a hypothesis which, properly formulated, is both substantially true and important in its implications. If it were even broadly correct, and if we were all constitutionally motivated by the pursuit, albeit typically under other descriptions, of a generic type of mesolimbic core state that our competing diversity of intentional objects only disguises, then the practical answer to the question "why?" would in essence be simple. Whether or not we should genetically reprogram the hedonic treadmill reduces to a straightforward issue of means-ends rationality. What is the most effective, and more pertinently the only, way to achieve what constitutionally we're already seeking in a multitude of guises? How can these emotionally ideal sorts of meso-limbic mind/brain states we're striving for be achieved and, more importantly, sustained?
Of course, even if some variant of psychological hedonism were to be in substance correct, it is always open to the sceptic next to ask "but then why be rational?" He might then even (ir?)rationally advance (ir?)rational arguments to support(?) his (in?)consistent position. Yet the self-defeating nature of irrational behaviour, and the variably camouflaged incoherence of irrational thought, means this option will not be explored here in any depth.
More subtly, it is always open to a critic of the biological program to acknowledge that psychological hedonism may be substantially true, but to hold that there are countervailing moral considerations why it would be good if we failed to achieve what we were [sometimes only unwittingly] after. Hence, on this view, it would be morally preferable for us to continue on a selective basis to act irrationally and ineffectually. In other words, given that the thought that one is a moral agent is psychochemically satisfying, and the proposals canvassed here are found, paradoxically, to be unpleasantly immoral, it would be morally better if the rational biological program outlined in this paper were not adopted.
All the above, however, presupposes rather than argues the case for the
broad accuracy of psychological hedonist hypothesis. The chain of argument
to be presented here for its substantial kernel of truth is, at least at
face value, extremely weak. This is because one link is going to rely on
an appeal to introspection. Since the very word sends a shudder of distaste
down many fastidious scientific spines, a few very brief reflections on
the nature and epistemological status of the suspect faculty are first
in order.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
2.1 How To Contemplate An Introspective Void.
Does introspection reliably tell us we're
pleasure-seekers and pain-avoiders? If so, is there a better way of achieving
what our mind/brains are up to?
Exteroceptive, so called "perceptual" data are crucial to the empirical method(s) characteristic, and arguably definitive, of the natural sciences. Introspective evidence is generally disparaged by the scientific mandarinate as cognitively worthless. The curiously named "third-person" perspective rules. Yet a distinctive and potentially fitness-enhancing faculty - so central to so many ordinary people's mental life - has presumably been selected for, and not just adventitiously selected, in the course of evolution. Even an unreliable and highly fallible system of neuropsychological self-monitoring could still have conferred differential adaptive value. Any insight, however incomplete, into the underlying causal reasons for one's behaviour can also, by analogy, logical inference or simulation, help one partially to understand and anticipate the behaviour of conspecifics and genetic competitors.
Methodologically, it is admittedly unclear how introspection can be studied
or even defined scientifically. Moreover, though it is an intrinsic part
of the natural world, an unfortunate conflation of the two senses of the
term "subjective" often leads to its being ontologically downgraded as
well as methodologically discounted. Of course, it can't be denied that
in trying to offer introspective reports subjects sometimes confabulate.
They can demonstrably deceive both themselves and others. The different
functional modules of the brain, however tightly integrated, do not simply
interpenetrate. Hence the merely locally distributed neuronal ensembles
of one particular module can't always know about what's going on in the
others, nor report on it if they can. This means verbal sincerity is no
guarantee of veracity. Worse still, in initiating some of one's actions,
one just doesn't seem to have much in the way of (even illusory) introspective
self-insight at all. We've got access to much of the product but very little
of the process. Moreover a lot of our nominal actions would appear to be
mainly automatic. Many more are not preceded by any notable introspective
musings or a hedonic weighing of options and possible consequences. So
how can we be said to be "really" seeking happiness?
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
2.2 The Importance of Banality.
In spite of all the above, it is still worth making a crashingly banal but cardinally important observation. It relates to the implicit criteria one uses in deciding consciously to act in a certain way rather than another when more than one option is perceived to be available. For at face value, one performs, at the very least, an extraordinarily large number of actions because one's image or concept of what they will notionally bring about makes one apparently more satisfied or less dissatisfied, however marginally; and because one's notion of what not doing so would entail is either less satisfying, affectively neutral or more aversive than acting otherwise. There are other, probably more felicitous, ways of formulating the idea, but their gist is essentially the same.
Banal or otherwise, a knowledge of the existence and nature of this difference in affective tone when one contemplates, and then carries through, alternative courses of action can be derived only from introspection; but is nonetheless important. From a third-person perspective, it is true, biological science can elucidate a physical counterpart to this subjective motivational impression. By experimentally enhancing or attenuating meso-limbic dopamine function, neuropharmacologists can use stimulants or neuroleptics to show the system's pivotal role in determining how the higher vertebrates behave. Neuroscience can even christen certain brain areas "pleasure centres", wire them with electrodes, and then demonstrate their irresistible potency. Yet it is only through correlating, and then identifying, particular types of physiological function and structure with particular modes of subjective experience that biology can attempt to explain how a person acts, rather than just physically behaves, at all.
Endorsing psychological hedonism as a theory of action - and compulsion in need of biotechnically rationalising - is not the same as saying that one always acts selfishly, or at least not selfishly in the sense of serving only one's own notional interests at the expense of other people's. Selfish genes can sometimes flourish by throwing up unselfconsciously selfless phenotypes. Imagining the happiness of friends and family, for example, can serve as a powerful source of motivation. So, too, can satisfying an idealised self-image of oneself as a moral person. More radically, there is a sense in which even sacrificing one's life for one's family or country isn't anomalous in the context of the hypothesis either. In certain circumstances, the image of living may afford less satisfaction than the image of oneself notionally acting and dying for the sake of others. Hence one opts for (one's emotionally encephalised image of) oblivion.
What the hypothesis of psychological hedonism doesn't even begin to answer
is why the meso (cortico-)limbic dopamine system has the extraordinary
and uniquely addictive phenomenology from whose encephalised inspiration,
in a sense, our civilisation has been built. Why does it feel so irresistibly
good? This question is simply too deep to answer here.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
2.3 Vacuous Desires?
Even if it were true for the most part as
so defined, might psychological hedonism be tenable only because it is
effectively vacuous - "not even wrong"? For what test could possibly falsify
the hypothesis? With what states of affairs could it ever be inconsistent?
I don't think the charge of vacuity can be sustained. There is indeed a close conceptual connection between the theory and our notion of action itself, yet this is a reflection of the theory's empirical adequacy rather than vacuity. Two examples and potential falsifiers may be noted here. First, psychological hedonism helps explain why one can never tire of having one's pleasure centres stimulated, naturally or otherwise, and why the standards of even the most priggish paragon of moral rectitude can deteriorate under the action of drugs such as heroin. The junkie and the total abstainer, whatever they may suppose, do not occupy two ontologically separate realms of being or chemical motivation. We are all dependent on opioids to feel physically and emotionally well. Opioids bind to receptors in the ventral tegmental area of the mesolimbic dopamine system, the mind/brain's final common pathway for pleasure. Here are the cells that call the shots. If they're not happy, the whole organism will be miserable as well until they've got their psychochemical fix. For their cellular processes infiltrate the rest of the mind/brain. The junkie derives his opioid supply exogenously; while the release of endogenous opioids in the rest of us is triggered, and not always very reliably either, by stimuli such as food, sex, exercise and social interaction. We're all still seeking the same core states of psycho-chemical well-being under one description or other.
Hence even "psychologically" addictive drugs can lead to criminal and compulsive drug-seeking and -taking behaviour if supplies run out, even in formerly high-minded and saintly souls. This is because the over-intoxicated brain re-regulates its cellular receptors and reduces its production of the relevant pleasure-chemicals; this in turn increases the user's reliance on the exogenous route of administration. Strong-minded individuals who are sure they can safely indulge "recreationally" may misunderstand the psychochemical roots of their behaviour. The results of such ill-judgement can of course be disastrous. Fast-acting euphoriants such as crack cocaine can potentially corrupt even the most vehemently moralistic opponent of the hedonistic hypothesis. Getting hooked on heroin or crack may provide, indeed, a most illuminating empirical insight into the nature of human motivation; though there is a strong case to be argued that this is carrying the experimental method too far.
As a second response to the charge of vacuity, it is worth considering the following thought-experiment. It is (purely epistemically) possible that, keeping the laws of physics constant, the commonly supposed closed causal sufficiency of physical events meant that we found our bodies just behaving, but with none of the phenomenological concomitants of willed action which do in fact accompany much bodily behaviour. If such were the case, then many of the behavioural options one found one's body pursuing might be in one's mind's eye be far more unpleasant in their envisaged consequences than those of their notional alternatives. One wouldn't in this scenario be surprised at what was going on: bodily behaviour might as now be viewed as ultimately a mere product of the playing out of law-like physical interactions. It's just that in this setting any incidental phenomenology would just be along for the ride.
Given that we do experience a distinctive phenomenology of willed action, however, it doesn't seem consistent with our current understanding of the concept or the experience that one could consciously, phenomenologically act in one way in preference to another simply because one's image of the chosen action and its effects seemed less satisfying than the alternative(s). Even more dubiously coherent would be the notion of someone whose pleasure-pain spectrum was inverted and who acted in the conscious expectation of securing the outcome (s)he least desired. This is not to say that the practical effects of some people's actions don't frequently defeat their intentions. Certainly, too, a person may act in a superficially less satisfying way if (s)he has a more satisfying long-term goal in mind; this is the deceptively puritanical-sounding principle of deferred gratification. But this is a principle which tends only to corroborate rather than undermine the hypothesis at issue.
The point here is that psychological hedonism presupposes that we act as distinct from merely behave. Its distinctive focus is of course on how we do so from the pleasant, less unpleasant etc occurrent image or concept of the act's anticipated consequences. Yet from the outset there does seem to be an intimate, if often only implicit, conceptual connection between something remarkably like psychological hedonism and our notion(s) of action itself, and in particular of our acting on one perceived choice in preference to another.
Now even if, implausibly, it were deemed to be analytically true that all
action was motivated by desire for anticipated happiness etc, whether overtly
or under another description, this wouldn't prove that psychological hedonism
was correct. "Paradigm case"-style arguments in the manner of bad old ordinary-language
philosophy certainly can't settle the matter. Our terms, "analytic" or
otherwise, may simply fail to refer. One can't just define anything into
existence. What is definitionally stipulated to be analytically true in
one era may be treated as empirically, or even analytically, false in another.
So undoubtedly at least as useful as armchair psychology is an empirical
investigation of the links between the brain's reward mechanisms and the
dopaminergically innervated, pre-frontal motor cortical regions subserving
experientially voluntary action. Yet if it weren't for the deliverances
of introspection, there could be no notion that even one single creature
in the world ever consciously acted, as distinct from insentiently behaved,
in the first instance. Behaviourism is intellectually dead, and its grave
should be danced on as vigorously as possible.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
2.4 A Dirty Window On The Soul.
With this in mind, all I can say is that,
most disappointingly, I have never been able introspectively to catch myself
acting in one way rather than another when the thought of the rejected
alternative was unequivocally more satisfying, or less unsatisfying, than
the option chosen. Were this universally the case, then the biological
program would be instrumentally rational.
Could some variant of the pure pleasure-principle be true of anyone, let alone everyone? Now one can easily be in the grip of a false theory which colours one's sincere introspective reports. So there is no need to get hot under the collar if those reports are challenged; one may be genuinely mistaken. But if so, one is mistaken in very distinguished as well as very numerous company. Furthermore, there is no behavioural evidence to suggest that people whose introspective avowals corroborate the hedonistic hypothesis are more likely than anyone else to behave in ways one's culture deems selfish. The deep and subtle conceptual connection between the concept of action and the pleasure-principle may reflect an important feature of the world.
For if sceptical worries about the Problem of Other Minds may be set aside
here as idle, it is natural to assume that in one's core mental attributes
one is a representative member of the species. On the unverifiable but
cognitively indispensable principle of the uniformity of Nature, it would
seem that something so fundamental as the affective coloration of willed
action is unlikely to be sporadic, but biologically innate. Given the irreducibly
personal nature of subjective what-it's-like-ness, there is no way that
natural science can prove that certain causally efficacious decision-making
states actually have the differential hedonic tone one's introspection
suggests. But there is at least strong presumptive evidence that they do,
and that our genes have biased our hedonic encephalisation accordingly.
Indeed, it is the substantial overlap between sociobiology's technical
genetic definition of selfishness and less formally defined behavioural
and psychological usage which suggests, yet again, that one's defining
attributes are a reflection of one's status as a disposable genetic vehicle
rather than an autonomous moral agent.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
2.5 Let's Get Rational.
What is crucial in the context of the biological
program mapped out in this paper, however, is not to lose sight of the
central and relatively uncontroversial proposition about human motivation.
We spend a lot of time trying to make ourselves happy, whether "vicariously"
via our emotionally encephalised concepts of other people or from more
transparently self-regarding motives. Often, in fact, we are quite candidly
explicit about our motivation. "I want to be happy - without hurting anyone
on the way" is an astonishingly widespread secular sentiment. Instrumental,
means-ends analysis is extremely useful in general as a way of helping
us to pursue more rationally and intelligently all kinds of titular goals
that we seek only some of the time. So possible counter-examples of people
under weird self-destructive compulsions, of weakness of will, and problems
caused by the lack of any unitary self are at best a diversion from the
practical rationale of the biological strategy. Such anomalous phenomena
are certainly intellectually interesting complications for the hypothesis
of psychological hedonism if it is construed strictly as a universal generalisation
about human motivation. They don't challenge the large-scale instrumental
rationality of the intra-cranial strategy as the only way to get everyone
happy.
Thus the practical case for some variant of the biological program, stripped
down to its essentials, is as follows. Convergent evidence from realms
as disparate as introspection and neurobiology suggests that we all spend
(at least much of) our time acting to try and satisfy the insatiable hedonic
demands of the meso-limbic dopamine system, albeit under myriad nominal
descriptions which spring from the different ways our emotions get encephalised.
Everyone likes, if not only likes, the kind of experience which accompanies
electrochemical excitations in the mesolimbic dopamine system, even though
the idea of "electrochemical excitations in the mesolimbic dopamine system"
is not one which is normally accompanied by any great mesolimbic pleasure
(cf "the paradox of hedonism"). The earlier arguments of this paper have,
I hope, substantiated the claim that what may be dubbed "Peripheralism"
is hopelessly less effective than the direct biological route in achieving
what we're not always wittingly after. Environmental reformism of any conceivable
kind fails, and will invariably fail, to overturn the hedonic treadmill.
We've tried it for ages, and it doesn't work. Given our (sometimes) nominally
disguised purposes, and given that irrationalism is not a live option,
the only countervailing reasons against pursuing the biological program's
rational strategic course of action will be moral considerations. So are
there any countervailing moral reasons why we shouldn't do what instrumental
rationality otherwise dictates? Or instead are their cogent moral as well
as practical reasons for adopting the all-out biological panacea? Is universal
happiness a bad thing?
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
2.6 The Morality of Happiness.
I suppose it requires an effort of the imagination
on my part to conceive how a Universe in which all humans and non-humans
alike led richly fulfilled and joyful lives could be a morally worse place
than where we are now. If we were to discover an alien civilisation of
ecstatics, would we try to introduce a bit of suffering into their lives
to stiffen their moral fibre? I fear the critic, however, is likely to
find this remark of only autobiographical significance. The question, (s)he
would presumably reply, is where do we go from here, not how would we go
from there. And at this point there might seem a danger that this paper
will run into an all-consuming quagmire of subjectivism. For whatever other
functions they may perform, the hard-headed scientific rationalist will
argue, value-judgements don't have propositional content and thus aren't
truth-evaluable. The universe may contain some extraordinary things, but
objective values aren't among them. After all, what in the world could
make such judgements true?
In the remainder of this section, the course of the argument runs as follows.
I shall first define and set out an ethical negative utilitarian case for
abolishing all forms of aversive experience. It will be argued that only
the apparently extreme overkill of the biological hedonist program can
realistically achieve this. Hence the practical consequences here of the
negative-utilitarian ethic will not significantly differ from standard
utilitarianism in which maximising pleasure is accorded equal moral worth
with minimising pain: both variants of the doctrine mandate implementing
something akin to the program advocated just as soon as it becomes biotechnically
feasible. The intimate links between both moral and non-moral value and
happiness (construed here in the sense of generically pleasant experience),
and between "disvalue" and misery, are noted. It will be argued thatof
the mass-production of happiness will correlate with the production of
actions and experiences empirically found valuable too. Hence the biological
program will yield results which its beneficiaries will find vastly more
valuable than the neurochemical status quo. Will they be right, or ultimately
is this mere opinion? In misguided support of the latter, the orthodox
physicalist and neo-Darwinian case against the objectivity of judgements
of value will then be spelt out. This value-fictionalism will be countered
by a form of value-naturalism. It is argued that value, no less than, say,
redness, is an intrinsic feature of the world. It is so in virtue of being
a unique quality of experience which is itself a spatio-temporally located
and causally efficacious property of the natural world. Value judgements,
it will be contended, are in fact truth-evaluable because they truly or
falsely report the presence or absence of this property of experience -
irrespective of their ostensible objects of reference. Several apparently
devastating objections to this view are stated, not least charges of ignoring
the fact that moral values may conflict, and of equivocation. These objections
are then rebutted.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
2.7 Why Be Negative?
But why negative utilitarianism?
Ethical negative-utilitarianism is a value system which challenges the moral symmetry of pleasure and pain. It doesn't question the value of increasing the happiness of the already happy. Yet it attaches value in a distinctively moral sense of the term only to actions which tend to minimise or eliminate suffering. It is counter-intuitive, not least insofar as the doctrine entails that from a purely ethical perspective it wouldn't matter if nothing at all had existed or everything ceased to exist. No inherent moral value is attached to pleasure or pleasant states. Indeed, if the option were humanly available, the logic of the position morally obligates bringing the world to an end were this the only way to eliminate the suffering endemic to it.
Following through the logical implications of this seemingly bizarre and perverse perspective is clearly not for the faint-hearted. Negative utilitarianism nonetheless stems, not from sublimated self-hatred or a nihilistic death-wish, but from a deep sense of compassion at the unimaginable scale and dreadful intensity of suffering in the world. No amount of happiness enjoyed by some organisms can notionally justify the indescribable horrors of Auschwitz. [And the Universal Schrodinger Equation (or whatever) entails them both. Its solutions don't allow one without the other, albeit in disparate bits of space-time/Hilbert space.] Nor can the fun and games outweigh the sporadic frightfulness of pain and despair that occurs every second of every day. For there's nothing inherently wrong with non-sentience or [infelicitously] non-existence; whereas there is something frightfully and self-intimatingly wrong with suffering. This manifesto was written, and will typically be read, in a relatively "euthymic" condition. One doesn't feel too bad. So it isn't difficult to dissociate one's feelings from a mere printed litany of frightfulness. It's easy to convince oneself that things can't really be that terrible, that the horror I allude to is being overblown, that what is going on elsewhere in space-time is somehow less real than the here-and-now, or that the good in the world somehow offsets the bad. Yet however vividly one thinks one can imagine what agony, torture or suicidal despair must be like, the reality is inconceivably worse. The force of "inconceivably" is itself largely inconceivable here. Blurry images of Orwell's "Room 101" can barely even hint at what I'm talking about. Even if one's ancestral namesakes [aka "younger self"] underwent great pain, then the state-dependence of memories means that much of pain's sheer dreadfulness is semantically, cognitively and emotionally inaccessible in the here-and-now. So this manifesto's rhapsodies on the incredible joys that do indeed lie ahead are tend to belie its underlying seriousness of purpose. For the biological strategy is propounded here in deadly moral earnest.
Negative-utilitarianism is only one particular denomination of a broad church to which the reader may well in any case not subscribe. Fortunately, the program can be defended on grounds that utilitarians of all stripes can agree on. So a defence will be mounted against critics of the theory and application of an utilitarian ethic in general. For in practice the most potent and effective means of curing unpleasantness is to ensure that a defining aspect of future states of mind is their permeation with the molecular chemistry of ecstasy: both genetically precoded and pharmacologically fine-tuned. Orthodox utilitarians will doubtless find the cornucopian abundance of bliss this strategy delivers is itself an extra source of moral value. Future generations of native ecstatics are unlikely to disagree.
Of course, there's only any need for morality if there is anything wrong
with the world. If there isn't, and suffering becomes biologically impossible,
then morality - in any sense we understand it - becomes redundant too.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
2.8 The Moral Panacea.
A built-in biological warranty of happiness
undercuts three standard critiques of utilitarianism. First, the utilitarian
ethic is often contrasted with agent-centred moralities and charged with
making impossibly onerous demands on people. According to the impersonal
felicific calculus, one should, for instance, give away perhaps 95% of
one's money to feed the starving in the Third World. Most people just aren't
capable of such generosity to anonymous strangers: our genes wouldn't let
us. Thus utilitarianism may be a useful sovereign principle for legislators
but, it is claimed, not much use as a personal moral code.
The effect of the biological program is to transcend such practical difficulties. There will come a time when saintly altruism can always be fun, albeit largely superfluous. Our genes can make it wretchedly difficult in the meanwhile, and much more necessary.
Second, utilitarianism seems to justify, on occasion, various types of behaviour e.g. lying, murder or even torture, that in most agent-relative moralities would be reckoned wrong or even wicked, if the net result is greater all-round well-being. Many critics have argued that this flexibility would, on balance, lead to a worse society. They have then gone on to develop their critiques of the principle on covertly utilitarian grounds of varying subtlety and sophistication.
The biological program sweeps these difficulties aside too. Its effect is to eliminate odious evolutionary hangovers such as murder and torture altogether. Lies, too, will become simply pointless.
Third, utilitarianism seems to demand, in effect, the ceaseless use of hand-held felicific super-computers to calculate the consequences of each of one's actions. This might prove quite exhausting. Worse still, the distant long-term effects of what one does might seem incalculable; possibly, on the likely assumption chaos theory applies to human affairs, even incalculable in principle. So, ultimately, there can be no way of knowing at the relevant time whether a course of action is right or wrong on such a strict consequentialist ethic. One is reminded of an observation of Mao Tse-tung who, when asked for his opinion on whether the French Revolution had been a good thing, said that he thought it was too early to tell.
The biological program dispels such worries altogether. If it is carried
through systematically, human action need never cause suffering again.
The long-term effects of genetic engineering will predictably be the abolition
of this category of experience.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
2.9 The Significance Of An Empirical Correlation.
Now the effect of this sort of genetic enhancement
and pharmacotherapy will be states of mind that are not merely overwhelmingly
more pleasurable than anything physiologically conceivable before. Empirically,
subjects will apprehend such states as self-evidently more valuable as
well, again by a vast margin. At humanity's current stage of development,
countless actions and states of mind, and not infrequently life itself,
are judged to be, truth-evaluably or otherwise, worthless and futile. After
the post-Darwinian transition occurs, then every single state of consciousness
in the world may be conceived as self-intimatingly valuable by its very
nature. Futuristic biotechnology of a sophistication we can today only
gesture at should enable the prolific mass-manufacture of states all apprehended
as intensely valuable by their subjects. So in phenomenological terms,
if no other, the quantity and quality of valued experience will skyrocket
along with its biological substrates. Every moment of the day will be far
better than the best sex anyone's ever had anywhere with anyone to date;
and a lot more productive.
Again, in an empirical sense at least, there is an extremely large overlap between actions and experiences that are found valuable and those found generically pleasant; and of those found pleasurable but not valuable, most are accounted as such because they are reckoned to endanger or diminish the likelihood of future pleasurable experience, whether in oneself or as imagined in others. All kinds of caveats, refinements and exceptions spring to mind at such a pronouncement. Yet in a secular age, this generalisation has extraordinarily wide scope. It would be wider still if the different intentional guises in which such judgements may be cloaked are included too. Some utilitarians, notoriously, have gone on to identify value with happiness. This is untenably simplistic. Too many plausible counter-examples present themselves for such a claim to be defended here. A far more modest position is all our purposes require. If an experience, either imagined vicariously as notionally undergone by others or unequivocally personal by self-ascription, is found to induce feelings of happiness or satisfaction, or reduce feelings of unhappiness or dissatisfaction, then it will be apprehended by its subject as valuable in the absence of any countervailing reasons. Less long-windedly, happiness is found valuable as the default condition.
Now this might serve as the cue for a heavy-duty treatment of the relationship
between value and pleasure. All that's needed for the argument to follow,
however, is to note that the biological program will generate, both quantitatively
and qualitatively, immensely more experiences found at once pleasurable
and valuable than those characteristic of the neurochemical status quo.
The program's therapeutic strategy will eliminate a whole host of states
that even today are thought worthless or obnoxious. With time, the correlation
between states found valuable and states found pleasurable should get ever
closer to 1. So if, first, value judgements are also truth-evaluable, and
if, second, subjects were normally capable of reliably apprehending their
truth, then the biological program would indeed prove ethically mandatory.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
2.10 A Tough-Minded Scientist Replies.
Yet so what? The contemporary critic will
not be impressed. Just as not everything that is more desired is more desirable,
surely not everything that is more valued is thereby more valuable. Only
if the valued were indeed also valuable would the biological program be
vindicated in an ethical sense. It can't be, because its defence attempts
to derive, or somehow smuggle in, an "ought" from an "is", which is logically
impossible. To argue otherwise is to commit the naturalistic fallacy. For
is value supposed to be some property of the natural world over and above
the ontology sanctioned by physics?
Physical science, the scientific rationalist may freely go on to admit, has not yet definitively settled on the ultimate ontological furniture of the universe. There is plenty of theoretical and experimental work to be done investigating whether its ontological primitives are particles, fields, probability waves, loops, superstrings or whatever. The relationships between these primitives still tantalisingly awaits a complete and unified mathematical description as well. But whatever really exists e.g. macroscopic objects, itself supervenes on mind-independent configurations of these ontologically basic primitive entities, events or properties. Values, on the other hand, are merely mind-dependent subjective fictions. We don't read them off the world, but project them on to it.
The scientistic hatchet-job on the status of objective values is often
supplemented with a neo-Darwinian account of their genesis. If one claims
that something is illusory, then one wants to explain how and why the illusion
occurs. Pro-Darwinian polemicists oblige. What might seem to be eternal
moral verities are ritually unmasked by their debunkers as mere instruments
of the genes. People's devoutly-held personal convictions, we learn, are
just another means by which competing alliances of information-bearing
self-replicators - genes - manipulate their throwaway vehicles at one remove
to promote their own inclusive fitness. Admittedly, genetic predisposition
does not equate with genetic determinism. Sociobiologists, evolutionary
ethicists and their ilk aren't claiming that our genes directly code, rather
than bias, the development of each idiosyncratic set of cultural values.
Yet independently-arising cross-cultural universals e.g. religious and
secular incest-taboos, can nonetheless best distally be explained by positing
selective pressures which act over many generations to shape our moral
fetishes and phobias. We would dearly love to believe that our subjective
values are somehow objectively underwritten by the nature of the world,
the scientific rationalist concludes, generally in tones which suggest
he bears their absence with remarkable fortitude; but they are epistemically
unserious verbiage. To believe otherwise is to fall victim to wishful thinking
or the toxic mind-rot of New Age mysticism.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
2.11 The Selection of Mysterious Reds.
I shall now defend a version of value-naturalism,
and consequently the objective ethical rationale of the biological program,
against this indictment. Is talk of objective values just claptrap? For
it is ironic that at a time when the scientifically-informed current of
analytic philosophy is witnessing an embarrassed scramble to "naturalise"
everything from epistemology to consciousness, any similar bid to legitimate
value should still widely be held to commit a logical fallacy. So it will
now be shown how, and in what sense, moral judgements can and can't have
truth-conditions; and how the existence of objective values could be consistent
with the apparently austere ontology of physical science. An analogy is
drawn with phenomenal colour. It is argued that, appearances to the contrary,
moral judgements in fact report, truly or falsely, a distinctive quality
common to the experience of those who avow them. What such judgements express
is mind-dependent, and on an identity theory thereby brain-dependent; and
thereby value is as much a natural, intrinsic and objective feature of
the world as phenomenal redness. The proposition that it is otherwise is
unnaturalistic, the legacy of a dualistic perspective which sees mind and
its experiential attributes as distinct from the physical world rather
than as objectively existing features of it. We don't simply "project"
our values onto the world. For we are literally bits of the world itself.
Four objections, each on their own apparently decisive, are levelled against
this sort of value-naturalist position.
So to begin a value-naturalist defence, it is worth drawing an analogy with, say, redness. On a mind-brain identity theory, redness is a phenomenological property intrinsic to certain patterns of neuronal firing. The presence of light of a particular frequency impinging on the retina, or indeed of any light at all, is neither a necessary nor a sufficient condition for the production of red experience in a subject. When dreaming, for instance, one can inwardly see or instantiate red phenomena. Conversely, when one is awake and in darkness, then a sufficient condition of one's having, say, a brief punctate red experience in front of one's body-image is that the relevant cortical area is electrically stimulated.
On the assumption that one is wholly a part of the natural world, then phenomenal redness, too, is one of the properties of the world. It is predicated of, and appears to inhere in, many macroscopic objects. Yet it is an intrinsic property of certain mind/brain states, and is not some relational property involving the interaction of light from intrinsically colourless objects and the mind/brain. The presence or absence of red phenomenal experience can be truly or falsely reported by the subject, whether the subject believes it is a property intrinsic to mind-independent physical objects or otherwise.
Given the above, it is worth noting the sense in which redness can, and
more importantly can't, be explained within the current conceptual framework
of the natural sciences. Natural selection has stumbled upon psychophysical
phenomenal colour states. These states are not inherently representational.
But natural selection has harnessed them so they now tend, in the awake
brain, to track certain causally co-varying patterns in the organism's
environment. The capacity to recognise these patterns (simplistically,
differential electromagnetic reflectancies of macroscopic objects) bears
on the differential reproductive success of the genetic vehicles in which
phenomenal colours are periodically instantiated. This explains why such
states have been selected. It doesn't explain their intrinsic phenomenal
nature. So natural selection doesn't in any but a shallow sense explain
states such as redness (or, it will be argued, value). It explains why
some such states have been selected rather than others. It doesn't explain
why any kind of experience has the phenomenal properties it does. Nor does
it explain why experience exists at all. If telepathy had existed, evolutionary
psychologists would doubtless offer excellent explanations and mathematical
models of why telepaths had been selected over non-telepaths. Telepathy,
we would tub-thumpingly be told, could thus be explained "naturalistically",
not as some divine gift of God. Yet the phenomenon itself would still be
utterly mysterious.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
2.12 The Formal Successes Of Scientific Triumphalism.
Physics and, derivatively, the rest of the
physical sciences can in principle provide a complete account of the natural
universe. It is (potentially) complete only in the sense that the mathematical
formalism of quantum mechanics is correct and isomorphic to the world.
The equations themselves are topic-neutral. The intrinsic nature of the
stuff they describe, what "breathes fire into the equations and makes there
a world for us to describe" is, as even Hawking concedes, unknown, and
perhaps unknowable. What can be known, however, since one is oneself a
tiny fragment of the "fire in the equations", is that the experience of
phenomenal redness exists as a matter objective fact. This is so even though
a (mathematically) complete physics on its own has nothing to say about
it.
This should be stressed because in conceptualising the contents of the world, it is tempting to defer, not merely to the unreasonable effectiveness of the equations, but also to one's ill-defined notions of the basic physical stuff those equations describe. And these notions don't include e.g. redness, or tickles, or happiness, or moral values. But, crucially here, the physicists' potential candidates for the status of brute ontological primitives e.g. superstrings or fields etc., are defined, ultimately, in purely mathematical terms. So if particular phenomenal colours, say, were to be identified with the particular numerical values of a set of occipito-temporal cortical fields, this is in no way inconsistent with the physical formalism. Redness would in this case be just one spark of the "fire in the equations". Likewise, if one identifies particular phenomenologically valuable states with a finite set of numerical values of intra-cranial fields, this is likewise consistent with the mathematical formalism. For they too are part of the fire in the equations which makes there a world for us to describe.
Unfortunately, it is all too easy to muddy the ontological issue here by
confusing the two senses of the word "subjective". It is the case, objectively,
that the world contains subjective, experiential states such as redness
with its unique, nameable, but ultimately ineffable what-it's-like-ness.
This property may be identified with complicated, occipito-temporal cortical
patterns of cortical fields. Redness is a distinctive mind-dependent property.
It lacks any mind-independent existence, since neither electromagnetic
radiation, molecules nor their macroscopic object patterns are red. This
doesn't challenge its objective existence. When one experiences, or is
presented with, or instantiates, redness, one can apprehend what colour
it is and report the experience, sincerely or otherwise. This judgement
has truth-conditions. Since red is mind-dependent it is also, on any mind-brain
identity theory, brain-dependent. It is as such an objective property of
the physical world. So what judgements of redness express is both mind-dependent
and objectively true (or, if one's avowals are insincere, false).
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
2.13 The Naturalisation of Value.
Now moral value itself will be examined. It
is going to be suggested that value, and conversely disvalue, are distinctive
features literally inherent in the world no less than phenomenal redness;
and thus there can be objective, truth-evaluable judgements of value. This
property is mind-dependent, hence brain-dependent, hence a natural and
objective property of the world. In consequence, the states of mind of
our ecstatic descendants are inherently more valuable by their very nature
than the relatively worthless psychiatric slumlands of our own era.
Of the finite, potential 101 000 000's of interestingly different types of conscious state of the human mind/brain, some are subjectively apprehended as experientially valuable and some aren't. Some states seem essentially neutral; some are merely pleasurable but not valued; some are found complex and ambivalent; some involve the mere parroting of received wisdom in the absence of the relevant experience; and the fuzzy boundaries of what the concept of finding something experientially valuable entails are an added complication too. Some valuable qualities strike one as intrinsic to the very nature of (one's emotionally encephalised virtual simulation of) the mind-independent world. Some seem to be local to one's body-image. Yet the presence or absence of any particular mind/brain-independent state of affairs is in principle neither necessary nor sufficient for the experientially valuable states to occur; whereas a necessary and sufficient condition for those experiences is the occurrence of the relevant pattern of neuronal firings.
Once proto-utopian neuroscience can identify the biomolecular substrates of experiential value, or redness, or pleasure etc, it will be feasible to mass-manufacture redness, pleasure or value. Value can be biologically synthesised in extant organisms or in mind/brains-in-vats. [Hence the derisive tag earlier of "biological program for Cosmic Value-Maximisation".] Futuristic vats could contain colours and values in virtue of containing brains. This sounds odd; but no category-mistake is involved.
So analogously to redness, then, value should be construed as a property
of a delimited class of mind/brain states. In future it can be both quantified
and synthesised. Certain forms of experience are indeed often said to be
unquantifiable: happiness is the most commonly cited example. But if particular
types of chemical (or perhaps, ultimately, relativistic quantum fields,
or modes of vibration of 10-dimensional heterotic superstrings etc) embedded
in the relevant neural state, are either identified with, or found to be
invariantly positively correlated with, phenomenologically valuable states,
then scaling up or down the number and size of the relevant states by the
relevant number and disposition of molecules increases or decreases the
level of happiness, redness, value etc in the world accordingly. Problems
of vague concepts with fuzzy boundaries, and of ill-defined criteria of
usage, complicate but do not change the issue. In an ideal taxonomy of
the mind/brain, experiential states would be as quantifiable, and their
exact texture as mathematically precisely defined, as any other feature
of the natural universe. The notion that what-it's-like-ness can be described
by a set of equations is indisputably counter-intuitive; but this is what
any scientific mind/brain identity-theory entails. And given such a theory,
the biological program can vastly increase the amount of both happiness
and naturalised value in the world.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
2.14 Four Deadly Objections?
Now for four potentially devastating objections
that can be levelled at the position sketched above.
First, when people express value-judgements, they frequently refer to states of the world. They're not alluding to some distinctive quality of their own experience. They may indeed frequently project aspects of their experience onto states of the world. Yet it is the world they are referring to, not their own phenomenology.
Second, surely values can conflict. They are sometimes violently contested. We even go to war over them. If two putatively truth-evaluable judgements of value are mutually contradictory, they can't both be objectively true; or perhaps they don't, and can't, have truth-conditions at all.
Third, by taking value to be an intrinsic phenomenological attribute of certain mental states, the value-naturalist position apparently makes some singularly obnoxious prejudices morally valuable, even immensely so. After all, Hitler found persecuting Jews extremely morally valuable. Given that, by every indication, Hitler was sincere in reporting at least this aspect of his mental states, albeit under another description, then from the value-naturalist perspective persecuting Jews would have to count as valuable: not as valuable as the exalted states alluded to in this paper, admittedly, but morally worthwhile nonetheless. This is surely a pretty conclusive reductio of the position. In any case, the above example exposes the argument's internal inconsistency. Hitler's value-judgements contradicted those of his victims. Therefore it is logically impossible for them both to be right.
Fourth, does not the value-naturalist case rest on an illicit equivocation? Not everything that is desired is desirable, a slide from the factual to the ethical. Likewise, surely not everything that is valued is valuable? Even if it were objectively the case that value-judgements obliquely reported, truly or falsely, a distinctive experiential state or family of states, this wouldn't mean that such types of state actually ought to be valued, or that one ought to strive for their maximisation.
The reply given here to these seemingly knock-down rejoinders to the value-naturalist
is highly counter-intuitive. For it depends for its key premiss on what
might appear to be a completely different issue altogether, the nature
of what we optimistically call perception; and in particular the falsity
of any sort of direct realism. The answer to be given is arguably consistent
with several non-direct realist theories other than the one set out below;
but the account, and the heuristic fable it contains, is designed to highlight
as starkly as possible the falsity of a presupposition common to at least
the first three charges above. The position defended here as a basis for
the argument to follow is a radical selectionist account of perceptual
experience. It contends that the difference between "dreaming" and "being
awake" lies essentially in the mode by which states intrinsic to the mind/brain
are selected. The most that the extra-neural environment can ever do is
partially select which of a finite menu of mind/brain/virtual world states
is instantiated at a given moment. Subjects can never, directly, do more
than apprehend their own mind/brain/virtual-world states. The values they
appear to find in the mind-independent world are instead intrinsic features
of particular states of their own brains. And insofar as future ecstatics
are capable of truly reporting this quality of experience, their states
are objectively more valuable than anything existing today. So the world
really will get better and better.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
2.15 Alone Amongst The Zombies.
These rather dogmatic and elliptical pronouncements
may first be illustrated by use of the following case study.
There is a rare sleep disorder in which the victims lack the muscular atony which, ordinarily, functionally decouples the bodily musculature from a dreaming brain. This decoupling is in the normal way highly adaptive. For it stops the rest of us from unwittingly acting out our dreams. In the absence of a functional decoupling of the musculature, all manner of dream-scenarios will be acted out. In such circumstances the external vocalisations and other forms of bodily behaviour of the dreamer are uncorrelated, except by chance, with the rest of the world outside the mind/brain.
Within the dreamer's virtual world, however, nothing will seem amiss. The meaning and reference of terms used by the central body-image are grounded purely internally in its pseudo-perceptually apprehended environment. Inside the neural dreamworld, a conscious, unwittingly private language of thought masquerades as public speech. The dreamer's body-image uses it to converse with the behaviourally intelligent homunculi his visual cortex intermittently activates. These noisily animated zombies, and other ostensibly perceptual experiences of macroscopic objects in a macroscopic world, are purely autobiographical. The whole virtual world flickers in and out of existence as its instantiator passes in and out of dreamless sleep. For it is not just the dreamer's non-occurrent beliefs and desires which are dispositional, but the macroscopic dreamworld itself. Its episodes are nonetheless readily reactivated. This is because its features lie latently encoded in the connection and activation weights of the dreamer's brain. The difference between us and a victim of this sleep disorder is that his extra-neural body acts out, obliviously, the actions performed by his body-image internal to the dream; whereas when we are asleep our bodies are effectively paralysed.
Now, counterfactually and for heuristic purposes, imagine a possible world in which this sleep disorder is both chronic and ubiquitous. Dreamers never "wake up". Nor do they have any notion of what such a familiar if ill-understood expression might mean. Natural selection goes to work over millions of years. It differentially favours the genotypes of organisms whose dreamworlds, initially just by chance, serve as though they were akin to quasi-real-time simulations of certain patterns in the extra-neural world. For genetically selfish reasons, each differentially selected genotype spawns an egocentric virtual world. It is a virtual world centred physically and affectively around one focal body-image. More proximate selection of dreamworld events comes into play due to a bombardment of patterned sequences of electro-chemical impulses from various afferent proto-nerves. These extend to what serve to become peripheral transducers in the organism's bodily surfaces. Over the generations, the fitness-enhancing correlations between the behaviour the extra-neural body unwittingly acts out and macro-patterns in its environment tend to get tighter and tighter.
With the passage of time, many dreamworlds quite regularly become, so to
speak, thoroughly undreamlike. Normal infant dream-worlders will learn,
over several years, pseudo-public criteria for language use from their
virtual mothers. A maturing dreamer may discover that his body-image's
surroundings show a good deal of coherence, law-like regularity and even
predictability. He may discover that his body(-image) can intelligently
manipulate and re-engineer, within sharply constrained limits, aspects
of the (neural dream-)world beyond itself. Obliquely and obliviously, dreamworlds
will tend in some degree mutually to select each other's contents. With
time, the unwitting behavioural by-products of purposeful actions internal
to billions of dreamworlds spin off an ever more elaborate material culture.
The collective result of these by-products is that the eternal sleepers'
host bodies act out the construction of everything from skyscrapers to
computer networks, particle-accelerators to jumbo jets. The resultant artefacts
enjoy a dreamworld-independent existence. They themselves serve thereafter
partially to select what kinds of dreamworld are neurally activated.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
2.16 The Perils of Idle Scepticism.
Should an overly-lucid dreamer ever doubt
the ontological integrity of his particular virtual world, the consequences
may be grave. Dreamworlds can be refractory and inhospitable places. His
virtual body-image may be mauled by virtual lions or, in a later era, knocked
down by a virtual bus. Thanks to millions of years of selective pressure,
such agonies correlate highly with parallel, mind-independent events befalling
the organism whose skull encloses the dreamworld brain. So any genes notionally
predisposing to such idle philosophers' fancies tend not to be passed on
to the bodily vehicles of potential baby-dreamworlds. Instead, each dreamer
strives to re-order his emotionally encephalised world so that its unsuspectedly
mind-dependent states more nearly match his desires.
Some dreamworlds are chaotic and schizoid; some are seemingly well-ordered
and amenable to quasi-scientific investigation; some are happy and suffused
with spirituality and magic; and some are violent and nightmarish. None
of these gargantuan psychochemical extravaganzas is inherently about anything
external to itself on the other side of its skull. Yet evolution has differentially
selected genes which predispose to the self-assembly of a very particular
range of phenotypical dreamworlds. These are the world-phenotypes which
serve as effective vehicles for the propagation of more copies of the genes
that made them. One of the properties of a successful vehicle is that periodically
some of its patterns causally co-vary, albeit on a highly selective basis,
with other patterns beyond itself.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
2. 17 The Price Of Inner Demons.
How is this relevant to a value-naturalist
defence of an objective warrant for the biological program? The fable's
significance may be illustrated by envisaging a counterpart to Hitler,
say, in the dreamworld scenario. In his dark and sinister virtual world,
his body-image fights against terrible inner demons/neuronal firings. He
spends his whole life pitted in a struggle to exorcise once-and-for-all
their malevolent and conspiratorial presence. The evil occipito-temporal
homunculi lurking beyond his somato-sensory body-image are of course mindless
phantoms. But their hostile intent appears frighteningly obvious to their
host. Tragically, Hitler's dreamworld brain is fully coupled to the bodily
musculature of the organism which houses such nightmarish neurochemical
patterns. There is no muscular atony to prevent the microcosmic horror
story from being acted out in the mind-independent macrocosm by the extra-neural
body. Natural selection has ensured that many types of event in his dreamworld
causally co-vary, albeit in a grotesquely selective manner, with the wider
world, its organisms and the dreamworlds they host. In consequence, over
fifty million people die in a brutal war.
Now this fable is all very well as a thought-experiment, it may be said. Even in our own world, there are rare and tragic cases of people who blamelessly and unwittingly kill their partner while asleep, whether during "night-terrors" or in the course of an exceedingly violent dream. But the real Hitler wasn't asleep. He was fully awake and acted quite deliberately in full knowledge of what he was doing. He perceived real, flesh-and-blood, sentient people. They were wholly innocent of the monstrous crimes he imputed to them.
And herein lies the crux. If real-world Hitler did directly apprehend or perceive his victims, or alternatively if certain neurochemical events in his mind/brain/virtual-world were, somehow, inherently about Jewish people in the world outside, then the argument shortly to be presented is false. If, on the other hand, Hitler was wrestling with horribly emotionally encephalised inner demons, apparitions of his own (involuntary) creation whose foul behaviour really did blight his early virtual world, then his behaviour in trying to banish such sources of negative value amounted to an epistemic rather than evaluative failure. Likewise today, in billions of other egocentric virtual worlds, desperate and often ineffectual attempts are being made by each genetic host's central body-image to exorcise all kinds of obnoxious phenomena. Unfortunately, in the absence of the biological program and the presence of naive realism, the net results are frequently tragic.
In the case of Hitler, profound sources of objective experiential "disvalue"
did indeed neurochemically transmit and present themselves to the functional
modules mediating his sense of self and neural body-image. It wasn't the
case that he somehow "projected" such experience onto his virtual world;
instead that quality of experience was intrinsic to it. Natural selection
ensured that Hitler, in common with all but a few philosophically and scientifically-minded
humans, was implicitly a naive realist about a perceptual world. So when
he apprehended great evil, a quality of experience located in what he couldn't
know was only his emotionally malencephalised virtual world, he tried to
destroy it in the only manner he knew how. By his lights, he was trying
to make the mind-independent world a better place. Had he been a brain-in-a-vat,
he might temporarily have succeeded. Tragically, he wasn't; and a mere
epistemological error turned into a moral catastrophe.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
2.18 Can We All Be Really Good?
Now if the human predicament were akin to
that of a dreamworlder, a very big and controversial "if" admittedly, then
the following answers may be given to the four objections to value-naturalism
levelled earlier.
First, yes, people certainly believe many of their value-judgements refer to the world and its properties rather than to some distinctive quality of their own experience. But both the philosophy of perception and quantum mechanics suggest that what a person treats as the mind-independent world - and to whose properties he linguistically refers - are toy, data-driven simulations his mind-brain is running. If so, then he is referring in a direct way only to aspects of his own neural experience in another guise. What his value-judgements express is still an objective property of the natural world. But it is mind-dependent. Experiences found valuable, whether by brains-in skulls or futuristic brains-in-vats, have a distinctive, nameable, but ineffable what-it's-like-ness about which physical science has nothing to say.
Second, people's value-judgements can mutually contradict each other only if they succeed in referring to the same thing. Hitler's internally-issued value-judgements couldn't really contradict those of his extra-neural body's inadvertent victims. Those same judgements accurately reflected the character of the emotionally encephalised bestiary of monsters that populated his mind/brain; and against whose machinations he fought, at terrible cost.
Third, what is morally wrong on a consequentialist ethic is the effect of the unwitting behavioural spin-offs of Hitler's attempts to extinguish his inner foes. He wasn't mistaken to find certain phenomena obnoxious, sources of profound objective "disvalue". Mein Kampf is testimony to their horrible phenomenology. He just mislocated their distinctive properties and origin as external to his composite self. The effects were of course catastrophic.
Now to what extent the dreamworld fable above does capture an aspect of
the human predicament is, to say the least, controversial. Aside from certain
details included for reasons of expository convenience, I would argue that
the account is empirically indistinguishable, at least, from more familiar
approaches to perception. To explore in any depth, however, the perceptual
and semantic minefields into which the question leads, not to mention the
paradoxes of self-reference it might seem to entail, would take us too
far afield. The account does nonetheless offer one programmatic way to
naturalise value, albeit at a price that may be considered too high for
comfort.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
2.19 Equivocal Values.
The fourth charge was one of equivocation.
The valued is being confused with the valuable. Even if it is granted,
the charge continues, that value-judgements are true or false reports of
a distinctive type of neurophenomenological state, that state itself is,
as the term suggests, just that: truth-valuelessly phenomenological. Finding
an experience morally good or bad in such a sense doesn't carry any logical
implication that one should objectively do anything about it. Hence, whatever
its instrumental merits, the claim that the biological program advocated
here is ethically mandatory is untenable if construed as expressing an
objective truth. Yes, executing the biological blueprint would vastly increase
the number and intensity of states found phenomenologically valuable; and
yes, it would abolish altogether states that aren't. But value-judgements,
and the qualities of experience they describe, are like tickles. They exist,
and they may make you want to do something about them. Yet they don't refer
to anything beyond themselves and they don't logically mandate any course
of action.
I would argue that properly understood there is no equivocation. We happen to live in a universe whose ontology includes literally valuable experiences in the same way as it contains literally painful experiences, visual and auditory experiences, feelings of irritation or obligation or indignation, and a teeming profusion of other forms of what-it's-like-ness most of which remain so far completely nameless. So the universe really does contain phenomena that are, literally and intrinsically, valuable. The utilitarian ethic championed here, and the biological program it instrumentally dictates, leads ultimately to the amount of intrinsic value as well as happiness in the universe being maximised; and all sources of negative value extinguished.
It will then no doubt be asked, perhaps somewhat impatiently as well as sceptically: but is an experience found really valuable really valuable? Why couldn't it just seem to be valuable? Yet one wouldn't, and couldn't, sensibly ask if an experience found really painful was really painful. One can apparently imagine a universe without values, in the same way as one can apparently imagine one without pains or pleasures or redness. But for reasons we admittedly don't understand, we don't live in that sort of Universe. We live in a Universe where some things intrinsically matter and have positive or negative value. If our image of a respectable physicalist ontology can't cope with the objective fact such modes of what-it's-like-ness exist, then we are misinterpreting what the formal mathematical description of the world is telling us.
Now perhaps a value-nihilist can sincerely deny having any such quality of experience. The nihilist can ask why should (s)he value value, whatever that might be. Yet this scepticism doesn't impugn the existence of value, any more than the status of pain is compromised by rare cases of people congenitally insensitive to it. The relegation of either kind of experience to some kind of ontological demi-monde is unwarranted and should be rejected.
This objectivity doesn't entail that valuable experiences can have, as
distinct from simulate, a type of mind-transcendent, truth-evaluable "propositional
content" over and above their intrinsic phenomenology which somehow manages
to alight on properties of the mind-independent world. But then there are
desperately hard problems in the context of a naturalistic world-picture
of explaining how any other spatio-temporal electrochemical event or episode
of experience, whether deemed cognitive or otherwise, could literally have
abstract propositional content either. Worlds where they don't can apparently
be empirically indistinguishable from ours - and a lot less ontologically
fishy. A lot of the time, one just has to cross one's fingers, whistle
in the dark, mix one's metaphors, and try and pretend otherwise.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
2.20 Good Vibrations: The Value Of String.
Russell once observed that "Ethical metaphysics
is fundamentally an attempt, however disguised, to give legislative force
to our own wishes." Perhaps he is right. Mixing up prediction and prescription
is usually a recipe for confusion. Attempts to ground the post-Darwinian
project - or any other moral enterprise - in something more exalted than
the pleasure-pain principle may simply be spinning a fantasy world of self-deception.
Perhaps talk of the moral goodness of eradicating suffering - or any other
kind of moral discourse - is merely idle opinion: just a lot of high-falutin
noise amid the digital babel of cyberspace.
The traditional-minded scientific rationalist, for one, will surely be unmoved. It will be claimed that the world's [allegedly inherently] valuable and valueless experiences as touted in this chapter are "really" "just" something else: patterns of neuronal firings, the differential modes of vibration of superstrings (or whatever) with which they are posited to be physically identical. Yet this is sophistry. The reductionist argument can be turned on its head. Presumably certain modes of vibration of superstrings etc are "really" "just" valuable experiences. This isn't very illuminating. Whether, why, how, and with what significance, different values of what-it's-like-ness should be mapped on to, or read off, the different numerical values of solutions to the equations of physics are deeper questions altogether, and not ones that can be explored here. They may all just be glorified tickles; or they may not: we simply don't know.
Instead, this section may be concluded with a quick restatement of the plot so far. The biological program holds out the promise that, within a few millennia at most, states of conscious mind everywhere will be by their very nature more enjoyable than anyone alive today can imagine. Our hereditary neurological pleasure-deficit stops us getting a grip on what biotechnology can genetically engineer. In (at the very least) an empirical sense, implementing the post-Darwinian program can fill the world with valuable experiences. They will be enjoyed by human, non-human and post-human beings. Post-Darwinian modes of experience are likely to be of a diversity, profundity and liquid intensity that goes beyond anything accessible to the impoverished hunter-gatherer-evolved imagination. All the moral ills identified by contemporary secular value-systems can be rooted out for ever. Suffering will one day become physically impossible. This all sounds rather bombastic; but the strategy is biologically feasible as a species-project should we choose to pursue it.
Whether maximising the valued in the world amounts, in practice and/or
theory, to maximising the intrinsically valuable in the world is another,
and harder, question. There is, I have argued, at least a prima facie case
that it does. We may one day live in a Universe whose equations describe
something which is intrinsically valuable by its very nature.
Chapter 3
3. When?
"The mass of men lead lives of quiet desperation"
(Thoreau)
3.0 Our Emotional Future.
Forget the biological program's practical
and ethical merits for now. What grounds are there for predicting that
pain and malaise will be replaced by ubiquitous well-being? When, if ever,
might it all become practical politics? If a fabulous Post-Darwinian Transition
does occur, then the revolution is likely to happen only once. It will
never be reversed. There won't be any going back to the old order because
it turned out that the heavenly microcosms cooked up by the paradise-engineering
specialists weren't as good as they were cracked up to be. For in practice
they will be far better.
That prospect may seem very distant back here in the biological Dark Ages.
Yet it shouldn't be. Even now, most of us try to manipulate our states
of mind via chemical means. We just aren't very good at it. Throughout
history, humans have tried to alter their consciousness by the use of a
variety of natural agents. Arbitrary, and highly selective, proscription
and persecution by the ruling elites has failed to prevent people from
experimenting with psychedelics and mood-enhancers alike. By the late twentieth
century, perhaps $400 billion or 8% of world trade was in illicit drugs.
Recreational agents which are legal and socially sanctioned by respectable society aren't, of course, popularly viewed as drugs at all. The nicotine addict and the alcoholic don't think of themselves as being practising but inept psychopharmacologists; and so alas their incompetence is frequently lethal.
Is such incompetence curable? If it is, and if the pan-hedonistic blueprint
is ever to be put into effect, a number of preconditions must first be
in place. A necessary and sufficient set could not possibly be listed here.
It is still worth isolating and examining below several distinct yet convergent
societal trends of huge potential significance.
First, it must be assumed that we will continue to seek out and use chemical mood-enhancers on a massive, species-wide scale.
Second, a pioneering and pharmacologically (semi-)literate elite will progressively learn to use their agents of choice in a much more effective, safe and rational manner. Better still, states of consciousness which can be induced chemically can later be pre-coded genetically.
Third, society will continue to fund and support research into genetic engineering and all forms of biotechnology. This will enable the breathtaking array of designer-heavens on offer from third-millennium biomedicine to be be implemented.
Fourth, the ill-fated governmental War On (some) Drugs will finally collapse under the weight of its own contradictions. Parents are surely right to be anxious about many of today's illegal intoxicants. Yet their toxicity will no more prove a reason to give up the dream of Better Living Through Chemistry than the casualties of early modern medicine are a reason to abandon contemporary medical science for homeopathy.
Fifth, the medicalisation of everyday life, and of the human predicament itself, will continue apace. All manner of currently ill-defined discontents will be medically diagnosed. They will be given respectable clinical labels. Mass-medicalisation will enable the big drug companies aggressively to extend their lucrative markets in medically-approved psychotropics to a widening clientele. New and improved alleles, and other innovative gene-therapies for mood- and mind-enrichment, will be patented. They will be brought to market by biotechnology companies eager to cure the psychopathologies of the afflicted; and to maximise profits.
Sixth, in the next few centuries an explosive proliferation of ever-more sophisticated virtual reality software products will enable millions, and then billions, of people to live out their ideal fantasies. Paradoxically, as will be seen, the triumph of sensation-driven wish-fulfilment will also demonstrate the intellectual bankruptcy of the Peripheralist approach. Unhappiness will persist. The hedonic treadmill won't succumb to computer software.
Seventh, secularism and individualism will
triumph over resurgent Islamic and Christian fundamentalism. An entitlement
to absolute happiness in this world, rather than the next, will take on
the status of a basic human right.
There are quite a few imponderables here. Futurology is not, and predictably
will never become, one of the exact sciences. Conceivably, one can postulate,
for instance, the global triumph of an anti-scientific theocracy. This
might be in the mould of the American religious right or even some kind
of Islamic fundamentalism. Less conceivably, there might be a global victory
of tender-minded humanism over the onward march of biotechnical determinism.
It is also possible that non-medically-approved drug use could be curtailed,
at least for a time, with punishments of increasingly draconian severity.
Abetted by the latest convulsion of moral panic over Drugs, for example,
a repressive totalitarian super-state could institute a regime of universal
compulsory blood tests for banned substances. Enforced "detoxification"
in rehabilitation camps for offenders would follow.
These scenarios and their variants are almost certainly too alarmist. Given
a pervasive ethos of individualism, and the world-wide spread of hedonistic
consumer-capitalism, then as soon as people discover that there is no biophysical
reason on earth why they can't be as happy as they choose indefinitely,
it will be hard to stop more adventurous spirits from exploring the option.
Lifelong ecstasy isn't nearly as bad as it sounds.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
3.1 Hedonism After The War.
So as an illustration of at least one plausible
run of events leading to an adoption of the biological strategy, it is
worth considering the consequences likely to ensue when western state governments
finally abandon their ill-starred and intellectually incoherent War Against
Drugs. This retreat might not seem inevitable. Here at least, however,
it will be assumed that the freedom to control one's own states of consciousness
can't be usurped by government indefinitely. State mind-control measures
may relax in the face of, first, an ascendant libertarian and free-market
ideology; second, a rising younger generation of experienced illegal drug-takers,
averse from being criminalised and scornful of the hypocrisies and double
standards of the older generation; and, third and not least, the unparalleled
and uncensorable information explosion across the Internet on the detailed
practicalities of how to synthesise and enjoy psychotropics of every description.
Decriminalisation, first de facto and then de jure, and subsequent legalisation
will not entail a straightforward abdication of state control. On the contrary,
the state will intervene from motives of fiscal self-interest and paternalistic
responsibility in the distribution process. The manufacture and supply,
and certainly the quality and purity, of psychotropics will be licensed,
guaranteed and regulated. This will reclaim a multi-billion pound sector
of economic life from organised and disorganised crime. It will further
allow a drastic and politically expedient reduction in direct taxation.
It should also eliminate some of the toxic adulterants common in street-drugs.
Thousands of newly decriminalised drug-users will re-enter mainstream civil
society. More intelligent drug-education, and the social institutionalisation
of previously illicit forms of drug-use, will further contribute to the
harm-reduction process.
Yet this is to paint a dangerously rosy picture of the consequences of legalisation. Desirable as it may be to stop criminalising and even locking up a growing percentage of the younger generation, notably in the USA, the far-reaching social and medical problems stemming from ill-informed drug-use will remain. For a start, an enormous and perhaps unquantifiable number of (currently) illicit and licit drug-users alike are, in effect, self-medicating. They don't like their own stressed, anxious or depressive consciousness the way it is otherwise. So they pursue what seem the only remedies realistically on offer. Their choices aren't altogether surprising. Other nominal mood-brighteners actually sound depressing. State-endorsed "antidepressants" are available solely on prescription. They get doled out by severe (wo)men in white coats. Officially, in any case, all such agents are of potential therapeutic value only to those deemed by the medical authorities to be mentally ill. This isn't a role or a label most people would willingly adopt. Such a severe image-problem means that millions of people who would otherwise benefit are missing out on some of the most worthwhile products of medical science.
They are more likely to turn instead to drugs with a very different image. The main shortcoming of the widely-used illegal euphoriants, such as cocaine and the amphetamines, is less that they are physically dangerous - they collectively kill only a minuscule fraction of 1% of the numbers carried off each year by the two legal state-sanctioned killers, tobacco and alcohol - but that receptor re-regulation ensures their long-term effects are very nearly the opposite of those for which their users take them in the first instance. The medical authorities, meanwhile, maintain a convenient fiction about all present or potential clinically approved mood-boosters. The official line is that delayed-action "antidepressants" have a negligible effect on "normal" people unless they are "really" depressed; or unless a "pathological" manic euphoria is induced, which would need to be medicated in turn. Moreover the medical profession's otherwise healthy caution about the risks of polypharmacy needlessly restricts the formulation and enjoyment of some very beautiful psychoactive cocktails of potent life-enrichers.
Once legalisation of currently banned and controlled drug-groups occurs, there will nonetheless be tremendous pressure on the state to sponsor the research, development and marketing of mood-brighteners for the wider population. These will be certainly be safer and more effective than the trashy street-drugs currently in circulation. Initially, many traditionalists will undoubtedly continue to practise and proselytise Total Abstinence in the spirit of the Just Say No school of thought. At the other extreme, a small minority of thrill-seekers in search of the ultimate high will probably still take crack and the like with predictably disastrous consequences. The human mind/brain isn't capable of sustaining such intensities of pleasure indefinitely without substantial design-enhancements not yet on offer. For millions of more responsible and psychopharmacologically educable people, however, the possibility of Better Living Through Chemistry will prove irresistible. They will judiciously pick-and-mix from a gamut of mood-brighteners, smart drugs, serenics, aphrodisiacs, anti-ageing drugs and other agents drawn from life-enhancing categories not yet invented. Already there are at least a few tentative indications that humanity's psychopharmacological stone-age is starting to draw to a close.
One class of mood-brightener appealing to the more temperamentally cautious
will be psychoactive agents with a therapeutic window: safer, more potent
and much more rewarding variants of a drug like nicotine. With nicotine,
the brain very efficiently modulates how much or how little it wants, and
within a quite narrow range, to achieve optimal effects. Other designer-drugs
will deliver dose-incremental benefits, but on a delayed-reward basis of
receptor re-regulation. Cautious polypharmacy, too, in the shape of combined
dopamine and serotonin agonists and re-uptake blockers looks especially
promising. Rather than spending months in exorbitantly expensive talk-therapy
with ill-defined goals and benefits, people will be able to take professional
specialist advice on customising and fine-tuning the psyche. Dysfunctional
traits of personality can then be psychochemically retailored. The gap
between idealised self-image and uncomfortable reality will shrink. Within
a few generations at most, the role of a national health service may be
to keep people happy as well as healthy: an anachronistic distinction that
may gradually outlive its usefulness.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
3.2 On Why We Need Bigger Drug Pushers.
Presently-illegal drug-use might be styled
"pressure from below". Pressure "from above" will come from the giant,
multi-billion dollar pharmaceutical companies. So long as the official
dogma of hard-line therapeutic minimalism dictates that there should be
no clinically-sanctioned drug-use in "healthy" people, a lot of very interesting
drugs indeed aren't going to make it to the marketplace. Hence while medico-political
orthodoxy holds, great commercial advantage accrues to the manufacturers
if as much of everyday human life as possible can be pathologised. For
it can then be mass-medicated with patentable drugs, preferably on a long-term
basis. The intimate relationship the industry enjoys with the medical profession
and its trade press will generally help the drug firms to communicate their
views effectively. If ill-specified and ubiquitous conditions such as age-related
memory-loss can be granted formal diagnostic respectability, they can then
be combated with cholinergic boosters and other forms of cognitive enhancer.
The use of such drugs can subsequently diffuse into the wider population.
They may be used by student examinees or ambitious executives, for instance,
to gain a competitive edge over their drugless contemporaries. And there
are much more exciting agents in development than the (not especially)
smart drugs currently on offer.
Very large numbers of young people today are at least in shallow, physical
terms tolerably fit. Possibly much of a sizeable and potentially lucrative
market will be allowed to remain untapped. If, on the other hand, it were
to be (rightly!) medically acknowledged that statistically normal spells
of youthful anxiety, lassitude, sub-clinical depression and angst were
a colossal health problem, then the pharmaceutical industry and the new
end-users of its products would in their different ways both be much better
off. For while the cynic may entertain doubts about the motives of the
drug companies and their marketing techniques, it should be emphasised
that the actual consequences of a creeping medicalisation of the human
condition are often to the good. Suspicious as many commentators may be
of such newly-labelled conditions as "dysthymia" and the like, diagnostic
categories of this nature reflect submerged misery and malaise on an uncharted
scale. Such states merit treatment even by today's dismally low minimum
criteria for emotional good health. The problem is not that we are medicalised
too much, but too little; and not very well.
Next in line for medicalisation might be a hitherto little-acknowledged
syndrome christened, say, "hypo-hedonic disorder" or some term of equally
portentous gravity. This label might widen the diagnostic drag-net to another
30-40% of the population. All of them, the drug companies will rightly
feel, deserve the best treatment money can buy. Slowly, the species-typical
emotional base-line will creep upwards, until take-off to self-sustained
felicific growth finally triumphs.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
3.3 Good Code Gets Better.
One as yet fundamentally under-medicalised
territory is the human genome. Several thousand reasonably well-defined
genetic disorders have currently been classified. Aside from a few tentative
clues, however, the genetic basis of medically-certified mood-disorders
has not been properly defined. We do not, in any case, have genes "for"
happiness, anxiety, depression, and so forth, in any but the following
sense. The presence or absence of certain genes with certain other genes
makes it statistically more or less likely that an organism will be happy,
anxious or depressed in a given type of environment and in a given range
of circumstances. The statistical margin of advantage, however, does not
need to be very large for natural selection to get to work.
Natural selection isn't going to be around for that much longer. The human
genome will have been mapped out within the next few years. It will take
several decades more to discover which combinations of genes code for structures
and proteins that, other things being equal, will depress mood and well-being
in childhood and later life. They can in time be taken out or repressed.
Those which have multiple complex effects, and can't readily be dispensed
with, can be replaced with variant alleles of the same gene whose actions
are more benign. Conversely, genes associated with hyperthymia i.e. the
relatively uncommon mental abnormality of feeling consistently happy in
the absence of exhausting (hypo-)mania, can be introduced, reduplicated
and vigorously expressed in progressively larger numbers of the population
and their germ lines. The spread of hereditary hyperthymia should portend
a comprehensive reworking of the genome. Recoding the genetic bases of
mind, body and virtual worlds will conceivably take hundreds of generations
and more. A lot will depend on how long it takes to cure the ageing process.
The end of obligatory mortality will force a halt to the traditional breeding
free-for-all. Genome redesign is sure to become ever more daringly ambitious.
Old-fashioned electrodes in the pleasure centres may be aesthetically distasteful.
But they are a great deal simpler.
Again, it will be the big companies, this time in the biotechnology sector, who will initially be driving the psychogenetic revolution forward. A huge potential market exists for their products. In the short-term at least, real moral dilemmas will have to be confronted. These will be not unlike the dilemmas posed today by the existence of fundamentalist parents who deny their child a life-saving blood-transfusion. Future parents who decide, whether in deference to God or Nature, to decline gene-therapy for a child they know will likely grow up depressive, for example, may be open to accusations of child-abuse. Responsible parents, on the other hand, will want to get their kids the best happiness money can buy.
Accounts like this inevitably sound cold, technocratic and Brave New Worldish.
It should be recalled that the developments they describe should avert
suffering on a scale which a single mind cannot possibly comprehend; and
make a lot of people blissfully well.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
3.4 The Death-Spasms Of Peripheralism.
A further reason for predicting the abolition
of the capacity for negatively-charged experience is superficially very
different. It stems from a speculation on one indirect effect of omnipresent,
multi-modal and immersive Virtual Reality software. This potential multi-trillion
dollar industry is here posited to dominate social, personal, artistic
and economic life after the first century or two of the next millennium.
An assumption of this paper has been that (post-)humanity will eventually
break free from the Tyranny Of The (traditional, gene-manipulated) Intentional
Object. Our genes have ensured that emotion is so pervasively encephalised
that we have convinced ourselves that happiness can only be achieved, and
frustration avoided, by chasing after a crazy patchwork of intentional
shibboleths of no inherent value whatsoever. Humans have fought thousands
of unbelievably vicious wars against each other in consequence. In a sense,
our whole culture is a monument to the Peripheralist strategy; and a very
unpersuasive advertisement for it too. One of the few things that might
convince us, as a species, that Peripheralism can't bring lasting happiness
would be for us to see what it would be like if everything in the environment
were perfectly as human-beings might wish, and for our most impossible
fantasies and desires to be realised. Of course it has always been natural
to assume that such a notion was an idle pipedream. Even a Roman Emperor
couldn't get everything he wanted.
An all-pervasive network of virtual realities, however, will enable everyone
to have their intentional objects of desire fulfilled, and at minimal cost.
Interactive or solipsistic, artistic masterpiece or pornographic wish-fulfillment,
an ever-growing software library of virtual worlds will enable everyone
to have their dreams come true.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
3.5 And Yet It Still Grinds.
It won't, mirabile dictu, make most of us
much more happy for very long. The hedonic treadmill will still grind.
A revolution of rising expectations will eventually lead people to expect,
as of right, to enjoy and enact any set of perceptions and narrative structures
they choose. They'll expect to do so in virtual worlds with laws and body-images
of their own choosing. In the absence of a decent mesolimbic repair-job,
boredom, angst and other dormant negativities will periodically surface.
They'll sour the ostensibly perfect idylls and utopias. For ironically,
a mass migration into virtual worlds might come to represent Peripheralism's
final fling. Only total control of one's notional surroundings may be enough
to convince many people of the futility of pure environmental manipulation
if their goals include lasting happiness and fulfillment.
A symbiotic union of biologically programmed euphoria and mature virtual
reality software engineering, however, is an awesomely good prospect. In
fact, such a hybrid could furnish one explanation, however unlikely, of
the absence of any signs of intelligent life elsewhere in the galaxy. For
if a species acquires the sophistication to generate to order any possible
experience at all, whether hedonic, perceptual or other modes of being
altogether, then the motivational incentives to choose the inconvenient
kinds of experience involved in (non-virtual) space-exploration etc are
somewhat diminished. Indeed, since VR is probably less difficult to accomplish
than interstellar flight, the very possibility of vulgar physical star-hopping
may just never arise.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
3.6 The Technology of Shop-Soiled Utopias.
Two problems with the VR-scenario in general
are worth briefly discussing. The first is technical. It may be alleged
that realistic VR won't happen, contrary to the above, because it's too
difficult. Serious interactive virtual world-making would require processing
power several orders of magnitude faster than anything available today.
In allusion to the power of the human visual apparatus, it has been remarked
that Reality is 130 million polygons a second. Barring a revolution in
portable quantum supercomputing, this is simply unattainable by artificial
means.
One response here is simply to cite Moore's Law: processing power has been
roughly doubling every other year, and its tempo shows no sign of slackening
off. This leads to some dizzying projections. Moreover 130 million polygons
a second are probably wasted on a lot of people. The kinds of fantasy scenarios
that stir our deepest emotions, and those which might supposedly make us
most happy, are mainly of a rather uncomplicated kind. They tend to appeal
to relatively primitive appetites in settings where finely-wrought visual
subtleties are less than crucial. For even in our fantasies we enact parodies
of genetic fitness-maximising behaviour.
It is true that the time-scales projected here for the development of the
more sophisticated sorts of virtual world are vague. They may even be wildly
off-beam. Yet the dates, in common with all the other rough chronologies
suggested in this manifesto, are but a twinkle in the eye of eternity;
vitally important to individual members of the few generations around the
Transition epoch, but a minor detail in the history of life on earth and
beyond.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
3.7 Living In The Real World.
A second reason for doubting that omnipresent
virtual realities will ever lead to the demise of Peripheralism is that,
as the name suggests, they aren't real. A sense of authenticity, or any
notion that one's actions really matter, will be lacking in even the most
startlingly life-like creations. They may sometimes be entertaining, it
will be suggested, but even the greatest masterpieces of virtual reality
software will never displace Real Life. Interacting with real flesh-and-blood
people endowed with real feelings will always take precedence over responding
to mindless phantoms conjured up by machines.
As a peg to hang one's discontents on, the unreality of the impostors one
might meet in virtual paradise (or in one's capacity as virtual Lord of
the Galaxy, Casanova of the Cosmos or whatever) might indeed temper one's
enjoyment. Admittedly, those who by contemporary standards have relatively
benign genes and psychochemistry may not be unduly troubled. After all,
when watching plays or movies, or when reading a good thriller, one isn't
usually perturbed by the fictional status of the protagonists. Many enthusiasts
find even today's crude electronic games gripping for long periods; and
when Sega's Sonic arrived, I recall feeling pangs of jealousy at being
unable to compete for people's attention with a mere electronic hedgehog.
Moreover even disbelievers in direct-realist stories of perception seldom
seem to be smitten down by the awful sense of loneliness and isolation
that life behind the veil can induce.
Yet even if any serious malaise in virtual paradise is confined to the
temperamentally angst-ridden, there is a limit to how far perceptual-style
manipulation can go. When, as a species, we can generate by artificial
means essentially any perceptual experience or scenario at all from the
finite selection of states theoretically on offer, then it is just about
possible, I suppose, that what used innocently to be called progress will
in effect come to a stop. The future beyond the next millennium might just
consist of people permuting variations of the same old types of perceptual
and pseudo-perceptual experience. On no particularly knock-down evidence,
however, I think it more likely that we will want to access and explore
the modes of consciousness accessible only by more radical reconfigurations
of neurochemistry, beyond the influence of mere surface transducers. The
limbic system will be a very obvious early target. And when the gene-driven
biochemistry of nastiness has been unravelled and purged from our minds,
it is hard to see us ever putting it back.
Chapter 4
4. Objections.
4.0 "Happy experiences, and the very concept
of happiness itself, are possible only because they can be contrasted with
melancholy. The very notion of everlasting happiness is incoherent."
Some people endure lifelong emotional depression or physical pain. Quite literally, they are never happy. Understandably, they may blame their misery on the very nature of the world, not just their personal clinical condition. Yet it would be a cruel doctrine which pretended that such people don't really suffer because they can't contrast their sense of desolation with joyful memories. In the grips of despair, they may find the very notion of happiness cognitively meaningless. Conversely, the euphoria of unmixed (hypo)mania is not dependent for its sparkle on recollections of misery. Given the state-dependence of memory, negative emotions may simply be inaccessible to consciousness in such an exalted state. Likewise, it is possible that our perpetually euphoric descendants will find our contrastive notion of unhappiness quite literally inconceivable. For when one is extraordinarily super-well, then it's hard to imagine what it might be like to be chronically mentally ill.
Here's a contemporary parallel. It's possible to undergo, from a variety of causes, a complete bilateral loss of primary, secondary and "associative" visual cortex. People with Anton's Syndrome not only become blind; they are unaware of their sensory deficit. Furthermore, they lose all notion of the meaning of sight. They no longer possess the neurological substrates of the visual concepts by which their past and present condition could be compared and contrasted. Our genetically joyful descendants may, or may not, undergo an analogous loss of cognitive access to the nature and variant textures of suffering. Quite plausibly, they will have gradients of sublimity to animate them and infuse their thoughts. So at least they'll be able to make analogies and draw parallels. But fortunately for their sanity and well-being, they won't be able to grasp the true frightfulness lying behind linguistic remnants of the past that survive into the post-Darwinian era. Such lack of contrast, or even the inconceivability of aversive experience, won't leave tomorrow's native-born ecstatics any less happy; if anything quite the reverse.
It's true that a world whose agents are animated by pleasure gradients
will still have the functional equivalent of aversive experience. Yet the
"raw feel" of such states may still be more wonderful than anything physiologically
possible today.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.1 "The scenarios mapped out in this paper are impracticable. None of them would work in reality. The human brain is too complex to be hardwired for lifetime bliss. Nature, in her wisdom, would ensure that some complicated cycle of feedback-inhibition eventually kicked in. This would restore more equable and subdued states of mind."
Any attempt to hardwire into the cerebral cortex a functional understanding of the Theory of General Relativity, say, or perhaps to set "by hand" the neural connections and activation weights mediating an appreciation of Shakespearean tragedy, would presumably defeat all but the most utopian neuroscience. Such virtuoso feats won't be necessary. The physiological roots of affective states lie mostly deep within the phylogenetically primitive limbic-system. They aren't "merely" limbic; this is to miss the evolutionary significance of their encephalisation. Yet their basis is still incomparably simpler than the plethora of cognitive processes they penetrate. For sure, the functional pathways of our emotions are complicated to twentieth-century eyes. Yet they should prove tractably so. Just as we can, with horrible cruelty, administer drug-cocktails that induce unremitting despair - this is sometimes done in exploring animal "models" of depression - so we can crudely, and some day exquisitely, polarise mood in the opposite direction.
It will be recalled that the monoaminergic neurons, peptides and endorphins
that underlie the emotional tone of experience play an essentially modulatory
role. They are not individually directed on notional site-specific representations
pre-coded by genes. If the receptors, enzymes, cytoplasmic proteins and
genetic switches in one's ventral tegmental area and nucleus accumbens
are suitably reconfigured, and if these wonderful cells continue to fire
away vigorously, then one is going to be outrageously happy indefinitely.
Natural selection has no powers of foresight and anticipation with which
to frustrate us. Nature isn't waiting to take its revenge. Given a richer
dopaminergic etc innervation of the neo-cortex, then the focus of future
ecstatic happiness will be on a shifting and unpredictable panorama of
intentional objects. The potential complexity and variety of those objects
- i.e. what one will be nominally happy "about" - is indeed staggering.
Yet when each fleeting neocortical coalition is blissfully innervated from
"below", every one of them can be a focus of delight. It will be exhilarating,
and the fun simply won't stop. For the hedonic treadmill will have been
genetically dismantled for ever.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.2 "If we were always elated, we'd suffer the same fate as intra-cranially self-stimulating laboratory animals. We'd starve, or die of general self-neglect. Both physical and psychological pain do more than promote the inclusive fitness of genes. For the most part, they protect the individual organism from harm too. If a regime of universal happiness were attempted, we'd never want to have sex and reproduce. Therefore we'd become extinct as a species."
A project geared to crude biological pleasure-maximisation alone could well undermine the autonomous survival-skills of its participants. In a comprehensively automated, computerised, robot-served civilisation, this supposed incapacity wouldn't in the long run pose a particular problem. Moreover it is only certain types, not intensities, of pleasure which are incompatible with efficient self-maintenance. Pragmatically, however, worry over the incapacitating effects of excess well-being on its victims illustrates the advantages of retaining both well-defined intentional objects and the goal-directed behaviour advocated in this manifesto. Tomorrow's paradise-engineering specialists will probably judge it prudent to keep these traditional forms of life. Such modes of old-style intentionality will be needed for the purposes of any practical medium-term utopia, at least. No heroic sacrifice of subjective well-being is thereby demanded.
The role of pain isn't as straightforward as it seems. Its dreadfulness has been adaptive in our evolutionary past. Yet any full explanation of pain's phenomenological nastiness, as distinct from the functional role of "nociception", still eludes us completely; and perhaps it always will. The spectre of raw nastiness, however, is not the only way a complex adaptive system can be induced to avoid, and respond to, injury. Unfortunately, it seems to have been the only adaptive response open to primordial carbon-based organisms consistent with the principles of natural selection. Fortunately, other strategies are now feasible. Evolution can't jump across deserts in the fitness landscape. Paradise-designers certainly can. Humans can already build robots armed with "self-taught" artificial neural networks. These toy robots can learn to negotiate simple environments. They are capable of avoiding noxious stimuli via responses to functional isomorphs of our pain states. Robotic silicon circuitry presumably lacks wetware's raw feel of phenomenological nastiness. So a less barbarous and primitive means of avoiding tissue damage in organic life-forms can surely be devised as well. [This expression of carbon chauvinism is controversial. It is not idle prejudice, however, but an inference drawn from the structurally and micro-functionally unique properties of the carbon atom and complex organic molecules.]
One expedient would be to use inorganic prostheses adapted from the design of our own future robots. A slightly more elegant solution would exploit our innate if often inept tendency to pleasure-maximisation. Peripheral nerves signalling noxious stimuli currently synapse on neural pain cells. They could instead be re-targeted on neurons which were simply less efficiently hedonistic in their biochemistry than their cellular neighbours. With their post-sensory signals remapped, infants could then learn self-preservation and pleasure-maximisation in harmony. At least as a stopgap, exploiting pleasure gradients is a much more civilised way to live. It's far more humane than responding to the contours of their nasty, and sometimes utterly excruciating, aversive counterparts.
A further presupposition of the question needs examining. One should be wary of assuming that we're the folk who can properly look after ourselves, whereas our descendants, if they become genetically pre-programmed ecstatics, will get trapped in robot-serviced states of infantile dependence. For it shouldn't be forgotten that exuberantly happy people also have a fierce will to survive. They love life dearly. They take on daunting challenges against seemingly impossible odds. One of the hallmarks of many endogenous depressive states, on the other hand, is so-called behavioural despair. If one learns that apparently no amount of effort can rescue one from an aversive stimulus, then one tends to sink into a lethargic stupor. This syndrome of "learned helplessness" may persist even when the opportunity to escape from the nasty stimulus subsequently arises.
Contemporary fatalism about the "inevitability" of suffering is analogous to this dysfunctional passivity (cf the behavioural syndrome associated with the religious traditions of the Indian subcontinent). Yet passive acceptance of the dark side of life is no longer useful to us. Species-wide hedonic engineering offers the prospect of eliminating all the vile types of experience we hate most; but even though it has become technically feasible to escape their clutches, a lot of us still aren't energetically striving to get rid of them. Unlike tortured lab-rats and monkeys, we can verbally rationalise our perceived helplessness in the face of psychological trauma or malaise. Suffering, we say, is "natural", "inevitable", "the way of the world", "Life", etc. By contrast, our eternally youthful, psychologically super-fit descendants won't need such coping-mechanisms. They are likely to be fired up with indomitable will-power. Their resourcefulness and zest for living should make them far better equipped to deal with life's practical inconveniences. Potential problems will be viewed as tremendously exciting challenges to be overcome. But in any case, future generations of post-humans are destined to enjoy god-like powers unknown to the mythical Olympians - both inside their virtual reality suites and out. Thus they may be ecstatically happy, but we would be rash to patronise them. For we're the ones who need help.
The argument that our descendants might become functional wireheads, too
happy to reproduce, isn't compelling either. Happy people tend to want
more sex, not less. Not everyone may opt for erotic modes of pleasure.
But amongst sensualists who do, then gene-coded hyper-dopaminergic well-being
is likely to promote, not celibacy, but heightened sexuality. This isn't
simply a recipe for loveless orgies. Enriched serotonergic, phenylethylamine,
oxcytocin and opiate function will allow us to care much more for each
other and our dependants than selfish DNA normally allows today. Just how
many newly-minted young ecstatics the world can ecologically accommodate,
on the other hand, is uncertain. The elimination of functional pathologies
like the ageing process is likely to make curbing rampant reproduction
rather than promoting it a priority.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.3 "This whole manifesto is flawed from the outset by its crudely reductionist approach to human beings. Our most profound spiritual experiences, and indeed what it is to be a person, can't be reduced to a dance of soulless molecules."
In the tough-minded reductionist camp, a hard-nosed atheistical scientist may be loath to see the beautifully choreographed neurons of his temporal cortex reduced to a spiritual buzz of religiosity. This isn't a very fruitful perspective either.
In one's eagerness to avoid an impoverished conception of human beings,
it is easy to fall victim to an impoverished conception of chemicals. Natural
scientists, no less than humanists, can easily fall into the same trap.
On the assumption that all conscious experience - "what-it's-like-ness"
- is identical with certain physical events or properties, then our classical
materialist image of the ontology of the physical world, and our concept
of what it means to be "physical", must be jettisoned as simply erroneous.
It is not our fanciful mental images of matter and energy, but our deepening
grasp of the formal mathematical tools needed for a description of quantum-mechanical
events, that has enabled us increasingly to control and manipulate the
basic stuff of the world. This grasp is now letting us control and manipulate,
as well, the experiences with which at least some distributions of that
"stuff" are identical. The phraseology sounds sinister and Orwellian. Yet
if one's sovereign ethical principle entails striving for the fullest possible
development of personal well-being everywhere, then embarking on the post-Darwinian
enterprise is the only rational option.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.4 "All of the drugs and therapeutic interventions touted here could potentially have long-term side-effects that we can't anticipate. The risk of another thalidomide tragedy writ large is too great to justify medical treatment of people who (by the norms of late twentieth century psychiatry, at least) are not suffering from any clinically recognised disorder."
The thalidomide tragedy took place several decades ago. The scandal unfolded before the medical significance of different optical isomers of the same compound in the body was appreciated. Such a mistake will not be made again. Of course, it can't be ruled out that other grave errors of judgement will be made instead. They probaby will. In the early stages of any innovative treatment, the risk-reward ratio must always be finely weighed. This is all the more reason for preliminary experimentation to take place in the clinic and the laboratory, not on the street.
Presently, for instance, millions of young people are left to obtain and
consume, in the most haphazard manner imaginable, the potentially neurotoxic
compound MDMA. "Ecstasy" typically offers an enchanting state of consciousness
while the trip lasts. Yet it's a dangerous short-cut to mental health.
Unless a subsequent dose of fluoxetine or other ssri is taken soon afterwards,
the drug damages serotonergic axonal terminals. Serotonin plays a vital
role in regulating mood, anxiety and sleep. Thus in the long-term, MDMA
and the other methoxylated amphetamines represent a poor choice of self-medication.
It would be far better if the government were to take on the job of educating
and training people in the most rational and effective ways to be happy.
This role will involve sponsoring the research, development and widest
possible distribution of the most safe, sustainable and beautiful euphoriants
that medical science can formulate. Better still, research should focus
on heritable gene-driven bliss. This will banish the need for drugs altogether.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.5 "The radical therapeutic interventions which the biological program entails will presumably necessitate large-scale testing on non-human animals. This is surely inconsistent with the animal welfarist stance adopted earlier in the manifesto."
Given the feasibility, albeit not without difficulty,
of implanting electrodes in the mind/brain's pleasure centres, there can
be no principled utilitarian objection to subjecting both human and non-human
animals to a great deal of enjoyment in the course of medical research.
Many of the practical difficulties the biological program will face, and
which demand greatest depth of understanding, stem precisely from avoiding
crude pleasure-maximisation in the absence of a suitably well-designed
encephalisation of emotion throughout the neo-cortex. If the animals in
any experimental procedure are kept exceedingly happy for its duration,
then the utilitarian ethicist needn't suffer any qualms of principle. At
present, of course, the difference between an animal-experimenter's laboratory
and a torture chamber is often imperceptible from his victims' point of
view.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.6 "Abolishing suffering is unnatural: in so doing we would forfeit our essential humanity."
Warfare, rape, famine, pestilence and child-abuse have existed since time immemorial. They are quite "natural", whether from a historical, cross-cultural or sociobiological perspective. The implicit, and usually highly selective, equation of the "natural" with the morally good is dangerously facile and simplistic. The popular inclination to ascribe some kind of benign wisdom to an anthropomorphised Mother Nature serves, in practice, only to legitimate all manner of unspeakable cruelties. Extremes of suffering are inevitable under the neurochemical status quo.
If a personified Nature did in some sense care about the progeny she prolifically churned out, then tampering with her benevolent handiwork might indeed represent a foolhardy Temptation of Providence. This sort of archaic romanticism about the physical world is impossible to reconcile with the neo-Darwinian synthesis. As has been all too aptly observed, our genes just use us and then throw us away. "Unnatural" here is no more than a pejorative label. We use it to stigmatise, rather than rationally argue against, whatever we reflexively dislike. The very notion that a playing out of the laws of physics might ever yield something contrary to Nature is itself deeply suspect. Construed in any literal sense, it is false. Nothing that occurs in Nature is, or could be, unnatural. Both we and the transformed universe of our near and distant posterity are equally a part of the natural world. Metaphorically interpreted, on the other hand, the charge is too ill-defined to be refutable.
And, yes, we will lose some primitive, "essential", human attributes. Yet
why on earth should this be reckoned a bad thing? Until the development
of powerful pain-killing drugs and modern surgical anaesthesiology, for
example, frightful extremes of physical suffering were simply a part of
the human condition. The unendurable just had to be lived through. Happily,
in the present era our access to potent narcotics means, for the most part,
that we no longer need to rationalise physical torments with the desperate
sophistries typical of the past. Anyone arguing on religio-mystical grounds
today that a loss of the agonies of the flesh is offensive to God, robbing
us of a vital part of our species-essence, etc., is likely to get deservedly
short shrift. Yet the supposedly ennobling properties of agonies of the
spirit are still widely respected. Perhaps this attitude will change when
retaining the capacity to feel psychological pain becomes a perverse aberration
rather than a condition of existence; and when inflicting it on others
becomes an unthinkable crime.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.7 "I'd get bored of being happy all the time. Variety is indispensable to personal well-being."
As an empty verbalism, "perpetual bliss" does sound fairly tedious. As Bernard Shaw once remarked, "Heaven, as conventionally conceived, is a place so inane, so dull, so useless, so miserable, that nobody has ever ventured to describe a whole day in heaven, though plenty of people have described a day at the seaside".
Successful paradise-engineering, however, must be the very antithesis of tedium by its very nature. If it sounds unexciting, one has simply missed the point. In a different age, religious iconographers were able to derive much greater satisfaction in depicting the tortures of the wicked in Hell than in evoking the curiously anaemic delights of Heaven; indeed, one could be forgiven for inferring that the eternal happiness of the Saved was dependent on contemplation of the eternal torment of the Damned. Likewise today, the secular equivalent of this syndrome is all too common. Potentially, however, there is no less a diversity of ways of being happy as being wretched. It is a grim reflection of the late-Darwinian human predicament that any notion of perpetual happiness evokes images of monotony. We can conjure up a rich and never-ending diet of disasters with ease.
Whatever humanity's contemporary failures of imagination, within a few generations the experience of boredom will be neurophysiologically impossible. From a naturalistic perspective, boredom amounts to just a complex of psychophysical states which natural selection has chanced upon like any other. It was retained because of the adaptive value its conditional activation can confer. Its more proximate physiological basis lies in the negative feedback mechanisms underlying the development of tolerance in the brain. These may be expressed in the form either of short-term habituation or a slightly more delayed process of gene-triggered receptor re-regulation. Such mechanisms can be disabled and replaced.
For as is experimentally demonstrable in the laboratory, the intra-cranial
approach of endless stimulation of the pleasure-centres of the brain confirms
that happiness, and happiness itself alone, never palls. Out in the wider
world, positive emotion just gets (re)directed to focus on and infuse a
variety of intentional objects. None of our neocortical patterns is inherently
nice or nasty in the absence of its distinctive signature of limbic innervation.
Some of them may in time cease to satisfy; stone-age love affairs are cruel.
Given the mind-brain identity theory presupposed in this manifesto, however,
there is no biological reason why each moment of one's existence couldn't
have the impact of a breathtaking revelation. As the phenomena of déjà
vu, and its rarer cousin jamais vu, strikingly attest, a sense of familiarity
or novelty is dissociable from the previous presence or absence of any
particular type of intentional object with which such feelings might more
normally be associated. So the kind of thrill one might first have got
witnessing, say, the Creation can in principle become a property of every
second of one's life. Cool.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.8 "In the light of past horrors, from Auschwitz to the most private of griefs, it is disgusting even to contemplate celebrating existence by getting perpetually blissed out of one's head. Happiness, and indeed any other emotional state or response, should be rationally justifiable. It should be experienced only when it is appropriate. Given the horrors existing elsewhere in space-time, pure bliss is rationally unwarranted."
If it doesn't diminish the well-being of others,
does happiness stand in need of justification any more than does the experience
of, say, redness? As long as there is any chance that what we construe
as the lessons of history might be ignored, and the obscenities of our
evolutionary past in some way re-enacted, then there are excellent ethical-utilitarian
reasons for keeping accessible even the most dreadful of memories. It may
be important to remember more recent history, too, so as to honour and
be supportive of those who have suffered in it and are now plagued by memories
of earlier traumas and sacrifice. Yet to enjoin a grim reflection on the
nature of the past for its own sake, a form of melancholy which, self-consistently,
must itself presumably be commemorated mournfully in turn, is to set in
motion an escalating cycle of misery without end. It's time to call a halt.
Sometimes it is just better to forget rather than endlessly relive and
recreate. If this sounds like shallow hedonism, it is worth recalling that
HI's negative utilitarianism is an ethical system against which such a
charge can least plausibly be sustained.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.9 "I don't want a lifetime of enforced ecstasy. I want the freedom sometimes to be sad, and not to be enslaved to a false chemical happiness."
It is most unclear how to unpack the notion of "false" happiness. Contaminating the God-given purity of one's soul-stuff with alien chemicals is presumably offensive if one's self-conception is essentially spiritual in character. If, on the other hand, all states of consciousness alike are physically mediated, then it is scarcely coherent to label some neurochemical patterns as inherently false, unreal or inauthentic. Such euphoric states have indeed hitherto been largely inaccessible and genetically maladaptive. They are still natural properties of suitably structured metabolic pathways of matter and energy. So in that sense they are all "true", though this is a most infelicitous way of putting it.
It is not, in any case, as though anyone will plausibly be forced to be
happy against their will. Just as, historically, many slaves did not challenge
the institutional legitimacy of slavery, and many self-confessed sinners
believed they deserved to be damned to an eternity of torment in Hell,
so many people have been able to convince themselves of the ennobling quality
of suffering. They will scarcely be ambushed and hauled in off the streets
one day by crack-demented ecstatics and forcibly pumped full of euphoriants.
A more apposite question might be what instruments of repression should
a coercive State apparatus be entitled to use on behalf of possible bigoted
die-hards of the old order against people who decide, reasonably enough,
that they do wish to live happily ever after. To what degree, and for how
long and in what form, should authoritarian reactionaries have the right
to compel others to suffer, once emotional primitivism becomes simply one
life-style option amongst many?
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.10 "Pharmacological hedonism would turn us all into junkies. Gene-driven hedonism wouldn't be any different. We would lose all personal freedom because we'd be as helplessly addicted to our chemical fixes as the typical crack-head."
Once one has tasted other-worldly transports of ecstasy, it is true, there is no foreseeable way one would choose voluntarily to renounce such a condition. For from our current perspective, we have no more grasp of the real glory of the sublime than a newly-instructed five-year old child has of all but the barest mechanics of love or sex. Does our absence of hyper-ecstatic experience entitle us to claim any greater authority than the precocious youngster? Is such a claim testable? In reality, the nature of what lies beyond the arid text displayed here will prove, on revelation, more wonderful than could currently be physiologically imagined. Enraptured, one will rapidly enter into whole new modes of being. Reality redefined will feel so good that any surrender of born-again existence would be unendurably traumatic.
This condition might seem almost definitive of addiction. On a utilitarian metric (barring only the austere "negative" sub-species), if such marvellous states are reliably and universally accessible, then seeking to achieve and maximise them is straightforwardly the right course to take. Addiction will tend to be a problem only if, first, people are hooked on something noxious to themselves or others; or, second, there is any likelihood of an interruption to their supply of the relevant drug or gene therapy. At present, we are dependent for what passes as mental health on different precursor amino-acids, essential fatty acids, minerals, vitamins etc to synthesise the brain's meagre dribble of pleasure-chemicals. We suffer gross psychophysical distress if we are deprived of them for long. This dependence, however, is regarded as wholesome rather than pernicious. It gets awarded the honorific "food". To achieve optimum mental health, on the other hand, one needs to dine on the richer diet of therapeutic agents advertised in this manifesto. The principle is the same.
The sheer finality of the Post-Darwinian Transition may indeed appal the metaphysical libertarian. For there can be no going back. Yet any opponent of the biological program should be unsettled, too, by how endorsement of the traditional Nature-knows-best stance turns on our not exploring, however fleetingly, one of the two alternatives at issue. Ignorance is not bliss. Anyone who does empirically investigate, and not just pronounce on a priori, the rival forms of life on offer will unswervingly opt for the new modes of existence pleaded for here. More tellingly for the libertarian, perhaps, there is a sense in which the right to select one's own chemistry of consciousness, and thus to choose precisely who or what one wants to be, is as vital a sort of personal freedom as any. It is one which we at present substantially lack. Any research program that opens up just such an option species-wide confers, surely, an incalculably life-enriching extension of choice.
Our own contemporary "choices" are in any case oversold. In the current
era, we may seem biologically unconstrained. Some of us feel we can be,
and do, more or less who and what we want. In fact, we can subsist only
within the largely insensible confines of an extremely restrictive state
space of psychochemical reactions. We can't hop outside their metabolic
pathways to check what we're missing. If we could, we'd find it too mind-wrenchingly
different for words. Soon, however, we need no longer languish in biological
servitude to our genes and the disposable vehicles they throw up. Today's
junkies may vainly wish to be free from their inadvertently acquired addictions.
This is only because the lows of illegal, dangerous and often self-defeating
drug-taking ultimately outweigh the ephemeral highs of ill-chosen chemical
euphoria. When, on the other hand, one opts once-and-for-all for a decent
molecular architecture of body-and-soul orgasmic sublimity, then one opts
as well for a lifetime's freedom from second thoughts.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.11 "I sometimes like being sad; it's an experience I wouldn't wish to lose."
An agreeable, wistful melancholy, a haunting
lullaby nostalgically recalled from childhood, or perhaps the bitter-sweet
memory of a long-lost love, are certainly preferable to the hell of unmitigated
depression. Yet all too many types of experiences are unambiguously dreadful.
They have no redeeming features at all. They don't issue in great works
of art, literature and scholarship etc. They would be far better abolished.
All the positive aspects of the more complex and ambivalent states one
may undergo can in future be magnified and sharpened; nothing enjoyable
need be lost. But the negative undercurrents which still diminish the value
and enjoyment of more perceptibly composite states can be chemically subtracted
out.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.12 "Without suffering, there can be no personal development; unearned happiness leads to stasis."
Suffering is often just coarsening and brutalising. If one is sunk in hopeless despair, or even caught in the grip of an ill-defined malaise, it is as difficult to care about one's inner growth as it is to care about other people. Personal growth is more likely to unfold if one's appetite for life gets steadily keener. This will occur if one's experiences get progressively richer and more rewarding. Odysseys of self-exploration across the hedonic landscape can offer scope for ever-deepening self-discovery and idealised self-reinvention. Odysseys of pain and misfortune are as likely to desensitise or crush one's spirit as develop it.
Under the grisly biological status quo, cultivating a sense of personal
development is a comforting form of rationalisation, e.g: if I hadn't lost
my legs in the accident 20 years ago I would never have become a great
artist. So it proved a blessing in disguise after all! Prospectively, however,
if one were told 20 years of suffering lay ahead if one sacrificed one's
legs, but boundless self-development would follow in consequence, then
one still wouldn't opt for it; and quite right too. As long as suffering
is biologically inevitable, fitfully at least, then its optimal rationalisation
is important. Thus reading this essay may cause more distress than joy
to inveterate rationalisers; I just trust any unease will be mild and temporary.
Yet when the biochemistry of suffering becomes only an optional neural
add-on, the solace that rationalisation provides will impede the abolition
of the miseries that demand it.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.13 "Why bother with this intentional flotsam and jetsam at all if happiness itself is supposedly the overriding goal? In the context of the biological program, aren't intentional objects really free-floating and inessential frills to be varied or discarded at will? Isn't invoking "sublimity", "beauty", "love", etc, intellectually dishonest. Aren't they just rhetorical camouflage to win over those whose ideal pleasures tend to the respectably cerebral and the ethereal rather than the orgiastic?"
Our emotions have been pretty thoroughly encephalised by evolution. So it is certainly easier to give some hint of the nature of the paradise that awaits us by evoking, one may hope, the feelings one's audience associates with their own most cherished fantasies and objects of desire. Advocating happiness bereft of any nominal focus, on the other hand, entails working with a lifeless and unpersuasive abstraction. Advocating "hedonism" in the abstract is even worse. The term evokes something shallow, one-dimensional and amoral. Unfortunately, that's the price of sacrificing an underlying seriousness of moral purpose for the sake of a snappy title.
Naturally, what we think and say we're happy "about" is likely to change. Many highly-charged intentional objects of contemporary desires will seem historical curiosities even a few decades hence. In common with the particular time- and culture-bound conceptions of heaven and the good life in, say, different eras of the Christian and Islamic traditions, today's favourite intentional objects may indeed be only of derivative value. The meso-limbic dopamine system is doing most of the real causal work. But if the lure of such idols can motivate us to act on the promise of the biological program, then they will have more than served their purpose.
There are, however, substantive reasons why non-arbitrary intentional objects, and indeed an ever-greater scientific understanding of the world, should remain accessible into the indefinite future. The merely pragmatic advantages of the intentionalist strategy have already been cited. Sometimes it's useful to be able to look after oneself. There are powerful ethical reasons for keeping intentionalism as well. For ethically it is imperative that the sort of unspeakable suffering characteristic of the last few hundred million years on earth should never recur elsewhere. If such horror might exist anywhere else in the cosmos, presumably in the absence of practical intelligence sufficiently evolved to eliminate its distal roots, then this suffering too must be systematically sought out. It needs to be extirpated just as hell-states will have been on earth. Such inter-stellar rescue missions won't be possible if post-humans have all become wedded to the functional equivalent of wirehead-style pleasure-frenzies. This is because planning, executing and then stewarding ethically-run ecosystems of primordial extra-terrestrial life will require ultra-high technology, wide-ranging research, and a very long time. Subject to a number of assumptions about the origin of information-bearing self-replicators, any primordial life-forms - as distinct from some of their possible artificial successors - will be carbon-based. If multi-cellular evolution occurs, such alien life-forms will quite plausibly run on the same pleasure-pain axis as we do. Of course, this is all hugely speculative. And if trying to save the world is ambitious, then trying to save the universe smacks of hubris; so this avenue won't be pursued further here.
A negative utilitarian will still think that the striving for ever greater
extremes and varieties of pleasurable experience while there remains any
suffering whatsoever in this universe is a frivolous distraction from what
morally matters. (S)he may be right. Certain contrived scenarios aside,
however, the direct intra-cranial route to paradise may serve the different
flavours of utilitarianism equally well.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.14 "Many of the greatest scientific and artistic achievements of humanity were born of tremendous struggles against adversity. Abolishing the biological substrates of suffering would mean there could be no fruitful inner struggle or creative tension, and hence no more Newtons, Picassos or Beethovens. Scientific and artistic genius demands a capacity for fierce criticism, both of one's own work and the ideas of others. Even if inducing a state of perpetual euphoria is consistent with bodily self-survival, the lack of critical self-insight such states entail would bring intellectual progress to a halt for ever."
It is worth distinguishing between the destiny of the humanities and the sciences after heaven has been biologically implemented. For a start, the exquisite aesthetic experiences on offer may inspire an unprecedented flowering rather than a withering of the arts. Our current enjoyment of, say, Van Gogh's "Sunflowers" or Leonardo's "The Last Supper" will seem distracting tickles in comparison. Those who would deny that beauty is in the eye of the beholder might, or might not, be impressed by the disposition of paint on canvass which inspires these rhapsodies. Yet any reservations will last only so long as they remain trapped in the neurochemical orthodoxy of the past. At present, cultivating a fastidious unresponsiveness to certain forms of artistic production is taken as a badge of sophistication and discernment; but then that is our loss.
A blessing of the transcendent beauty awaiting discovery is that it will not depend on the vagaries of artistic genius for its production. The mind/brain lacks "beauty centres" of the same relatively well-defined architecture as its meso-limbic pleasure-system. Yet once the neurochemical concomitants of aesthetic appreciation are pieced together, they can then be enhanced and selectively amplified. It should be recalled that perennial happiness can as easily lead to more being done in one's life rather than less. Intense episodes of creative energy today are often indistinguishable from mild euphoric hypomania. Some temperamentally laid-back lotus-eaters may indeed ultimately opt for meditative bliss and serenity. On the other hand, post-Transition society will probably be shaped by hypomanic "high-achievers" of formidable dynamism and productivity. Today's thrusting, can-do go-getters will seem lackadaisical in comparison.
The modes of well-being optimal for doing first-rate science and mathematics
are obviously different from those best for practising first-rate art,
poetry or sex. There is no reason why they should be less intense and rewarding.
As to any lack of critical insight, there are also intellectual advantages
to be derived from states of invincible well-being. Criticism of one's
ideas in modern academia, for instance, is commonly taken as a full-frontal
assault on the ego. In the future, critical scrutiny may be actively solicited
and ecstatically welcomed. This might prove conducive to markedly better
scholarship.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.15 "The proposals of HI are too fanciful ever to gain credence, or even deserve serious critical consideration. They make a mockery of all our current values, aspirations and life-projects. A program so abhorrent to one's common-sense and moral intuitions belongs to the realm of vulgar science fiction rather than serious applied science or ethical debate."
Science has comprehensively confounded "common-sense" in all empirical matters. Our traditional ethical intuitions, when wrapped in secular guise, are less susceptible to experimental challenge. It would be a piece of singular good fortune if the least testable aspects of common-sense folk-wisdom just happened to be the ones that could most be relied on. At the very least, intellectual honesty demands that radically counter-intuitive challenges to received value-systems should receive close critical appraisal. The "values, aspirations and life-projects" typical of, say, classical antiquity or the Indian sub-continent may easily seem ridiculous to the jaundiced contemporary eye. Likewise, the disparate intentional objects with which our own well-being now seems inseparably bound may eventually be seen as no less superstitiously revered. They objectively matter, but only because they objectively matter to us. So on the assumption that ethics amounts to something more than truth-valueless word-spinning, then it is worth at least considering the merits of ethical standpoints no less repugnant to common sense than, say, the theories of contemporary physics.
Appearances to the contrary, there is in any case a sense in which this paper, however superficially outlandish its substance, does not demand any revolutionary transformation of the core values of our secular culture. Its thrust stems from taking a quite conventional principle with the utmost seriousness it deserves. Only a minority of contemporary philosophers or laypeople are expressly utilitarians. Yet a diffuse and unsystematic utilitarianism is extremely widespread in society. It permeates the outlook of many people who never use the term. More interestingly, perhaps, an extraordinarily large proportion of non-, or even professedly anti-, utilitarian positions are argued on, or are underlain by, grounds which on examination prove subtly utilitarian.
Paradoxically, for utilitarian reasons it is nonetheless probably all to the good, this side of paradise at least, that at least some expressly non-utilitarian values are still held. This is because traditional folk-verities offset the acute discomfort many people still feel at the full implications of an exclusively utilitarian ethic.
Of course, one does not have to be a utilitarian to endorse the proposals
of this manifesto. To those who are broadly sympathetic to the ethical
utilitarian approach, however, then the biological program amounts, figuratively
at least, to a gift from the gods.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.16 "Being trapped in a chemical paradise would leave one wholly at the mercy of the ruling elites. The authorities could then treat people as puppets to be manipulated at will for their own ends."
The image that provokes this anxiety is presumably that of a drug-pacified class of helots. Perhaps a chemically enslaved underclass will work sweatshop hours for their masters simply to get their next chemical hit. In this fanciful scenario, it is in fact debatable who, if anyone, would really be exploiting whom. Also, certain sanctions are effective only if threatened rather than applied. No group is more ungovernably rebellious towards law and authority than addicts deprived of their fix. Moreover in our society, at least, the idea of the ruling elites engaging in a conspiracy to keep their population happy while they stoically shoulder the burdens of office tends to overtax the imagination; this is one conspiracy theory too far.
In any case, the conventional equation of happiness and docility owes more to distant memories of Huxley's Brave New World than to any deep reflection on the genetic, sociobiological and social-scientific literature. Prozac-style serotonin-enhancing mood-boosters, for instance, dramatically and consistently increase the status in the social pecking-order of the animals to whom they're administered. Such drugs may even lead them to reject a subordinate role altogether. It is revealing, too, that the manifestations of euphoric mania and melancholic depression also serve as descriptions of people occupying alpha and omega status-roles respectively. Mania, unlike most mental disorders, is most common in the upper social and economic classes. It typically involves an exaggeration of behaviour associated with achieving dominant status. By contrast, depression is most common among the poor. Even in today's society, the persistence of depressive states and behaviour fosters stable hierarchies of social dominance. From the perspective of evolutionary psychology, the typical depressive syndrome is part of an adaptive coping-process. "Endogenous" depression involves the passive submission to a prolonged or uncontrollable stress. The elevated levels of cortisol and pain-relieving beta-endorphin characteristic of official clinical depression are also those which promote physiological adaptation to prolonged stressors. In the ancestral environment, depressive behaviour reduced the risk of physical damage by its tendency to reduce fighting within the group. In the post-Darwinian world, by contrast, depression simply won't exist.
So the "Brave New World" objection needs to be turned on its head. Given the correlation between depressed mood and low social status, the project of radically enriching the mood and motivation of the bulk of the population will probably leave people much less, not more, vulnerable to exploitation by a power-elite. In Brave New World, members of the populace were effectively the opiated and tranquillised dupes of the ruling authorities. Soma was a pacifying agent of social control. The consequences of genetically pre-programming happiness, however, will be very different. This is because everyday mental super-health will undermine the biological underpinnings of the dominance- and submission-relationships characteristic of our evolutionary past. More specifically, boosting the efficiency of tyrosine hydroxylase, for instance, won't just act to elevate mood. The consequently enhanced noradrenaline function in the locus coeruleus will tend to diminish subordinate behaviour. These simplistic "one neurochemical, one behaviour" stories are of course travesties of the truth, justified only on grounds of expository convenience. This doesn't challenge the essential point.
This point is that happiness, and an enhanced responsiveness to a wider
range of rewards, is potentially hugely empowering. We're eternally slaves
to the pleasure-pain axis; but a biologically enriched apparatus of pleasure
and value-creation will help people assume a greater sense of control of
their own lives. As noted, an all-action life-style fuelled by dopamine-driven
well-being contrasts with the "learned helplessness" and "behavioural despair"
characteristic of fatalists convinced that suffering is simply The Human
Predicament. Either way, we shouldn't simple-mindedly project the power-and-submission
relationships typical of early humans on the African savannah into the
indefinite future. For the genetic basis of our core repertoire of social
behaviour will first be tweaked and then drastically recoded. Too many
sci-fi romances rely on extrapolating primate dominance-rituals into the
indefinite future. That's what makes sci-fi soap operas set in one million
years time so curiously (and so spuriously) intelligible. Whereas over
the next few millennia and beyond, we'll have the chance to leave endless
re-enactments of the ritual power-plays of the ancestral environment ever
further behind.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.17 "I'd rather stay in touch with Reality than live in an escapist fantasy world."
Some people enjoy the lucky conviction they have more intimate relations with Reality than the rest of us. A robust sense of intimacy is of course all the easier if one holds an agreeably commonsensical direct realist view of perception. Unfortunately, common sense is ill-named and at variance with the neuropsychological and quantum mechanical facts. Yet even a virtual worlder, for whom an awake mind/brain can aspire only to real-time data-driven simulations, may be sensitive to the charge of wanting to live in a fool's paradise, blissed out of his head come-what-may. Better, surely, to live like a sad but wise Socrates than as a happy pig.
Happy pigs should not be despised, but Socratic intellectual heavyweights
can be happy too. In a magically transfigured environment in which all
one's fellow creatures were fabulously well, it is not clear at all why
occupying an affectively neutral or pensive state should promote greater
realism and representational fidelity. Perhaps the only way to grasp the
actual nature of the unexplored celestial chemistry that beckons is to
try becoming blissfully happy as well; and this is surely as good a reason
as any for seeking maximal comprehension.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.18 "Any creature which enjoyed perpetual bliss would no longer be me. I'm defined as much by my sorrows as my joys."
Winning £20 million on the national lottery, say, would wreak quite radical changes on most people's consciousness and sense of self-identity. It may nonetheless be suspected that the millions of punters who indulge their gambling streak are untroubled by the thought that their picking the lucky number will allow "somebody else" to enjoy the proceeds.
Philosophically, the notions of an enduring metaphysical ego, or for that
matter of so-called "relative" identity, are indeed problematic if not
incoherent. So in that sense the anxiety noted above is well-founded. Yet
in such case any anxiety over personal (non-)identity applies no less to
the psychochemical Dark Ages than to the post-Transfiguration era. One's
namesake elsewhere in space-time who fell asleep last night is neither
token nor even type-identical with the different configuration of matter
and energy which bears one's name right now. Fortunately, even if personal
identity is formally disavowed, one can normally muster the degree of altruism
necessary to promote the future well-being of one's multiple namesakes,
and likewise the namesakes and successors of one's family and friends.
If contemporary notions of personal identity are ever culturally displaced
by a different metaphysic, it may be hoped that our successors can muster
the necessary degree of altruism too.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.19 "When much of the world is still mired in poverty, hunger and disease, it is at best a flippant irrelevance to dream up hedonistic utopias. Their practice, if not aim, will be the cocooning of an already over-privileged planetary elite. We should instead concentrate on putting all our efforts into ensuring that everyone in the Third World has enough to eat, clean water supplies, a decent education and medical care and a civilised standard of living."
By most objective indices of well-being (the rates of marital breakdown, crime, suicide, clinical depression and other forms of psychiatric illness etc), the urban-industrial Western elite scores poorly compared to the materially underprivileged masses of the Third World. So the relative good fortune of the inhabitants of liberal capitalist democracies is easily overstated.
An "us and them" approach to life has its limitations. Within the next
few hundred years, the invidious distinctions of class, nationality and
race which poison the contemporary world will become redundant. On all
but the most optimistic projections, the great majority of the world's
population aren't going to achieve First World lifestyles for the foreseeable
future; but we most assuredly do have the resources to enable the whole
planetary population to be magnificently happy. If, for a start, a minute
fraction of the resources currently poured into zero-sum status-goods and
consumer fripperies were diverted to researching the development of safe,
cheap, effective mood brighteners, delayed-action designer euphoriants,
and genetically pre-programmed mental super-health, then we would all be
far better off. This is no less true of the jaded plutocrat than the impoverished
Third World peasant.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.20 "The idea of spending one's entire life consumed by whole-body-orgasmic states of hyper-crack-like intensity and euphoria is simply grotesque. It is an affront to human dignity."
Unbridled sensual bliss will be merely one
of the flavours of pleasure on the psychochemical menu, though not one
that should cause us any embarrassment. In our own time, the dignified
nature of such natural and short-lived routes to pleasure as sex is not
always readily apparent to the untutored eye either. The more conspicuous
pursuit of money, power and status characteristic of selfish DNA-driven
civilisation tends to compromise human dignity in subtler but much more
insidious ways. Champions of human dignity do not on the whole forswear
such life-style choices, and understandably so; (in)dignity is very much
in the eye of the beholder. Being made to suffer, however, is arguably
the greatest indignity of all.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.21 "The track-record of utopianism, whether romantic or allegedly scientific, is uniformly disastrous. Appalling crimes are committed on the assumption that the end justifies the means. A dystopian result is far more likely."
A "dystopia" where everyone is superlatively
happy and fulfilled is surely the ultimate misnomer. Perhaps, if one's
concept of perennial happiness still evokes images of bland and sterile
monotony, then the charge may seem reasonable. In fact, the worst coercive
excesses one can imagine, albeit somewhat implausibly, from a notional
regime of State-sponsored hedonism might stem from the imposed penal sanction
of compulsory biological euphoria - perhaps objectionable, but scarcely
a cruel (though certainly an unusual) punishment.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.22 "Genetically pre-programmed euphoria would undermine the basis of all human relationships. All this fancy verbal window-dressing about combining perpetual ecstasy with love, empathy, beauty etc is only superficial. Say, for example, some terrible physical misfortune overtakes a friend; after all, accidents can happen in even the best-run utopias. One will still be ecstatically happy: love for one's friend may indeed feel intense; but it is completely shallow if one can't grieve for a tragedy that befalls her."
By hypothesis, one's friend will be incapable of suffering; however badly mangled his or her body. Indeed s(he) will still be happy, albeit, we shall assume here, less intensely than before. Perhaps some of her favourite pleasure-cells are damaged. Let us also assume, in this scenario, that the molecular substrates of volition have long since been identified and toned up. One has chosen to blend the biochemical substrates of pleasure with those of dopaminergic "incentive" motivation rather than blissed-out satiety. If this is the case, then one will strive with all one's prodigiously augmented will-power to find means to restore one's friend to a state of maximal well-being. One will try far harder in dopaminergic overdrive than would be psychophysiologically possible if one were stuck in one's current comparatively weak-willed and ineffectual state. Thus a life of unremitting happiness doesn't entail that friendship is shallow or inauthentic; on the contrary, one will have the motivational resources to express depth of personal commitment all the more.
This is not to say that relationships won't change in many different ways
after the Transition occurs. At present, for example, friendship often
consists of offering mutual support in times of hardship and despair. In
future, it may consist of a shared celebration of life.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.23 "One big risk posed by the global species-project of The Hedonistic Imperative is that (post-)humanity will get "stuck" in a better, but perhaps still severely sub-optimal, state. Evolutionary progress, if one may be allowed to use such a term, would thereby come to an end. This is too high a price to be paid, or to run the risk of paying."
This worry shouldn't be lightly dismissed. But perhaps three points are worth making here.
First, natural selection has promoted such an abundance of dreadful states that even a severely sub-optimal (by whose criteria? - presumably not the sublimely fulfilled super-beings themselves) result would ethically be far preferable to today's status quo; and indeed preferable to any of our often hellish world's environmentally-tweaked successors.
Second, the danger of getting irreversibly stuck is still present even if genetic engineering and psychopharmacology are renounced in favour of time-honoured "peripheralist" approaches to making the world a better place. In fact, for what it's worth, psychoactive drugs potentially offer a form of "simulated annealing" [in artificial neural network-speak], enabling us to escape entrapment in local minima - though sometimes the jolt may be too uncontrollably violent and even dangerous commonly to be useful e.g. taking psychedelic agents such as lysergic acid diethylamide (LSD), ketamine or DMT.
Third, the idea that the paradise-engineering project sketched in HI would more readily lead to us getting "stuck" stems, I think, from its conflation with one or both of its two immediate intellectual antecedents of which I'm consciously aware. These are opiated-style quiescence a la Brave New World and the endless, uncontrollably orgasmic lever-pressing frenzy of a rat-/human-driven pleasure-machine. Both stereotypes are deceptive. One consequence of enhancing dopamine function in the manner stressed in this manifesto is that not merely is overall motivation deepened, but also the range of different activities one finds rewarding is increased (cf. the recent excitement over finding the D4 "novelty-loving" gene). Consequently, the likelihood of an organism, or a species, getting stuck in rut is diminished, though certainly not eliminated, by a strategy which incorporates boosting key receptor sub-types of dopamine-mediated process. It's worth noting that there is an experimentally demonstrable tendency of anti-dopaminergic mood-darkeners- and -flatteners, notably the D2-blocking major tranquillisers, to reduce incentive-motivation and novelty-seeking behaviour. They are "rut-inducers". Analogously, most of us Dark Age humans, stuck on a hedonic treadmill way down in the historical abyss, don't realise just how trapped we are.
On the other hand, there's a sense in which getting generically "stuck"
in paradise is precisely what some of us are after.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
4.24 "The eradication of suffering via genetic engineering and nanotechnology is an admirable goal. So why the disproportionate and perhaps (since so easily misinterpreted) irresponsible emphasis on mood-elevating drugs?"
Advanced genetic engineering and nanotechnological paradise-construction may yield states of conscious existence so wonderful and god-like that the notion of chemically fine-tuning them will seem absurd. What transhuman super-being would wish to contaminate the natural beauty of his or her soul-stuff with alien dirt? Yet some boring level-headedness about prospective time-scales is in order. It is true that the human genome of three-billion-odd base-pairs will be decoded within a decade. A far greater problem for intelligently encephalised paradise-production is the combinatorial explosion issue. This arises, quite inevitably, from a genotype's differential expression in differing environments. Airily invoking "genetic algorithms" and "quantum computation", for instance, is not wrong; but it tends to gloss over the formidable technical difficulties first to be overcome.
In the meantime, many people alive today will want biologically underwritten fulfilment for themselves and their loved ones. Born, tantalisingly, just prior to the Transitional era, they will have only the suspect stop-gap of enhancements to contemporary psychopharmacology to fall back on. Their access to cheap-and-cheerful paradises born of quick-and-dirty chemical fixes will, no doubt, seem dreadfully makeshift by the exalted lights of our more distant posterity. This doesn't mean that next century's pharmacotherapies should be damned with the knee-jerk invocation of "Drugs" conjured up by our own era's ill-judged recreational excesses. For one of the paradoxical effects, for instance, of a mind-healing strategy using even present-day selective serotonin reuptake blockers can be an enhanced sense of undrugged "normality" in the user. Such a sense can coincide with a biographically abnormal brightening of mood. Unacknowledged everyday states of derealisation, depersonalisation, and indeed other modes of depressive weirdness more typically associated with "bad trips" and "bad drugs", are in fact disturbingly common. Low-grade forms are frequent even in the absence of any exogenous agent to precipitate them. Moreover it's worth recalling that a subjective sense of humdrum, drug-naïve normality is itself just a chemically-induced adaptation. Neither we nor our blissful descendants need feel at all "drugged"; even if, in a sense, that's what we are; and always have been. But if we want to glimpse, rather than talk about, the naturalistic implementation of Paradise, then our generation(s) at least will need to use psychoactive tools-of-the-trade to get there.
In any case, given that so much of our very essence comprises the chemical
ingredients of our recent meals, it's not as though one's ontological integrity
as a pure spirit-being, or whatever, will be under threat from alien soul-pollutants.
The difference between a drug and a nutrient, after all, reflects little
more than the accidents of evolutionary history.
Chapter 5
5. Conclusion.
"The world of the happy is quite different
from the world of the unhappy."
(Wittgenstein)
5.0 Puppet-Masters Without Strings.
One's attitude to the proposals and predictions
of this manifesto will be largely a function of the mood in which it is
read. The judgement of our ecstatic descendants is likely to be clear.
The self-authenticating value of heavenly states, and the need to offer
them universally, will seem compelling. At the other extreme - barring
mood-darkening experiments cruel beyond belief - a significant proportion
of people diagnosed even today as (sub-)clinically depressed will welcome
the prospect of universal happiness. For an era of genetically preprogrammed
self-fulfilment seems to promise a release from their malaise. Sadly, salvation
will probably arrive too late. This pessimistic verdict has admittedly
been pieced together on the basis of anecdotal and impressionistic evidence,
not an independent study.
The greatest resistance to the prospect of real-life heaven-on-earth will most likely come from medically ill-named "euthymics". "Euthymic" mood is statistically typical of products of the present human genome. It's also a brutish parody of mature post-Darwinian mental health. To someone of this "natural" cast of mind, however, the assent of genetically-enhanced ecstatics to lifelong bliss will count for little. After all, the crack addict in the throes of an uncontrolled cocaine binge is untroubled by self-doubt either. His rational acumen and practical wisdom are seriously open to question. Likewise, any endorsement of the biological program expressed by depressives can be dismissed too. It's just a cognitive pathology consequent on their morbid state.
So we have a bit of an impasse. In what mood should this manifesto be appraised? Is there a more-or-less cognitively neutral type of affective state from which the moral worth, and/or practical advantages, of all other affective states can best be judged? When does a mere processing-bias or a cognitive filter take on a hallucinatory aspect which means that certain possibilities are intellectually closed to the victim? Could one be living one's whole life in the grip of an affective psychosis?
This discussion can all seem objectionably psychologistic. All that really counts, one will be told severely, is logical rigour of argument. Rationally, mood doesn't matter. So why extend a woolly, touchy-feely invitation to assess the biological project in a blissed-out and presumably uncritical state? Surely the general idea can be understood and appraised well enough right now.
Unfortunately it's not that simple. We are not disembodied inference-engines. Abstract platonic propositions can be accessed only by abstract platonic minds. From a naturalistic perspective, there are only spatio-temporally located thought-episodes. Their causal sequence may partially simulate, but cannot literally instantiate, some notional platonic realm of causally inert abstract inference. Anything that physically tends to optimise one's reasoning processes in the natural world should not be lightly dismissed. For in practice the affective, volitional and cognitive aspects to one's thoughts are only notionally separable. Mood and meaning interpenetrate. One's conception of the very nature of Reality itself depends, in large measure, on where one presently finds oneself in the affective spectrum. There doesn't seem to be any cognitively neutral affective state from which all the others can be judged.
Sadly, medical science cannot hope to resolve the question of Ideal Mental States. Which of an organism's psychophysical processes should be classified as pathological would seem very much a conventional - though not arbitrary - matter of culture, social negotiation and personal prejudice. Mental health and soundness of judgement will tend to be defined, in part, by contemporaneous statistical norms. And if the average hedonic base-line of the species were to be ratcheted upwards substantially via germ-line "paradise-genes", then the nominal good health of one age could be regarded as the profound psychopathology of a more enlightened era. Perhaps we're all very sick indeed.
So if one finds oneself viscerally hostile to the idea of universal happiness, and if by contemporary standards one falls within the statistically normal range in one's emotional repertoire, then just how seriously should one contemplate the following possibility. We are today the victims of what subsequent and better-informed ages will reckon an atavistic mood disorder. It is a historical condition no less epistemically defective than are dream-psychoses from the perspective of the waking state.
Is this worry just the product of idle scepticism? Given the cognitive
inaccessibility of most of the generically ecstatic states alluded to here,
perhaps one wouldn't know if one were so afflicted. After all, damaged
and disfigured minds may have limited self-insight. Nor would one necessarily
have the conceptual resources even to grasp what was at stake if one suffered
from such a deficiency. Pure, genetically "unearned" bliss of even the
mildest flavour militated against the inclusive fitness of one's genes
in the past. Happy freaks of nature got eaten or outbred. Is one's potential
unease, if not revulsion, at the prospect of paradise an incidental cultural
by-product of natural selection? Or has selection pressure ensured that
one is genetically predisposed to be biased against the idea of enduring
bliss in the first instance?
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
5.1 Could Life Really Have A Happy Ending?
It's time to take stock. Most of the more
exotic delights sketched out here will probably never be enjoyed by the
reader. They require a level of theoretical understanding and biomedical
finesse that we simply do not yet command. Many of the practical difficulties
to be overcome have been skated over with the kind of blithe disregard
for detail that only an ignorance of nitty-gritty technical complexities
can bestow. If, however, a single major government or a segment of the
global power elite were to sanction the necessary research and development,
then sustainable chemically-underwritten euphoria is quite tantalisingly
accessible, even now, to those of us who want it as an option. Better still,
germ-line therapy can then turn lifelong ecstatic well-being into the hereditary
post-human condition.
Admittedly, in the absence of concerted action to promote at least a skeletal world-wide counterpart to the national welfare-state, then the physical plight of much of the world's population means that any instant dash to raw, unempathetic euphoria on the part of a materially privileged minority would be premature. It would be selfish in the extreme - though not necessarily more so than the life-styles of competitive individualism, rampant consumerism and incompetent recreational drug-abuse that many of us live at present. Yet one of the providential blessings of the blueprint for biological redemption is that - with a decent bit of planning - it can supplant the old, quasi-zero-sum approach to the allocation of life's rewards. If properly managed, the route to felicific enlightenment ahead will soon be open to all. It needn't be the preserve of the affluent few. Nor need it be the reward of just the morally good and "deserving". In fact with a combination of cognitive-enhancers and time-delayed euphoriants, there is no reason why the old age of the sympathetic reader shouldn't herald, not a slow, spirit-sapping decline, but a period of beautiful experiences and glorious self-fulfilment. It can be a time immeasurably richer than anything (s)he has enjoyed before.
Many people will have internalised too many of the life-impoverishing hang-ups
of humanity's biological past to contemplate playing a pioneering role
and participating in the era ahead; just as misplaced prudery prevents
many people from enjoying sex. But life, one may think, should climax in
an orgasmic celebration of being, not a fatalistic world-weary fade-out.
The Ministry of Truth Home Page