That Virtue May Be Taught
1. Men deliberate and dispute variously concerning virtue, whether
prudence and justice and the right ordering of one's life can be taught. Moreover, we
marvel that the works of orators, shipmasters, musicians, carpenters, and husbandmen are
infinite in number, while good men are only a name, and are talked like centaurs, giants,
and the Cyclops, and that for any virtuous action that is sincere and unblamable, and
manners that are without any touch and mixture of bad passions and affections, they are
not to be found; but if Nature of its own accord should produce any thing good and
excellent, so many things of a foreign mix with it (just as wild and impure productions
with generous fruit) that the good is scarce discernable. Men learn to sing, dance, and
read, and to be skilful in husbandry and good horsemanship; they learn how to put on their
shoes and their garments; they have those that teach them how to fill wine, and to dress
and cook their meat; and none of these things can be done as they ought, unless they be
instructed how to do them. And will ye say, O foolish men! That the skill of ordering
one's life well (for the sake of which are all the rest) is not to be taught, but to come
to its own accord, without reason and without art?
2. Why do we, by asserting that virtue is not to be taught, make it a
thing that does not at all exist? For if by its being learned it is produced, he that
hinders its being learned destroys it. And no, as Plato (Clitophon 407C) says, we never
heard that because of a blunder in metre in a lyric song, therefore one brother made war
against another, nor that it put friends at variance, nor that cities hereupon were at
such enmity that they did to one another and suffered one from another the extremist
injuries. Nor can any one tell us of a sedition raised in a city about the right accenting
or pronouncing of a word, --as whether we are to say Telci`nas or T'elcinas,
-- nor that a difference arose in a family betwixt man and wife about the woof and the
warp in cloth. Yet none will go about to weave in a loom or to handle a book or a harp,
unless he has first been taught, though no great harm will follow if he did, but only the
fear of making himself ridiculous (for, as Heraclitus says, it is a piece of discretion to
conceal one's ignorance); and yet a man without instruction presumes himself able to order
a family, a wife, or a commonwealth, and to govern very well. Diogenes, seeing a youth
devouring his victuals greedily, gave his tutor a box on the ear, and that deservedly, as
judging it the fault of him that had not taught, not of him that had not learned better
manners. And what? is it necessary to being to learn from a boy how to eat and drink
handsomely in company, as Aristophanes expresses it,--
Not to devour their meat in
haste, nor giggle,
Nor awkwardly their feet across to wriggle.
(Nub. 983)
and yet men are fit to enter into the fellowship of a family, city, married estate,
private conversation, or public office, and to manage it without blame, without any
previous instruction concerning good behavior in conversations?
When one asked Aristippus this question, What, are you everywhere? he
laughed and said, I throw away the fare of the waterman, if I am everywhere. And why canst
not thou also answer, that the salary given to tutors is thrown away and lost, if none are
the better for their discipline and instruction. But, as nurses shape and form the body of
a child with their hands, so these masters, when the nurses have done with them, first
receive them into their charge, in order to the forming of their manners and directing
their steps into the first tracks of virtue. To which purpose the Lacedaemonian, that was
asked what good he did to the child of whom he had the charge, answered well: I make good
and honest things pleasant to children. These masters also teach them to bend down their
heads as they go along, to touch salt fish with one finger only, but fresh fish, bread,
and flesh with two; thus to scratch themselves, and thus to tuck up their garments.
3. Now he that says that the art of physic may be proper for a tetter
or a whitlow, but not to be made use of for a pleurisy, a fever, or a frenzy, in what does
he differ from him that should say that it is fit there should be schools, and discourses,
and precepts, to teach trifling and childish things, but that all skill in greater and
more many things comes from use without art and from accidental opportunity? For as he
would be ridiculous who should say, that one who never learned to row ought not to lay
hand on the oar, but that he might guide the helm who was never taught it; so is he that
gives leave for men to be instructed in other arts, but not in virtue. He seems to be
quite contrary to the practice of the Scythians, who, as Herodotus ( IV.2) tells us, put
out their servants' eyes, to prevent them from running away; but he puts the eye of reason
into these base and slavish arts, and plucks it from virtue. But the general Iphicrates --
when Callias, the son of Charbrias, asked him, What art thou? Art thou an archer or a
targeteer, a trooper or a foot-soldier? -- answered well, I am none of all these, but one
that commands them all. He therefore would be ridiculous that should day that the skill of
drawing a bow, of handling arms, of throwing with a sling, and of good horsemanship, might
indeed be taught, but the skill of commanding and leading an army came as it happened, one
knew not how. And would not he be still more ridiculous who should say that prudence only
could not be taught, without which all those arts are useless and unprofitable? When she
is the governess, ranking all things in due place and order, every thing is assigned to
become useful; for instance, how ungraceful would a feast be, though all concerned were
skilful and enough practiced in cookery, in dressing and serving up the meat, and in
filling the wine as they ought, if all things were not well disposed and ordered among
those that waited at the table?