selections from an essay from envirolink titled,"beyond might makes right", about animal rights and ethics.
The reason given most often for claiming that other animals should
not have rights is that they are not human. However, "human" is only
an arbitrary label without any moral relevance in and of itself.
In the past, the term "human" was used to refer only to light-skinned
people of European descent. Given that the definition of "human"
can change, one cannot simply say that an individual has rights
because that individual is "human" while another individual has no
rights because that individual is not "human."
Differences in degree
Many say that humans deserve rights while other beings do not
because humans have a greater level of certain characteristics than
other animals: humans are more intelligent, creative, aware,
technologically advanced, dominant, able to use language, able to
enter into contracts, able to make moral choices, etc. Thus, humans
deserve rights because they have a greater degree of these
characteristics.
This argument of degrees has two problems:
Instead of thinking that rights are granted to an entire group, a
more accurate view of rights is that they are granted to
individuals, because it is individuals, not groups, who are
capable of suffering and dying. To say, "all individuals in the
group `human' have the right not to be killed" has meaning,
but to say "the group `human' has the right not to be killed"
has no meaning.
Not all humans possess these characteristics to a greater
degree than all other non-humans. There are non- humans
who are more intelligent, creative, aware, dominant,
technologically advanced (in reference to tool making), and
able to use language, than some humans; many animals are at
least equal to many humans in their ability to enter into
contracts or act morally. Examples would be a chimpanzee
compared to a human infant or a severely mentally
handicapped person. If rights were granted at a certain level
of a characteristic such as those listed, the more intelligent
(creative, etc.) animals would have rights while the less
intelligent (creative, etc.) humans would not.
Despite this, many people believe that all humans, regardless of their
relative level of intelligence, creativity, etc. should have rights, while
other animals should not. These people try to include all humans
while excluding all other animals in one of several ways.
Potential characteristics
Some say the humans who are surpassed by some animals in a
certain characteristic have rights because they have a greater
potential for these characteristics than do other animals.
Again, this argument is not true of all humans. For example, humans
who have had portions of their brains irreparably destroyed,
although still able to function to a degree, have no potential for
obtaining the intelligence level of a chimpanzee. Yet most people
would say that an injury or disease which causes brain damage does
not rob that individual of their rights.
Value to others
Another rationale is that even though infants cannot enter into moral
contracts, they should be granted rights because they are valued by
other humans (their parents, for instance) who can enter into
contracts. By this argument, infants themselves do not possess any
inherent rights, but receive them only if valued by an adult human.
At the same time, being valued by an adult human does not grant
rights to pigs, parakeets, pet rocks, or Porsches. This is inconsistent:
either one is granted rights by being valued by an adult human, and
thus everything valued by an adult human has rights, or there must be
a different criteria for granting rights.
People who believe that rights are granted to infants because of their
value to an adult human would have to admit that infants who are not
valued by other humans could be used in medical research. Indeed,
this would be morally imperative in order to benefit infants who are
valued by others. Most people would contend, however, that even
unvalued orphans have rights. Therefore, rights must be based on
other criteria.
Biological rights
If only individuals of the group now defined as "human" have rights
regardless of their level of certain characteristics, on what basis are
chimpanzees, pigs, elephants, dogs, cats, etc., excluded from the
group to which all humans belong?
One answer is that humans have rights because they belong to the
species Homo Sapiens. In other words, a chimpanzee may very well
be as intelligent (or creative, etc.) as some humans, but chimpanzees
do not have rights because they are not members of the biologically
defined rights-bearing species, Homo Sapiens.
Supposing that it is possible to come up with a genetic definition of
Homo Sapiens that includes most individuals our society currently
considers "human" and excludes all individuals our society currently
does not consider "human," the questions then become:
Why should rights be deserved solely on the basis of a certain
sequence of genes?
If rights should be based on genes, why should the line be
drawn at the species level? And why at Homo Sapiens? Why
shouldn't the line be drawn at race, order, phylum, or
kingdom?
Among the genes that determine one's eye color, etc., which
gene is it that confers rights?
A thoughtful person might find having their rights (or lack thereof)
determined by a sequence of molecules to be a bit absurd. It is no
better than basing rights on the pigmentation of one's skin (which is
also determined by the individual's genetic code).
The law
Some would argue that while infants and the mentally handicapped
deserve rights, other animals don't because the current law grants
legal rights to infants and the mentally handicapped. However, these
people are ignoring the fact that whoever has legal rights is
determined merely by the opinion of today's legislators. The law
changes as people's opinions or political motivations change.
Politicians decide who they think should have rights and make laws
accordingly, not vice-versa. Though the law changes over time, the
moral status of beings - whether a being has inherent rights, such as
the right to non-exploitation - does not. For example, minorities in
the United States did not change when the law decided to include
them.
Ability to understand abstract concepts
It has been argued that non-humans do not deserve rights because
they cannot understand abstract concepts. An example is the
contention that pigs do not understand death, so there is no moral
reason not to take a pig's life.
Anyone who has observed pigs in a slaughterhouse would find it
difficult not to conclude that pigs understand death to the extent that
they are in great terror when confronted with it. Indeed, most
animals act as though they have a functional idea of what death is.
They fight to stay alive and can tell when another of their own is
dead. What more do humans know about death that is morally
relevant? Indeed, many animals have a greater grasp of death,
self-preservation, and other concepts than do infants and the
mentally impaired.
The Golden Rule
In the past, humans may have respected each other's rights in order
to survive without constant violence, and many people still function
on this level. Yet over time, the more civilized people have evolved a
moral system that grants rights based not just on self-protection, but
on the Golden Rule - treat your neighbor as you would like to be
treated. We know that we want to stay alive, do not wish to suffer,
etc., and we assume others like us have the same desires. Being
capable of looking beyond our own individual interests, we apply
the Golden Rule even to people who could not harm us.
How much like us does a being have to be before we include them
under the Golden Rule? At one time, women were not enough like
the men who held power to be granted many rights. Neither were
minorities in the United States and other societies. Even though the
circle has expanded to include these individuals in the United States,
today other animals are still not considered sufficiently like us for the
majority of people to treat these animals our neighbors under the
Golden Rule.
If they looked like us ...
Searching for some characteristic to justify granting all humans rights
while denying rights to all other animals is futile. A moral system
based on any of the characteristics discussed so far would either
include many species of non-human animals or exclude infants and
some mentally handicapped.
While the term "human" seems defining, and is even used here for
the convenience of easy communication, it is an ambiguous, morally
meaningless label. The question remains: where does one draw the
line? A difference of appearance is a matter of degree as well as
ethically irrelevant - outward physical attributes have no relationship
to whether a being or object should be granted rights or could even
appreciate them. A human-looking mannequin has no more need or
desire for rights than a rock or a log. However, as when race was
the dividing line for rights, the dividing line for most people is still
looks - if the animals we eat and use in experimentation looked like
us, they would be granted rights and protected from exploitation.
Suffering
To have a consistent moral philosophy, a characteristic must be
found that not only allows for the inclusion of all humans, but also
distinguishes between a wax dummy and an infant. This
rights-granting characteristic must be morally relevant. The only
characteristic that simply and consistently meets these requirements
is the capacity for suffering.
As Jeremy Bentham, head of the Department of Jurisprudence at
Oxford University during the 19th Century said in reference to his
belief that animals should be granted rights, "The question is not,
`Can they reason?' nor, `Can they talk?' But rather, `Can they
suffer?'"
If a being cannot suffer, then it does not matter to that being what
happens to it. For example, some computers have an intelligence (in
some ways greater than any human), but these machines do not care
whether they are turned off, harmed, or even destroyed.
On the other hand, if a being is sentient - able to experience pleasure
and pain - then it does matter to that being what happens to it.
Irrespective of intelligence, language, etc., a sentient being has
interests in its existence - at the least, to avoid pain and to stay alive
- and any complete moral philosophy cannot ignore these concerns.
Animals don't feel pain
Historically, many philosophers and scientists ended any discussion
of ethics and animals by stating that animals cannot feel pain. That
this idea is still held by people today is what prompted noted
scientist and Pulitzer-prize winner, Dr. Carl Sagan, along with Dr.
Ann Druyan, to write in their book, Shadows of Forgotten
Ancestors:
Humans - who enslave, castrate, experiment on, and fillet other
animals - have had an understandable penchant for pretending that
animals do not feel pain. A sharp distinction between humans and
`animals' is essential if we are to bend them to our will, make them
work for us, wear them, eat them - without any disquieting tinges of
guilt or regret.
It is unseemly of us, who often behave so unfeelingly toward other
animals, to contend that only humans can suffer. The behavior of
other animals renders such pretensions specious. They are just too
much like us.
The nervous systems of all vertebrate animals, including humans,
operate in the same manner. All these animals are capable of feeling
pain and fear, which has led many researchers to use other animals
in "pain research." Indeed, most people understand that animals are
capable of suffering, and oppose inflicting "unnecessary" suffering on
them.
Other animals also have an active desire to live, and the act of
depriving them of life or freedom is harming them in many of the
same ways a human is harmed when deprived of life or freedom.
Animals show us they value their lives and that they want to stay
alive by their struggles against adversity, threats, and slaughter.
While some animals do not always make the best decisions in order
to stay alive, and some even appear to commit suicide, the same can
be said of some humans to whom we grant rights.
There are those who still believe that there is no evidence that
animals value their lives because they have not said so in English or
another human language. These people must admit, however, that
the same is true of human infants.
Some would say having a God-given soul is what gives one rights.
However, like the label "human," those in power have historically
denied souls to women and other groups of individuals. Even if God
did grant souls to humans while not to other animals, the animals
have the capacity to feel pain and the desire to live. It would require
a cruel God to create beings with these capacities whose only
purpose was to suffer at the hands of humans. As Nobel Laureate
Romain Rolland has written:
To one whose mind is free, there is something more intolerable in the
suffering of animals then in the suffering of men. For with the latter, it
is at least admitted that suffering is evil and the man who causes it is
a criminal. But thousands of animals are uselessly butchered every
day without a shadow of remorse. It cries vengeance upon all the
human race. If God exists and tolerates it, it cries vengeance upon
God. If there exists a good God, then even the most humble of living
things must be saved. If God is good only to the strong, if there is no
justice for the weak and lowly, for the poor creatures who are
offered up as a sacrifice to humanity, then there is no such thing as
goodness, no such thing as justice....
Secularist's faith
While many people grant rights to some beings and not to others
based only on the majority interpretation of their individual religious
doctrine, secularists who accept that all humans have rights yet
reject the idea that any non- human animals have rights must also be
basing their moral code on faith. As there is no objective criteria for
discriminating all humans from all other animals, these secularists
must believe in an intangible, unmeasurable, and undefinable
"humanness" that somehow confers rights.
Eskimos
Some contend that since some people, such as Eskimos, must kill
animals to survive, killing animals is acceptable. This excuse raises
the hypothetical question of if Eskimos, or another group, "had" to
kill other Homo Sapiens to survive, would it be morally acceptable
to deny rights to Homo Sapiens?
Even if Eskimos would starve to death if they did not kill other
animals, that is not the case for people in our society who kill and
eat animals out of habit and taste. In today's world, eating animals is
not a case of survival.
Furthermore, if everyone were to base their actions and morality on
what Eskimos do, then vivisection and factory farming would have
to be abolished, since the Eskimos do neither. Each one of us could
no longer pay someone to raise and murder animals to satisfy our
taste for flesh, but would instead have to hunt and kill for our own
meals.
Even though rights can only be granted consistently and justly on the
basis of the capacity to suffer and not on the ability to make moral
choices, there is ample evidence that many animals can and do make
moral choices, often to the shame of rights-bearing and "superior"
humans. Carl Sagan and Ann Druyan, in their book Shadows of
Forgotten Ancestors, relate the following:
In the annals of primate ethics, there are some accounts that have
the ring of parable. In a laboratory setting, macaques were fed if
they were willing to pull a chain and electrically shock an unrelated
macaque whose agony was in plain view through a one-way mirror.
Otherwise, they starved.
After learning the ropes, the monkeys
frequently refused to pull the chain; in one experiment only 13%
would do so - 87% preferred to go hungry. One macaque went
without food for nearly two weeks rather than hurt its fellow.
Macaques who had themselves been shocked in previous
experiments were even less willing to pull the chain. The relative
social status or gender of the macaques had little bearing on their
reluctance to hurt others.
If asked to choose between the human experimenters offering the
macaques this Faustian bargain and the macaques themselves -
suffering from real hunger rather than causing pain to others - our
own moral sympathies do not lie with the scientists. But their
experiments permit us to glimpse in non-humans a saintly willingness
to make sacrifices in order to save others - even those who are not
close kin. By conventional human standards, these macaques - who
have never gone to Sunday school, never heard of the Ten
Commandments, never squirmed through a single junior high school
civics lesson - seem exemplary in their moral grounding and their
courageous resistance to evil. Among these macaques, at least in this
case, heroism is the norm. If the circumstances were reversed, and
captive humans were offered the same deal by macaque scientists,
would we do as well? (Especially when there is an authority figure
urging us to administer the electric shocks, we humans are
disturbingly willing to cause pain - and for a reward much more
paltry than food is for a starving macaque [cf. Stanley Milgram,
Obedience to Authority: An Experimental Overview].) In human
history there are a precious few whose memory we revere because
they knowingly sacrificed themselves for others. For each of them,
there are multitudes who did nothing.
If animals can feel pain as humans can, and desire to live as humans
do, how can they not be granted similar respect? As moral beings,
how can we justify our continued exploitation of them? We must
stand up against the idea that might makes right. We must question
the status quo which allows the unquestioned infliction of so much
suffering. We must act from our own ethics, rather than blindly
follow what we are told.
Discussing the macaque monkeys who chose to starve rather than
inflict pain on another, Drs. Sagan and Druyan conclude, "Might we
have a more optimistic view of the human future if we were sure our
ethics were up to their standards?"
thanks to envirolink...
table of contents