READING QUESTIONS

Philosophy 1

 


 

Set I

Set II

Set III

Set IV

Set V

Set VI

Set VII

Set VIII

Set IX

Set X

Set XI

Set XII

Set XIII

Set XIV

Set XV

Set XVI

Set XVII

 


 

Reading Questions

Set I

 

“Good Reasoning”

Applying Ethics, pp. 49-70

 

1.                  What two sorts of statements comprise an Argument? [See p. 50]

2.                  What is the purpose of an argument? [See p. 50]

3.                  What two tests must A Good Argument (or, as the author puts it, a “sound” argument) pass? [See p. 51] (You might want to think, here, about the relation of what the author calls “validity” to what we will call “the inference test.”)

4.                  What is a counter-example to an argument, and what is a counter-example to an argument supposed to show? [See pp. 51-52] Provide a counter-example to the following argument:

                        1          If Maria traveled on a plane, then she took a trip.

                        2          Maria did not travel on a plane.

                        3          Therefore, Maria did not take a trip.

[Hint: Think of some things other than a plane on which Maria might have traveled and still have taken a trip. If you can think of any, then you have a counter-example to the above argument.]

5.                  What two “subtasks” are involved in evaluating an argument? [See p. 55]

6.                  Define these other important terms:

                        The Premise Test

                        The Inference Test

                        Premise

                        Conclusion

                        Inference

                        A Bad Argument

 

Return to the top of the page

 


 

Reading Questions

Set II

 

James Rachels, “The Challenge of Cultural Relativism”

Reason & Responsibility, pages 616-623

 

1.                  What “recurring theme” is suggested by Rachels’ early examples, which include the example of the Callatians and the example of the Eskimos? [p. 617]

2.                  What is Cultural Relativism? [p. 618]

3.                  What argumentative strategy do cultural relativists employ? [p. 618]

4.                  What is a Sound Argument? [See page 619 for Rachels’ use of this terminology.] Why does Rachels think that the Cultural Difference Argument is not a sound argument? Do you agree with Rachels’ assessment of the argument? Why, or why not?

5.                  What is a Fallacious Argument? [See page 619 for Rachels’ use of this terminology.]

6.                  According to Rachels, what are some of the consequences of taking cultural relativism seriously? [pp. 619-620] He suggests that these consequences might be bad enough to lead one to reject cultural relativism. Do you agree that it is reasonable to reject cultural relativism because it has these consequences? Why, or why not?

7.                  Rachels claims that “cultures do not differ [in their views of right and wrong] nearly as much as it appears” (620). How might his arguments in favor of this claim relate to the Cultural Differences Argument?

8.                  On page 622, Rachels lists the “mistakes” made by cultural relativism. What are these mistakes? He goes on to say that these mistakes “add up to a pretty thorough repudiation of the theory” (622). Do you agree with him? Why, or why not?

9.                  According to Rachels, what is the first lesson that we should learn from cultural relativism? [pp. 622-623]

10.              According to Rachels, what is the second lesson that we should learn from cultural relativism? [p. 623]

11.              If you’re inclined toward cultural relativism, can you think of any of your own arguments that will support that position? If you’re not inclined toward cultural relativism, can you think of any of your own arguments against that position?

 

Return to the top of the page

 


 

Reading Questions

Set III

 

James Rachels, “Ethical Egoism”

Reason & Responsibility, pages 559-566

 

1.                  What, according to Rachels, is the “common-sense view” of, or the “common-sense assumption” about, which actions we should and should not perform? [p. 560]

2.                  What is Ethical Egoism? [p. 560]

3.                  What does the word ‘Normative’ mean [See page 560 for Rachels’ use of this word.] {Hint: The word ‘normative’ is closely connected to the word ‘norm.’}

4.                  What exactly is the first argument for ethical egoism? [p. 561]

5.                  What, according to Rachels, is the first defect in the first argument for ethical egoism? [p. 561]

6.                  What, according to Rachels, is the “more serious defect” in the first argument for ethical egoism? [p. 561] Do you agree with Rachels that this is a defect in the argument? Why, or why not?

7.                  What exactly is the second argument for ethical egoism? [pp. 561-562]

8.                  What, according to Rachels, is the problem with the second argument for ethical egoism? [p. 562] Do you agree with Rachels that this is a problem with the argument? Why, or why not?

9.                  What is “a revisionist moral philosophy”? [p. 562]

10.              What exactly is the third argument for ethical egoism? [pp. 562-563]

11.              What, according to Rachels, is the first serious objection to the third argument for ethical egoism? [p. 563] Do you agree with Rachels that this is a defect in the argument? Why, or why not?

12.              What, according to Rachels, is the second serious objection to the third argument for ethical egoism? [p. 563] Do you agree with Rachels that this is a defect in the argument? Why, or why not?

13.              What is Kurt Baier’s objection to ethical egoism? According to Rachels, how might the ethical egoist respond to Baier’s objection? [p. 564] Can you think of any ways in which Baier might in turn respond to the ethical egoist?

14.              What is the second alleged refutation of ethical egoism? What, according to Rachels, is wrong with this alleged refutation? [pp. 564-565]

15.              What general principle stands in the way of a defense of, say, racism? [p. 565]

16.              Why, according to Rachels, is racism “an arbitrary doctrine”? [p. 566]

17.              Rachels claims that “Ethical Egoism is an arbitrary doctrine, in the same way that racism is arbitrary” (566). Do you agree with him? Why, or why not? (If you do not agree with him, then you’ll need to show why his argument – in the second column of page 544 – is not a good one.)

18.              If you’re inclined toward ethical egoism, can you think of any of your own arguments that will support that position? If you’re not inclined toward ethical egoism, can you think of any of your own arguments against that position?

 

Return to the top of the page

 


 

Reading Questions

Set IV

 

John Stuart Mill, “Utilitarianism”

Reason & Responsibility, pages 694-707

 

1.                  What does ‘a priori’ mean? Is a priori reasoning associated with the intuitive or with the inductive school of ethics? [p. 695]

2.                  What “universal first principle” does Kant propose? [p. 696]

3.                  What does “every [utilitarian] writer from Epicurus to Bentham” mean by ‘utility’? [p. 697]

4.                  “The creed which accepts as the foundation of morals Utility, or the Greatest-Happiness Principle, holds” something. What do they hold? [p. 697]

5.                  What, for Mill, does ‘happiness’ mean? What does ‘unhappiness’ mean? [p. 697]

6.                  Given all that Mill has said so far, try to define Utilitarianism in your own words.

7.                  What, according to Mill, are “the only things desirable as ends”? [p. 697]

8.                  Mill says that “some kinds of pleasure are more desirable and more valuable than others” (698). According to Mill, which kinds of pleasure are more desirable and more valuable than “pleasures … of mere sensation”? Do you agree with Mill here? Why, or why not?

9.                  What, according to Mill, makes one pleasure more desirable than another? [p. 698]

10.              According to Mill, why do people sometimes choose lower pleasures over higher ones? [p. 699]

11.              According to Mill, is the utilitarian standard concerned with “the agent’s own greatest happiness” or with “the greatest amount of happiness altogether”? [pp. 699-700] Given your answer, do you think that utilitarianism is an egoist theory or a non-egoist one?

12.              Some object to utilitarianism on the grounds that happiness is unattainable. How does Mill respond to this objection? [pp. 700-702]

13.              Explain a few of the other objections to utilitarianism. Then explain how Mill responds to those objections. [pp. 702-707]

14.              If you’re inclined toward utilitarianism, can you think of any of your own arguments that will support that position? If you’re not inclined toward utilitarianism, can you think of any of your own arguments against that position?

 

Return to the top of the page

 


 

Reading Questions

Set V

 

Immanuel Kant, “The Good Will & The Categorical Imperative”

Reason & Responsibility, pages 679-694

 

1.                  What do you think Kant means by “a good will”? [p. 679]

2.                  Why, according to Kant, aren’t “[m]oderation in affects and passions, self-control, and calm reflection” (680) good without qualification?

3.                  In the second column of page 680, Kant argues for the claim that happiness isn’t “the proper end.” What’s his argument for that claim?

4.                  What, according to Kant, is “the true vocation of reason”? [p. 681]

5.                  Kant claims that the good will need not be “the sole and complete good, but it must still be the highest good and the condition of every other” (681). How does this compare with the utilitarian hierarchy of goods?

6.                  What is the example of duty supposed to show? [p. 681]

7.                  According to Kant, what are the only sorts of actions that have “moral import” or “moral worth”? [pp. 682-683]

8.                  What is a Maxim? [See page 683 for Kant’s use of this terminology.]

9.                  Kant asks, “[M]ay I, when hard pressed, make a promise with the intention not to keep it?” How does he answer this question? Why does he provide that answer? [pp. 683-684]

10.              What is an Imperative?

11.              What is a hypothetical imperative? [p. 685]

12.              What is a categorical imperative? [p. 685]

13.              What purpose do all rational beings have “by a natural necessity”? Is the imperative concerning happiness a hypothetical one or a categorical one? [p. 686]

14.              What does empirical mean? [See page 687 for Kant’s use of this terminology.]

15.              Why does Kant say that “imperatives of prudence cannot, to speak precisely, command at all”? [p. 687]

16.              Why does Kant say that “the categorical imperative alone has the tenor of a practical law”? [p. 688]

17.              What is The Categorical Imperative? [p. 689]

18.              Kant also states the categorical imperative in another way, as “the universal imperative of duty” (689). What is the universal imperative of duty, and how does it relate to the categorical imperative? (Are those two imperatives identical? If not, what are the differences between them? Are those differences substantial, or are they trivial?)

19.              Kant provides four examples of the categorical imperative at work. [pp. 689-670] Do you agree with his treatment of these cases? Why, or why not?

20.              According to Kant, what is it that “exists as an end in itself, not merely as a means to be used by this or that will at its discretion”? [p. 692]

21.              What is the “practical imperative”? [p. 693] How does it compare to the categorical imperative and to the universal imperative of duty?

 

Return to the top of the page

 


 

Reading Questions

Set VI

 

Peter Singer, “Famine, Affluence, and Morality”

Reason & Responsibility, pages 708-715

 

1.                  With what assumption does Singer begin? [p. 709] Can you think of any reason to question that assumption?

2.                  What is Singer’s “next point”? [p. 709]

3.                  How, according to Singer, would “our lives, our society, and our world … be fundamentally changed” if we were to act upon his principle? [p. 709]

4.                  Singer says, “The outcome of [his] argument is that our traditional moral categories are upset” (711). In what way or ways will our traditional moral categories be upset? [p. 711] Given your answers to these questions, do you think that Singer’s moral theory is a revisionist moral theory? (See question 9 under Rachels’ “Ethical Egoism.”) Why, or why not?

5.                  What is a Supererogatory act? [p. 711]

6.                  In your own words, explain the first objection that Singer notes “to the position [he has] taken.” [p. 712]

7.                  What is the “second objection to [Singer’s] attack on the present distinction between duty and charity”? [pp. 712-713] How does Singer respond to this objection?

8.                  On pages 713-715, Singer provides two arguments for the claim that we have no obligation to do anything to prevent famine. Explain in your own words each of these arguments, and then explain Singer’s response to each argument. Can you think of ways in which Singer’s responses might be ineffective?

 

Return to the top of the page

 


 

Reading Questions

Set VII

 

Onora O’Neill, “Kantian Approaches to Some Famine Problems”

Reason & Responsibility, pages 716-722

 

1.                  What, according to O’Neill’s reading of Kant, does it mean to “use someone as a mere means”? [p. 717]

2.                  What, according to O’Neill’s reading of Kant, is required if we are to “treat someone as an end in him or herself”? [p. 718]

3.                  Why, according to O’Neill, might Kant’s moral theory “have little to say about famine problems”? [p. 718]

4.                  Why does Kant’s moral theory prohibit people from cheating when they are in famine-stricken populations with a rationing scheme? [p. 719]

5.                  What is the second thing that Kantian principles require in famine situations? [p. 719]

6.                  Does Kant’s moral theory allow for a distinction between “one’s personal responsibilities” and “one’s role responsibilities”? Why, or why not? [p. 720]

7.                  What are the “grounds of duties of beneficence”? [p. 721]

 

Return to the top of the page

 


 

Reading Questions

Set VIII

 

René Descartes, “Meditations on First Philosophy”

 

1.                  What does Descartes find doubtful at the very beginning of Meditation I? [151]

2.                  According to Descartes, what reason justifies his rejecting all of his doubtful beliefs? [151-2]

3.                  How has Descartes learned “[a]ll that up to the present time [he has] accepted as most true and certain”? [152]

4.                  Why does Descartes doubt his senses with regard to “things which are hardly perceptible, or very far away”? [152]

5.                  It seems to Descartes that he “cannot reasonably have any doubt” about some things. What are some of the examples that he gives? [152]

6.                  As it turns out, though, Descartes discovers that he can doubt these things. Why does he believe that he can doubt them? [152]

7.                  Descartes then suggests that “whether [he is] awake or asleep, two and three together always form five” (153). Nevertheless, he thinks that he can doubt this, too. Why does he believe that he can doubt mathematical and geometrical truths? [153-4]

 

Return to the top of the page

 


 

Reading Questions

Set IX

 

Introduction to Part IV: Determinism, Free Will, and Responsibility (pages 410-414)

 

1.                  What is Compatibilism? [412]

2.                  What is Libertarianism? [413]

3.                  What is Determinism (a.k.a. hard determinism)? [410, 413]

 

Paul Holbach, “The Illusion of Free Will”

 

4.                  What, according to Holbach, is the will? By what is the will “necessarily determined”? [417]

5.                  Holbach compares the human will (or the brain) to a bowl. Explain the comparison. [417] Do you think that the comparison is a good one? Why, or why not?

6.                  What is a primum mobile? [418]

7.                  Why, according to Holbach, have philosophers erred “on the free agency of man”? [418]

8.                  According to Holbach, are “the actions of man” ever free? [418] Why does he answer this question as he does?

9.                  At the bottom of the second column of page 418, Holbach provides an argument for free will. Explain this argument, and then explain Holbach’s response to it.

10.              At the bottom of the first column of page 419, Holbach defines “free agency.” How does he define “free agency”? What does he have to say in opposition to those who think that we are free agents? [419]

11.              Why, according to Holbach, do we suppose ourselves to be free agents? [420]

12.              What, according to Holbach, would we need to perceive in order to “perceive that all [our] actions [are] necessary”? [420]

 

Return to the top of the page

 


 

Reading Questions

Set X

 

A. J. Ayer, “Freedom and Necessity”

 

1.                  How, according to Ayer, are free will and moral responsibility connected? [430]

2.                  Describe the “apparent conflict” that Ayer recognizes. [430]

3.                  Ayer claims that some events might not have causes. What is his argument for this claim? [430-1]

4.                  Why, according to Ayer, might someone think that we will one day be able very precisely to forecast human behavior? [431]

5.                  What about human behavior does “the moralist” wish to imply? What doesn’t she wish to imply? [431-2]

6.                  The determinist has an argument that will serve as a response to the moralist. What is that argument? [Ayer provides the argument in the first full paragraph of the first column of page 432.]

7.                  What, according to Ayer, must we do “if we are to retain this idea of moral responsibility”? [432]

8.                  According to Ayer, with what is freedom to be contrasted? [433]

9.                  What shall Ayer try to show? [432]

10.              In what circumstances can Ayer legitimately be said to be constrained? [432]

11.              From the end of page 433 to the beginning of page 434, Ayer seems to be presenting an argument that is similar to an argument of Holbach’s. How does Ayer respond to that argument? [434] Do you think that his response is a good one? Why, or why not?

12.              What is a tautology? [See page 434 for Ayer’s use of this terminology.]

13.              What three conditions must be fulfilled if “I may be said to have acted freely”? [434] Do you agree with Ayer that these are the conditions of free action? Why, or why not?

 

Return to the top of the page

 


 

Reading Questions

Set XI

 

Roderick M. Chisholm, “Human Freedom and the Self”

 

1.                  How does Chisholm characterize “the metaphysical problem of human freedom”? [452]

2.                  According to Chisholm, what does it mean to be “responsible for a certain event or a certain state of affairs”? [452] On this picture of responsibility, what will it mean to say that someone is not responsible for a certain event? Do you agree with this picture of responsibility? Why, or why not?

3.                  How might determinism conflict “with a familiar view about the nature of God”? [453]

4.                  What “stratagem” do compatibilists sometimes employ? [453] The stratagem yields a particular argument in favor of compatibilism. [454] State and explain that argument.

5.                  How does Chisholm object to this argument for compatibilism? [454] Do you find his objection compelling? Why, or why not?

6.                  According to Chisholm, what possibility remains even after we discover that “[o]ur conception of action … should be neither deterministic nor indeterministic”? [454]

7.                  How does Chisholm define causation (when considering “only inanimate natural objects”)? [454]

8.                  What is transeunt causation? [454]

9.                  What is immanent causation? [454-5]

10.              State and explain the first objection to Chisholm’s view. How does Chisholm respond to that objection? [455]

11.              State and explain the second objection to Chisholm’s view. How does Chisholm respond to that objection? [455]

12.              Explain what the Hobbist approach is. [457]

13.              Explain what the Kantian approach is. [457]

 

Return to the top of the page

 


 

Reading Questions

Set XII

 

Introduction to Part III: Mind and Its Place in Nature

 

1.                  What are bodies? [298]

2.                  What is a mind? [298]

3.                  What is Dualism? [298]

4.                  What is Idealism? [298]

5.                  What is Materialism? [298]

 

Keith Campbell, “Dualisms”

 

            COMING SOON!

 

Frank Jackson, “The Qualia Problem”

 

6.                  What does Jackson mean by ‘physical information’? [333]

7.                  What is a “qualia freak”? [333]

8.                  By the way, what do you think qualia are? [See pages 333-4 and page 335 for some ideas.]

9.                  What, according to Jackson, is “[t]he major factor in stopping people from admitting qualia”? [334]

10.              The Fred example and the Mary example are supposed to show that physicalism – also known as materialism – “leaves something out” (335), or that physicalism is false. How is the Fred example supposed to show this? [334-5] How is the Mary example supposed to show this? [335]

11.              In the last section of the paper, Jackson argues that there is no good reason to think that qualia are causally efficacious. That is, he argues that there is no good reason to think that epiphenomenalism is false. What two objections does he provide to epiphenomenalism, and how does he respond to each objection? [336]

 

Return to the top of the page

 


 

Reading Questions

Set XIII

 

Introduction to Part I: Reason and Religious Belief

 

1.                  What is an Inductive Argument? [3]

 

Saint Anselm, “The Ontological Argument, from Proslogium

 

2.                  According to Anselm, what sort of being do we believe God to be? [6]

3.                  State and explain the argument that Anselm gives for the existence of God in the first paragraph of Chapter III. [7]

4.                  State and explain the argument that Anselm gives in Chapter IV. [7]

5.                  In these passages, Anselm argues that God exists. State his overall argument in your own words. Do you think that the argument succeeds? Why, or why not?

 

William L. Rowe, “The Ontological Argment”

 

            COMING SOON!

 

Return to the top of the page

 


 

Reading Questions

Set XIV

 

Saint Thomas Aquinas, “The Five Ways, from Summa Theologica

 

1.                  State and explain Aquinas’ “argument from motion.” [18] Do you think that the argument is a good one? Why, or why not?

2.                  State and explain Aquinas’ argument from “the nature of efficient cause.” [19] Do you think that the argument is a good one? Why, or why not?

3.                  State and explain Aquinas’ argument from “possibility and necessity.” [19] Do you think that the argument is a good one? Why, or why not?

4.                  State and explain Aquinas’ argument from “the gradation to be found in things.” [19] Do you think that the argument is a good one? Why, or why not?

5.                  State and explain Aquinas’ argument from “the governance of the world.” [19] Do you think that the argument is a good one? Why, or why not?

 

William L. Rowe, “The Cosmological Argument”

 

6.                  What is an A priori argument? [21]

7.                  What is an A posteriori argument? [21]

8.                  From what fact does the Cosmological Argument start? [21] Is it an a priori argument or an a posteriori argument?

9.                  From what fact does the Teleological Argument (a.k.a. the Argument from Design) start? [21] Is it an a priori argument or an a posteriori argument?

10.              From what fact does the Ontological Argument start? [21] Is it an a priori argument or an a posteriori argument?

11.              According to Rowe, how might one object to Aquinas’ argument? [21]

12.              What does Rowe mean by “a dependent being”? [22]

13.              What does Rowe mean by “a self-existent being”? [22]

14.              What, according to Rowe, does the first premise of the Cosmological Argument assert? [23]

15.              State and explain the Principle of Sufficient Reason (or the PSR). [23-4]

16.              How does the truth of the first premise of the Cosmological Argument depend on the truth of the PSR? [23-4]

17.              How does the truth of the second premise of the Cosmological Argument depend on the truth of the PSR? [24-5]

18.              According to Rowe, we might object to the Cosmological Argument in four ways. State and explain the first three of these objections, and then explain how Rowe responds to them. [25-8]

19.              Rowe also believes that we might object to the Cosmological Argument by questioning the PSR. How, according to Rowe, might a proponent of the PSR defend the PSR. Does Rowe think that such defenses work? Do you think that such defenses work? Why, or why not? [28-9]

 

Return to the top of the page

 


 

Reading Questions

Set XV

 

William Paley, “The Argument from Design”

 

1.                  According to Paley, “when we come to inspect the watch,” what do we perceive? [30]

2.                  Once Paley finds the watch, he examines it twice. What is the conclusion of the first examination? [30-2, 34]

3.                  For the second examination, Paley has us suppose that the watch possesses “the unexpected property of producing in the course of its movement another watch like itself.” (32) That is, Paley has us suppose that the watch reproduces. What is the conclusion of this second examination? [32-4]

4.                  What similarities are there between the watch that Paley finds and “the eye, … animals, … plants, … [and] all the organized parts of the works of nature”? [34] What are these similarities supposed to suggest about “the organized parts of the works of nature”?

 

Return to the top of the page

 


 

Reading Questions

Set XVI

 

J. L. Mackie, “Evil and Omnipotence”

 

1.                  Why, according to Mackie, can the theologian accept the criticism of traditional arguments for the existence of God? [90]

2.                  What, according to Mackie, can be shown by “the traditional problem of evil”? [90]

3.                  What is The Problem of Evil (in “its simplest form”)? [90] Why is the problem of evil a problem?

4.                  What “additional principles” do we need in order to show that there is a problem of evil? [90]

5.                  What, according to Mackie, could we say in order to adequately solve the problem of evil? [91] Do you think that it is a good idea to say any of these things? Why, or why not?

6.                  What is “the general form” of fallacious solutions to the problem of evil? [91]

7.                  According to Mackie, what problems—I think there are three of them—arise for the first solution to the problem of evil? [92-3]

8.                  According to Mackie, what problem arises for the second solution to the problem of evil? [93]

9.                  What is first order evil, or Evil (1)? [94]

10.              What is first order good, or Good (1)? [94]

11.              What is second order good, or Good (2)? [94] How are evil (1), good (1), and good (2) supposed to be related?

12.              What is third order good, or good (3)? [94] How is it supposed to be related to good (2)?

13.              What is the third (and “fatal”) objection to the third solution to the problem of evil? [94] Do you think that this objection is in fact fatal? Why, or why not?

14.              How, according to Mackie, can the fourth solution be combined with the third solution? How is this combination supposed to evade Mackie’s criticism of the thrid solution? [95]

15.              How, according to Mackie, are freedom and Evil (2) related? [95]

16.              What is Mackie’s first worry with the fourth solution? [95]

17.              What, according to Mackie, is “a fundamental difficulty in the notion of an Omnipotent God creating man with free will”? [95]

18.              What is the Paradox of Omnipotence? [96] Why is it a paradox? [96]

19.              How, according to Mackie, can we solve the Paradox of Omnipotence? [97]

 

Return to the top of the page

 


 

Reading Questions

Set XVII

 

Peter van Inwagen, “The Magnitude, Duration and Distribution of Evil: A Theodicy”

 

1.                  Why did God need to take a risk? [98]

2.                  What “familiar ‘move’ in discussions of the problem of evil” is at the heart of van Inwagen’s theodicy? [98]

3.                  By the way, what is a Theodicy?

4.                  van Inwagen claims that the following claim is true: An omnipotent being cannot insure that a creature who has a free choice between x and y choose x rather than y. Do you think that this compromises God’s omnipotence? Why, or why not?

5.                  What is the only source of evil? [98]

6.                  What is ‘natural’ evil? [100, 101]

7.                  “[G]iven the facts of history,” what must a theodicist do? [100]

8.                  What does van Inwagen’s tale demonstrate? [101] First of all, do you think that the tale does in fact demonstrate what van Inwagen thinks it demonstrates? Why, or why not? Next, do you agree the suffering and death caused by earthquakes is the result of the actions of human beings? Why, or why not?

9.                  How does van Inwagen respond to Question 1? [103]

10.              What is van Inwagen’s first response to Question 2? [103]

11.              What are his second and third responses to Question 2? [103-5]

12.              What three “speculations” does van Inwagen suggest as responses to Question 3? [105-6]

13.              What are horrors? [106]

14.              On what should “students of the Problem of Evil” concentrate? [107]

15.              What is van Inwagen’s response to Question 4? [107]

16.              How does Eleonore Stump object to van Inwagen’s argument? How does van Inwagen respond to Stump’s objection? [109]

 

Return to the top of the page

 


Philosophy 1 Syllabus  ·  Tim’s Philosophy Page  ·  Tim Black’s Homepage