Gttinger Forum fr Altertumswissenschaft 2 (1999) 17-76

http://www.gfa.d-r.de/2-99/schmitz.pdf

Ex Africa lux?

Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US*

von THOMAS A. SCHMITZ, Kiel

Writing about Martin Bernal's   Black Athena1 and  its  reception  in  the US is  a
formidable task. Few, if any scholars can  claim  competence on the numerous
questions this book raises.2 The prehistory of the  Aegean  world,  Egyptology,
Ancient Near Eastern Studies, Archeology, Linguistics, Classics, the history  of
philosophy and politics in Europe from antiquity to modern times, the history
of scholarship these are just some of the fields that Bernal  touches. Hence, it
was with  some  reluctance  that  I  accepted  the  assignment  to  talk  and  write
about this  topic. The  thought  that  the  main  part  of my  paper  would  not  be
about the  assessment  of  Bernal's   claims  (about  which  more  competent
scholars have written  extensively3), but rather about the fierce debate that his
theses have triggered was small consolation because it meant I had to venture
into fields I find even more alien,  such  as education and politics  in  the  US.
However, I believe that it is important  for academics  in Europe to learn more
about this debate, not only because it has provoked such an immense  amount
of attention to the classical world but also because it can  serve as  an example
for intellectual  developments  in  the US  which  few Europeans  know  about.
Moreover, I am convinced that it would be at our own  risk,  and  to our own
detriment, if we chose  to ignore such  developments  or derided them  as  an
American eccentricity that does not affect academics  (and politics)  in Europe.
As I will  try to show, we had  better take these questions  seriously  since  they
are bound to be raised  in  Europe as well,  and Classicists  especially  here  in
Germany have every reason to learn  the lessons  which  this debate can  teach
us. Hence, although lacking the competence to speak authoritatively about all
the questions  involved,  I  have  followed the discussion  in  scholarly  and
popular publications  during a recent stay in the US, and I hope that an  eye-
witness account will be useful for intellectuals here in Europe.
* A number of  friends and  colleagues have shown interest in this  article  and  have  made
many helpful suggestions. Josef Wieseh.fer talked  me into writing it  and  supported  me
all  the  while. Ernst-Richard  Schwinge offered  helpful comments  and  let  me use  his
collection of material on the history of scholarship. Gerhard Binder called my attention to
some important  contributions.  And,  last  not  least,  Hartmut  Leppin  read  an  earlier
version and  made me rethink the arguments in the last  section.  I am  indebted  to  all  of
them.

1  Bernal [1987] and [1991]. References to these volumes will be given in parentheses.
2  Cf. Baines [1996] 42-3.
3  See especially the articles in Lefkowitz/Rogers [1996] and Marchand/Grafton [1997].

18 Thomas A. Schmitz

My paper  will  be structured  in  three parts.  Although  this  will  not  be  (yet)
another review of Black Athena, the first part will  give a summary  of Bernal's 
main theses and the scholarly reactions to  them. In  the second  part, I  will  try
to describe and  analyze  the wider implications  of  this  academic  debate. For
many classicists,  it  was  probably  Bernal's   book  and  the  use  that  some
quarters made  of  its  conclusions  which  brought  the  phenomenon  of
Afrocentrism to  their  attention.  Afrocentrism itself  has  to be understood
within the wider context of American  discussions  about equal rights for and
emancipation of  ethnic  minorities,  especially  African-Americans,
multiculturalism and identity politics. I will try to analyze the ways in which
the debate about Black Athena relates  to these  issues  and  to current  political
problems  such  as  the  controversies about  affirmative action  or  curricula  in
history. Finally, I  will  give a (necessarily  brief) outline of the importance  this
debate has  for classicists  in Europe, especially  in Germany. I will argue  that
the society in our countries  is bound to face similar  problems  with  our own
minorities and  that we should  try to avoid some of the mistakes  which  have
exacerbated the controversy in the US. Finally,  I  will show that classicists  in
Germany have  a  special  obligation  to  pursue  the question  raised  by  Black
Athena whether our profession was and is influenced by racist assumptions.

An Outline of the Arguments of Black Athena

As Martin  Bernal  himself  writes  in  the  preface  of  the  first  volume  of  Black
Athena, he was  not trained  as  a  classicist  or  Egyptologist  (Bernal  [1987]  xii-
xv). Prior to 1987,  he had  done work chiefly in  the field of Chinese  and  East
Asian studies and taught (and still teaches) at  the department of Government
at Cornell University, one of the renowned Ivy League schools.  According  to
his own account, he developed an interest in the relations  between Greek and
Semitic languages  in the second half  of the seventies.  Although  he  seems  to
have lectured  on topics  such  as  the  development  of  early  forms  of  Indo-
European and Afroasiatic  languages  and  the migration  of the alphabet,4 he
had published  very little on these topics. Accordingly, the publication  of the
first volume of Black Athena in 1987 was a big surprise  to most scholars  active
in the fields of Egyptology, Classics and the history of ideas. This  first volume
began with  a  detailed outline  of the  argument  of  two  more  volumes  to  be
published subsequently  (Bernal [1987]  38-73).  Volume 2 appeared four years
later, in 1991.  In  it, Bernal announced  that he had  changed  the original  plan
of his project and that Black Athena now was to comprise four volumes. So far,

4 Some of his unpublished papers  are listed in the bibliography of Bernal [1987]  526;  see
the items Bernal 1980, 1983a and 1983b.

Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 19

no further tomes have been published. Some of Bernal's  critics concluded  that
he  may  have  found  the difficulties  in  producing  the parts  concerning  the
linguistic evidence (especially etymology) and  the consequences  of his  theses
for our view of ancient  history  so  overwhelming  that  he  simply  abandoned
the project. Yet the persistence with which  Bernal  has  replied to almost  every
review and  has  participated  in every debate about Black Athena suggests  that
he is still very interested in the subject and that he may still  surprise  everyone
by publishing  the third tome. However, in view of the fundamental  critiques
which he would have to take into account, this would be a difficult task.
The arguments  in Black Athena can  be divided into two main  groups:  on  the
one  hand,  Bernal  treats  the history  of  the last  three  millennia  BCE in  the
whole Mediterranean, especially in Egypt and Greece, on the other hand, he is
concerned  with the  history  of historiography  about  these  ancient
Mediterranean cultures  from the classical  Greek period (fifth century BCE) to
the  present  day.  Although  Bernal's  theses about  the  history  of  the
Mediterranean are  mostly presented  in the  second  volume,  it  is  more
convenient to begin  with this  part  before looking  at  his  contribution  to the
history of scholarship.
Bernal is convinced  that the whole Mediterranean and  especially  Greece had
experienced  deep reaching  and  decisive  Egyptian  influence  as early  as the
third millennium BCE. The earliest phases of this influence are most visible in
Crete and in Boeotia. Although he does not assume large Egyptian colonies  in
mainland Greece at  this  point  in  time,  Bernal  is  convinced  that  irrigation
works in Boeotia (especially  at lake Kopais) and  other archeological  remains
show that Egyptians  were present in  the regions in  significant  numbers  in
the third  millennium  BCE  (Bernal  [1991]  146).  Memory  of  this  Egyptian
influence has  been preserved in  the myths  about  Herakles,  who  is  at  once
depicted as  a  Middle Kingdom  pharaoh  and  a  hydraulic  engineer  (Bernal
[1991] 109-120).  In  Crete, Bernal  sees proof of Egyptian  influence  in  the  bull
cult which  was  adopted  from Egypt in  the 21st  century BCE (Bernal  [1991]
165-78); although  Egyptian  rule  or suzerainty  over Crete and  some  of  the
islands at  this  time  cannot  be proven, it  is  a  plausible  hypothesis (Bernal
[1991] 185).
The next period of Egyptian influence is marked by the conquests  of pharaoh
Senwosre I, dated by Bernal to the 20th century BCE. Bernal assumes  that this
pharaoh should  be  identified  with  the  Sesostris  mentioned  by  the  fifth-
century BCE historian  Herodotus  (2.102-10)  and  the  Sesoosis  mentioned  by
the first-century BCE writer Diodorus Siculus  (1.53-58),  and  he accepts  these

20 Thomas A. Schmitz

writers' accounts of his conquests. Sesostris led  extensive military  campaigns
that took him to Palestine, Anatolia, Thrace, Scythia and even to the Caucasus
(see the  map  Bernal  [1991]  542),  though  not  to  Greece.  Memory  of  these
conquests has been preserved in the Greek legends of Dionysus/Osiris  and  of
Memnon (Bernal [1991] 238-9, 257-69).
The most important phase of Egyptian expansion over the Mediterranean and
especially Greece, however, was  still  to come.  At some  point  in  time, Lower
Egypt was  conquered  by a  foreign  people  of  unknown  origin,  as  the
Egyptian historian  Manetho (third  century  BCE) wrote (quoted in  Josephus,
Contra Apionem 1.75  to genos asmoi); these  invaders  came  from the East  and
were called  Hyksos.  It  is  difficult  to  give a  precise  date  for this  dramatic
development because, as Bernal himself  writes (Bernal [1991]  323),  this was
one of the most confused periods of Egyptian history. Nevertheless, Bernal  is
confident that he can  date this  conquest to the 1740s or 1730s (Bernal  [1991]
406) or the 1750s BCE (Bernal [1991] 323 and in the chart Bernal [1991] xxviii).
Folk memory of the Hyksos conquest (and  their  later  expulsion  from  Egypt)
has been preserved in the Biblical story of Genesis  and  Exodus  (Bernal [1991]
355-8). The ethnic makeup of the Hyksos  as  described  by Bernal  is  a  rather
complicated matter.  If  I  understand him  correctly,  he  sees them as  a
multinational corporation (Bernal [1991] 345), the  two oldest ingredients  of
which were Hurrians  and  Indo-Aryans  (Bernal  [1991]  346-8).  They  moved
from their home in upper Mesopotamia  into the Syro-Palestinian  area in the
18th century  BCE  and  there  formed  the  warlike  elite  of  what  was  a
predominantly Semitic  society.  After  that,  they  overran  Egypt,  adopting
Egyptian civilization  soon after  their  arrival.  Very  soon after  this  (around
1730, it would seem, see Bernal  [1991]  364),  the now  Indo-Aryan-Hurrian-
Semitic-Egyptian (Bernal  [1991]  381)  Hyksos  again  moved  on  to  conquer
Crete (where  they  established  the  Late  Palatial  society),  the  Cyclades  and
southern Greece  (Bernal  [1991]  406).  The  entire  Mycenaean  civilization,
according  to  Bernal,  should  be interpreted  as  an  amalgam  of Levantine,
Egyptian and  Cretan  elements imported  by  these  Hyksos  invaders  who
established long-lasting  heroic  dynasties (Bernal  [1991]  405)  and ruled
large parts  of Greece between 1720 and  1570 (Bernal [1991]  408).  These  new
rulers founded  petty  kingdoms  following  Cretan  palatial  bureaucratic
customs and  Hyksos'  and  native  habits  of frequent if  not  constant  warfare
with each  other (Bernal  [1991]  449).  Bernal  is  convinced  that  it  was  from
this society that not only  the cultivation  of the later  Mycenaean  palaces  but
also Greek  language and  culture as  they  survive  until  today first  took
shape (Bernal [1991]  408). The extensive and intensive  influence  that  Egypt
exerted on  Greece  during  this  formative  period  of  Greek  culture  (Bernal

Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 21

[1991]  494)  would  warrant  Bernal's   assertion that  all Greek  culture  is
permeated by Egyptian influence (Bernal [1991] 266).
The  Greek myths  about  the  arrival  of Kadmos  and  of Danaus  preserve  the
memory of this Hyksos conquest (Bernal  [1991]  501-4);  however, the  Greeks
altered the historical facts in a significant way: they depicted Danaus  not as  a
victorious conqueror, but as  a refugee, thus  intimating  that  the  Hyksos  only
came to  Greece  after  they  had been  expelled  from Egypt.  This  distortion,
according  to Bernal,  was  due  either  to a  desire  to give low  dates  for any
kind  of  events  in  order  to appear  sober  and  reasonable  or  to Greek
patriotism which would find it less  painful  to accept  the  arrival  of refugees
than  of conquerors  (Bernal  [1991]  364).  It  should  be emphasized  that  the
Hyksos  conquest  of large  parts  of the  Mediterranean  world  within  just  one
generation  must  have  been  one  of  the  most remarkable  feasts in human
history unfortunately, Bernal  provides no details  about  the ways  in  which
the immense  logistical  problems  could  be solved, and  he  does  not  explain
how the Hyksos  could  adapt  to  the  foreign  civilizations  they  encountered
with such  amazing  speed.5 This  adaptability,  however,  and  the incredible
swiftness with which the Hyksos moved help his  argument a lot: whether he
finds  Anatolian,  Levantine,  Egyptian  or Cretan  artifacts  or influences  in
Greece, Bernal  can  use  any  of these  as  proof of a  Hyksos  conquest  (Bernal
[1991] 406-7).
According to Bernal, the Hyksos were expelled from Egypt in  the wake of the
catastrophic consequences  of  the  great  volcanic  eruption  on  the  island  of
Thera, which he dates to 1628 BCE (Bernal [1991]  274-88).  Nevertheless, close
contacts between Egypt, the Levant, Crete, the Aegean islands  and  mainland
Greece  persisted  during  the  next  four  centuries (albeit  with  some minor
interruptions), mainly  in  the form  of  state  or  private  trading,  certainly  in
luxuries and  very  probably  in  staples  (Bernal  [1991]  447).  During  the
expansion of Egyptian power in the 15th  century under  pharaoh  Tuthmosis
III, Egyptians seem  to have claimed  some sort of suzerainty  over the Aegean
(Bernal [1991]  434,  451),  and  this  rule  over large  parts  of the  Mediterranean
was maintained  by his  successors  for over a  century  (Bernal  [1991]  465).
During this  period,  the Mycenaean  civilization  was  only  able  to uphold  its
elaborate social  structure and  large populations  because  of  Egyptian  grain
supplies (Bernal [1991]  485-7).  Egyptian rule seems  to have  remained  stable
even as a new wave of immigrants  from Anatolia,  the Achaioi  (whom Bernal
identifies with the famous Ahhiyawa of Hittite texts), vanquished  the Hyksos
kings in southern Greece and  established  their own  rule  (Bernal  [1991]  452-
5  On the alleged Hyksos invasion, see the remarks of Weinstein [1992] 382.

22 Thomas A. Schmitz

60). Bernal  sees a memory of this  conquest  preserved in  the  Greek myths  of
the arrival  of Pelops and  his  descendants  from Asia  and  their  victories  over
the Heraclids.
This relatively stable Pax Aegyptiaca began to disintegrate in the 13th  century
BCE when  the balance  of  powers  in  the Mediterranean  shifted  and  some
empires  (such as the  Hittite)  were  destroyed.  The  entire  Mycenaean
civilization collapsed in  this  situation.  At the end of his  historical  account  of
bronze-age Greece, Bernal  gives a variety of reasons  for this  collapse  (Bernal
[1991] 520-1):  Mycenae  was  damaged  firstly  by local  wars  at  Thebes and
Troy and the subsequent dynastic  feuds described in  the epics  and  tragedies;
secondly,  by the  breakdown  of trade  and  civilization  around  the  East
Mediterranean  after  the Invasions  of  the Sea  Peoples  c. 1190  BC, with the
consequent lack of  the  staples  necessary  for  a  specialized  food-deficient
economy. Thirdly, there were the migrations  of northern Greek tribes around
1150 BC, which were possibly precipitated by the Hekla volcanic disaster.
Unusual as  Bernal's   picture of the early Mediterranean may seem, he claims
that this  view was  universally  accepted before  the  nineteenth  century.  The
first volume of Black Athena provides an account of the history of this Ancient
Model and  its overturn by what Bernal labels  the Aryan  Model. The  first
chapter argues  that  the  Greeks of  the  classical  and  Hellenistic  periods
themselves  knew about Egyptian  colonization  in  the  bronze  ages.  Greek
sources claiming that Greek letters, philosophy, institutions and religion were
imported from Egypt tell the truth; they are  aware  of these  facts  because  of
traditions  whose origins  can  be traced back to the bronze ages. This  view of
Greek history remained unchanged until the Renaissance  (Bernal [1987]  121):

" no  one  before 1600  seriously questioned  either  the  belief  that  Greek
civilization  and philosophy  derived  from Egypt,  or  that  the chief  ways  in
which they  had  been  transmitted  were  through  Egyptian  colonizations  of
Greece and  later  Greek study  in  Egypt. Many  strains  of  Western  religious
and  mystical  traditions,  such as  Hermeticism, Kabbalistic mysticism,
Freemasonry, Rosicrucianism or even some aspects  of Christianity  ultimately
go back to Egyptian  sources  of the  bronze  age,  transmitted  via  Greece.6 The
6  Chapter  3  is an interesting,  if not  particularly  original account  of  hermeticism  and
occultism during the Renaissance.  Bernal succeeds  in showing that  these traditions  have
often been underrated and played down in order to produce a more rational, less  strange
picture of  Renaissance intellectual history. However, the reader  is  left  to  wonder what
exactly this  account  proves.  Does  Bernal  really  contend  that  all  these Freemasons,
Rosicrucians and  magicians  did  indeed  possess  the  wisdom  of  ancient  Egyptian
priesthoods, as they frequently claimed?  Bernal never explicitly  says  so.  If, on the other
hand, this claim is fictitious, this whole section is a rather irrelevant digression.

Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 23

seventeenth and  eighteenth centuries  even  witnessed  The  Triumph  of
Egypt, as the heading of chapter 3 has it; scholars were convinced that Egypt
had been an advanced civilization long before Greece and that the Greeks had
derived their philosophy from Egyptian sources.
It was  only  in  the second  half  of the eighteenth  century that  Hostilities  to
Egypt (heading  of chapter  4)  began. Bernal  argues  that  four  reasons  were
responsible for this change of attitude (Bernal [1987] 189): Christian  reaction,
the rise  of  the concept  of  progress,'  the growth  of  racism,  and  Romantic
Hellenism. Christianity  could  not  accept  claims  that  Egyptian  religious
traditions  were older  than  the  Hebrew Bible;  the  Protestant  Reformation
favored Greek studies  and  ultimately  the superiority  of Greek over Egyptian
civilization (Bernal [1987]  190-5). 7 The concept of progress favored historical
appreciation of societies  that were supposed  to be dynamic  and  developing
and worked against Oriental civilizations, which were supposed to have been
static and thus  inferior. " the introduction  of the progressive  paradigm'
was ultimately  fatal  to  the  reputation  of  the  Egyptians.  Their  antiquity 
which had previously been one of their major assets now became a liability
(Bernal [1987]  201).  Romantic  philhellenism,  which  had  existed  in  the
eighteenth century, was stimulated  by the Greek War of Independence  in the
early  nineteenth  century, which  was  interpreted  as a continental  struggle
between Europe on the one hand,  and Asia  and Africa on the other  (Bernal
[1987] 248). However, it was racism, together with European colonialism  and
racially motivated slavery, that was to prove most pernicious  to the Ancient
Model. The  new  racial  science  claimed  to  have  scientific  proofs  for  the
assertion that  Caucasian  races  were  superior to  all  other  human  races.
Scholars convinced  of  the  validity  of  this  view  could  not  tolerate  the
assumption  that racially  inferior peoples  such  as  Egyptians  or  other
Africans could  have exerted  any  deep  reaching  influence  on Greece,  the
paragon of Western  civilization,  let  alone  have  conquered  and  ruled  large
parts of Europe.
Hence,  from the late  eighteenth  to  the  early  twentieth  centuries,  scholars
attacked  the Ancient  Model, replacing  it with  the view  that  Greek
civilization  was  by and large free from any outside influences  and had  been
developed by an  Indo-European  people  that  had  invaded  Greece  from  the
north during the late bronze age. According to Bernal, the development of this

7  Bernal remains somewhat vague on how Protestant  interest in Greek language, literature
and philosophy entailed disparaging Egyptian civilization;  his statement  (Bernal [1987]
194)  From using Greek to attack  Roman Catholic superstition,  it  was  not  such a  long
step to employing it against Egyptian magic is enigmatic rather than convincing.

24 Thomas A. Schmitz

new model was  not  due to new  findings  (such  as  the discovery of Sanskrit
and  the  decipherment  of cuneiform  scripts), but the  destruction of the  old
model took  place  entirely  for what  historians  of  science  call  externalist'
reasons. The Ancient Model fell not because of any new developments in the
field but because it did not fit the prevailing world-view. To be more precise, it
was  incompatible  with the paradigms  of race and  progress of the  early  19th
century (Bernal  [1987]  316).  Ancient  sources  containing  accounts  of
Egyptian colonization  and  the  Egyptian origin  of  Greek  religion  and
philosophy  were  discredited,  not  least because of  the  newly  developed
methods  of historical  positivism,  the most  important of  which  was source
criticism  (Bernal [1987]  217-8).  Bernal  sees source criticism  as  merely a form
of arrogant Besserwissen (which, incidentally, is not a German  word: we speak
of besser wissen  or of Besserwisserei,  the noun Besserwissen  does not
exist): blinded by their ideological  prejudices, the moderns  think they know
better than the ancients.
The new  Aryan  Model,  as  Bernal  calls  it, was  constantly  being  modified
and fine-tuned, yet the basic tenor remained  the same  throughout. According
to Bernal, there was  a tendency  to derive a maximum  of Greek words from
Sanskrit precursors and  to deny the massive  borrowings from  Egyptian  and
Semitic languages  which  he  claims  to  have  detected.  Egyptian  cultural
influence was minimized. For a while, scholars accepted that the Phoenicians
had played  an important  role  in  the  development of  Greek  civilization,
especially because  many  Victorians  had  a  positive  feeling  towards  the
Phoenicians  as  sober  cloth merchants  who did  a little  bit  of slaving  on  the
side and  spread  civilization  while making  a tidy profit (Bernal  [1987]  350).
Yet with  growing  anti-Semitism  at  the  end  of  the  nineteenth  and  the
beginning of  the  twentieth  centuries,  scholars  insisted  more  and  more
forcefully that the Phoenician  influence  had  come late in the development of
Greek  civilization  and had had a  very  limited  impact.  Bernal  calls  this
process  The final  solution  of the  Phoenician  problem  (heading  of chapter
9).
Although the Aryan Model has  become  so  entrenched  that  it now  works  as
what Thomas  Kuhn described as  a scientific  paradigm  (Bernal  [1991]  11-2),
Bernal is confident that it is  untenable  and  that  the  Ancient  Model will  be
restored at some point in the early 21st century (Bernal [1987]  402).  His own
work could then be seen as  ahead  of its time. Bernal  is  certain  that much  of
contemporary work  on  the  archaeology  and  ancient  history  of  the  East
Mediterranean  will  have to  be  rethought (Bernal  [1991]  527),  and  he
promises that  the  next  volume  to  be  published  will  be  even  more

Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 25

revolutionary than the first two tomes (Bernal [1991] 527):  "  the outrages'
in this book are nothing to those I propose for the next volume ".

The Scholarly Reception of Black Athena

So much  for  a  short  summary  of  Bernal's   arguments.  Given  the  normal
delays in  scholarly  publishing,  the  academic  debate  started  almost
immediately insinuations by  Bernal  himself  (Bernal  [1991]  xx-xxi)  that
some sort  of conspiracy  tried to suppress  attention  to his  book  are  clearly
unfounded.8 In  1989,  a  discussion  on  The  Challenge  of  Black Athena: The
Classicists'  Response  was sponsored as  the presidential  panel at  the  120th
meeting of  the  American  Philological  Association;  the  proceedings  were
published the same year in a special issue of the journal Arethusa.9 In 1990,  an
issue of the American Journal of Archaeology comprised  a number of articles on
the book  and  the questions  it raises.  The  most  extended,  if  one-sided
treatment so  far  has  been  the  collection  of  responses  and  reactions  in
Lefkowitz/Rogers [1996]. The overwhelming majority of academic  responses
to Bernal's   book,  while  acknowledging  its  importance  as  a  catalyst  of
renewed interest  in  the  questions  it  raises,  pointed  out that  its  main  theses
were deeply  flawed.  What  follows  is  just  a  selection  of  the  most  serious
critical objections raised against Black Athena.
  The part of Bernal's   arguments  that  has  met  with  almost  unanimous
disapproval was  his  linguistic evidence,  especially  his  Egyptian
etymologies for numerous Greek nouns  and  names.  Critics pointed out
that his  supposed  derivations  are  most  often  based  on  nothing  but
vague resemblances.  Even if we admit  that (conscious  or unconscious)
prejudice has  led earlier scholars  to underestimate  the  real  number  of
Semitic borrowings and that conclusive  proof cannot  be attained  in the
slippery field of etymology,10 it remains  true that Bernal  disregards  the
most elementary  rules  of  linguistic  developments.  Accordingly,  the
judgment of trained linguists is harsh:11 No effort is made to go beyond
the realm  of appearances;  known and  inferable facts  about  the  history
of individual  forms  are  systematically  ignored,  misrepresented,  or


8 Cf. McNeal [1993] 151 and Coleman [1996] 291: Bernal's  claims of 
victimization  act  as
a sort of preemptive  strike against  potential  criticism; readers who even mildly disagree
with some points may be reluctant to risk possible charges of racism for speaking out.
9 Peradotto/Levine  [1989].
10  Burkert [1992] 33-40.
11  Jasanoff/Nussbaum [1996]; cf. Burstein [1993] 158 or Assmann [1992] 926.

26 Thomas A. Schmitz

suppressed. Bernal's  linguistic evidence, which  he  himself  says  is  a
keystone of his argument (Bernal [1987] 62), is thus void.
  Bernal's   use  of ancient  documents,  especially  of Greek  mythological
narratives, is  deeply flawed. On the  one  hand,  his  construction  of an
ancient model  of Egyptian colonization  and  influence  in which  the
Greeks  are  said  to have  believed,  is  simplifying  to the  point  of
misleading readers  unacquainted  with the sources. Greek beliefs about
the origin  of  their  own  culture  were  various  and  contradictory,  and
different authors or groups constructed versions that fit their individual
argumentative needs.12 Bernal's   method  consists  in  arbitrarily  taking
into  account  only  versions  that  seem to  support his  thesis  and
disregarding conflicting  ones.  This  becomes  particularly  clear  in  the
case of  Danaus,  whose  myth  is  fundamental  to  Bernal's   argument.
Bernal often mentions  that  the  Greeks  told  stories  about  Danaus's
flight from Egypt, his  arrival  in Argos and  his  accession  to  the  throne
(Bernal [1987] 75-98; 2.137-8, 502-4 and passim). He interprets this  myth
as preserving memories  of a Hyksos  colonization  of Greece. However,
he fails to mention that in these narratives, Danaus  is of Greek descent:
he is a great-great-grandson of Io, daughter of the Argive king Inachus.
In Aeschylus's  tragedy  The Suppliants, Danaus  and  his  daughters
emphasize this Greek origin to support their claim  for protection  from
the king  of Argos (274-326,  see especially  274-5  To  cut  a  long  story
short: we claim to be of Argive extraction). Bernal's  partial summary of
the myth is thus deceptive.13

  This selective use of ancient  documents  demonstrates  the  absurdity  of
Bernal's  polemic against nineteenth-century  source criticism,  which  he
often (e.g., Bernal  [1987]  118, 377; 2.200,  237, 308, 309)  disparages  as
Besserwissen. Bernal goes so far as to assert  that the cultural,  racial  and
temporal arrogance or Besserwissen of the critical method " has been a
bane to the writing of history  ever since  the  early  nineteenth  century
(Bernal [1987]  306).  Yet  Bernal  himself  obviously  cannot  accept  the
totality of the ancient documents;14 he has to differentiate between what
he deems more or less  credible, or, as  he would probably  say,  more  or


12  Hall [1992] 341; cf. Green [1989], Gordon [1993] and Burstein [1993] 161.
13  Hall [1992] 338-9, Lefkowitz [1997] 18-20. Cf. also Bernal's  partial citation of  Euripides
Phoenician Women at  Bernal [1991]  507.  In Bernal [1992],  he just  attempts  to  obfuscate
the issue.
14 Bernal [1991]  404:  Although I have  a  great  respect  for  the  historical  knowledge and
judgement of the Greeks in Classical and Hellenistic times, I do not believe that they were
infallible.

Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 27

less useful  to his  argument.  He lays strong  emphasis  on  the myth  of
Danaus, which he interprets as pointing  to an  Egyptian origin of Greek
culture, yet he virtually ignores the myth of Pelops, who was  described
as coming  from  Asia  minor and would  thus  symbolize  that  Greece
was  colonized  from  the northwest  corner  of  the Asiatic  seabord.15
When ancient  sources  do  not  fit  his  argument,  Bernal  is  ready  to
criticize them in the spirit  of Besserwisserei that  he  usually  decries.  For
instance, the Egyptian historian Manetho is said  to have garbled and
confused several pharaohs (Bernal  [1991]  196);  his  account  is  said  to
be internally  inconsistent  and  of only  very  limited  value  for  this
period (Bernal  [1991]  325);  the  Greek  historian  Diodorus  Siculus  is
said to  have  misunderstood  Herodotus's  account  because  of  its
linguistic ambiguity (Bernal  [1991]  202) thus  Bernal  believes  he
knows Greek  better than  a  native  speaker  of  the  language.16 Hence,
Bernal's  critics  are  indubitably  right  when  they  denounce his
repudiation  of source  criticism  and historical  methodologies  as self-
contradictory.17  What his  strategy amounts  to is  a  return  to the
uncritical antiquarianism  of  earlier  historians  and  a  collection of
fragments which  suit  the  present  purpose  while everything  else  is
neglected.18

  These flaws are especially prominent  in  Bernal's   treatment of myths  as
historical sources. In  general,  he  seems  entirely convinced  that  myths
can be  read  as  reliable  traditions of  historical  events  and  social
structures,19 and  he is  inclined  to accept  even late  sources:  e.g., Bernal
[1991] 173  a passage  in the Greek writer Aelian  (second century CE) is
said to  preserve  correct  information  about  a  cult  of  the  fourth
millennium BCE, an instructive example of the strength and durability
of traditions  over  this  huge  expanse  of  time.20 When  it is  more
convenient for  his  argument,  however,  Bernal  dismisses  Greek
traditions because  the  Greeks  had  no  long-term  cultural  memory


15 Hall  [1992]  347  n.  2.  She  rightly points  out  this  omission;  however,  Bernal  mentions
Pelops  a  few times in passing,  e.g., Bernal [1987]  365,  491  n. 109  or  Bernal  [1991]  45,
446-7, 452-6. As  Assmann [1992]  924  rightly remarks, the omission is symptomatic  for
Bernal's  overall neglect of the orientalizing period of archaic Greece.
16  For further examples see Tritle [1992] 304-5.
17  Tritle [1992] 305.
18  See Liverani [1996] 424-5.
19  Against this view, see McNeal [1993] 144-5.
20  In this, as Baines [1996] 40 rightly remarks,  Bernal curiously follows  older classicists  in
assuming that the Greeks were a people with quite special qualities.

28 Thomas A. Schmitz

(Bernal [1991]  319).  Again,  the  absence  of any  historical  methodology
makes for an ahistorical eclecticism that has only rhetorical value.21
  Bernal's  treatment  of modern  scholarship  is  as  indiscriminate  as  his
use of  ancient  documents.  His  sweeping  generalizations  ignore  the
discussions, controversies  and  doubts  of  historians,  philologists,
archeologists and  philosophers  about  the  origin  and  originality  of
Greek culture  that  had  existed  at  almost  every  period  of  European
scholarship. Neither was the Ancient Model as undisputed before the
nineteenth century as  Bernal  implies, nor did all  Europeans after 1800
accept the claims of racial  science  or believe in  the inferiority of non-
whites. It  is  certainly  true that  Bernal's   failure  to  recognize  this
variety22 is  a  serious  flaw  of  Black Athena. His  own  first-hand
knowledge of the most  important  texts  of eighteenth-  and  nineteenth-
century European historiography, philosophy and  political  theory is so
meager that  his  generalizations  rest  on  very  shaky  ground.23 Hence,
Marchand/Grafton are  justified  in  their  harsh  judgment  about  his
contribution to the history of scholarship:  Bernal  simply  has  not done
enough work to deserve respect or attention as  a historian  of European
thought about the ancient  world. The ability  to make  noise  entitles  no
one to a hearing, and  up to now, Bernal has  made noise, not historical
argument.24 This is especially true in  the field of classical  studies.  It is
simply not true that scholars  have been as  stubborn  in  their  refusal  to
acknowledge Oriental influences on Greek culture as Bernal thinks  they
have been. Suffice it to mention  just a few: F. Dornseiff in Germany, W.
Burkert in  Switzerland  and  M.  L.  West  in  Great  Britain  have  been
publishing well-known works about the interrelations between Middle-


21  Cf. Assmann [1992]  922.  See also  Bernal's  treatment of  the myth  of  the Seven against
Thebes (Bernal [1991] 459; repeated at 512 with  n. 87):  On the one hand,  he states  that
these narratives  have  so  many  mythic  characteristics  it  is  hard  to  believe  in  their
historicity or base substantial historical constructions upon them; on the other hand,  he
sees no reason to  doubt that  there were two  sieges of  Thebes in the  13th  century and
that some of the heroes involved were historical  figures and  that  the second  siege ended
in the city's destruction.
22  Palter [1996] 359.
23  As he acknowledges himself, see Bernal [1989] 26-7: " it  is  perfectly  true that  I relied
very heavily on  secondary  sources  when treating  the  eighteenth and  early  nineteenth-
century historians. " Obviously, I was skating on very thin ice over huge areas.
24 Marchand/Grafton  [1997]  3.  For  further  negative  evaluations  of  Bernal's   arguments
about the history of scholarship, see Turner [1989], Palter [1996], Norton [1996]; Jenkyns
[1996], Stray [1997] 231.


Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 29

and Near-Eastern cultures and Greece for a long time.25 If these scholars
do not see Egypt as a decisive influence on Greece,26 this  is  certainly not
due to any kind of prejudice, let alone  racism,  but reflects the  evidence
of our archeological, historical, and literary documents.
  Lastly, Bernal never states clearly whether his  Aryan  Model is due to
a vast, worldwide conspiracy of classicists with  the aim  of suppressing
the truth about  the origin  of ancient  Greek culture  or  whether  earlier
scholars  were merely  influenced  by the  prejudices  and  beliefs  of their
times without actively manipulating  the evidence. We will  see  shortly
that Bernal's   failure to  make  this  crucial  distinction  is  not
coincidental rather, it amounts  to a  demagogic  manipulation  of  his
readers.

The Background: Afrocentrism in the US

From  the beginning,  the scholarly  debate  about  the argument  and
methodology of  Black Athena had  been  accompanied  by  an  intensive
discussion  in media aimed at wider audiences,  such  as  the New York Review
of Books, the New Statesman, or even the Village Voice. Initially,  this  debate was
restricted to typical  highbrow or middlebrow publications,  but before long, a
genuine craze  set in. This  was  especially  sensible  after Mary Lefkowitz, who
teaches Classics  at  Wellesley  College,  took  up  Bernal's   challenge  and
published her own  reactions  to Bernal's   book  and  related  tendencies.  Two
articles in the New Republic and the Wall Street Journal in 1992 and 1993 started
the  controversy. The  media  were eager  to  transform what  had begun  as a
scholarly  discussion  into an  epic battle that was  to be another chapter  of the
ongoing culture  wars  in  the  US. The  real  frenzy  started  when  Lefkowitz
published her  book  Not Out  of  Africa in  1996  and  co-edited  Black Athena
Revisited; Bernal reviewed both books several times. Almost every major paper
ran stories on the debate, there were programs  on local  and  national  TV and
radio stations.  When  the  publisher  Harper  Collins  staged  a  debate between
Bernal  and  Lefkowitz  on  the  internet  in  April  1996, some  2,200 people




25  See Dornseiff  [1959], Burkert [1992], West  [1971]  and  West  [1997]. This is  just  a  very
small and subjective sample; many more books  and  articles  could have been quoted; cf.
Burstein [1994] 13-4.
26 See also Morris [1989],  who, on archeological grounds, argues for Levantine rather than
Egyptian influence.
30 Thomas A. Schmitz


immediately signed  up  and  have  been deluging  the  discussion  list27 with
their contributions.
Although part of this enormous  interest can  be attributed to media  hype, the
genuine basis of the passion lies in the fact that Black Athena and  the debate it
triggered  bear  upon  a  subject  which  has  never  ceased  to  be of interest  in
American society, namely the relations between blacks and  whites. Moreover,
the question how history ought to be taught in schools and  colleges and what
kind of history should  be taught  has  been on  the  political  agenda  for some
time. Bernal's  book, with its imposing bibliography, its scholarly notes and its
Egyptian hieroglyphics,  epitomized much  of a debate which  had  been going
on for a long time. A number of black writers had made similar  claims  since
the beginning  of the twentieth century.28 One of the first was  Marcus Mosiah
Garvey (1887-1940), who claimed  that Greece and Rome have robbed Egypt
of her arts and letters29 in a number of articles published in the 20s. The most
influential account  was  published  in 1954  by George G. M. James,  a  college
teacher in  Arkansas. 30 Another  important  author  is  the  Senegalese  scholar
Cheikh Anta Diop, who has  published  a  number  of books  in  French  which
attempt to demonstrate that Western civilization originated in Africa; some of
them have been translated into English.31 The main  thrust of these books can
be summed up in  a few sentences:  philosophy  and  science  were invented by
the Egyptians,  a black people from Africa that had  libraries  and  universities
long before any Europeans  had  achieved such  accomplishments.  The Greeks
learned from them  and  stole  this  Egyptian  legacy.  This  historical  fact  has
been systematically  denied  by a  conspiracy  of white  historians  (Napoleon
even had the sphinx's nose shot off to conceal that it had  a black face32), yet it
continues to be remembered in  the  folk traditions  of  black  people.  Modern
Afrocentrists have made  it  their  task  to  unearth  this  hidden  history.  They
claim to have  found  out  that  the  Egyptians  used  electricity and  airplanes, 33
and they demand that their view of Egyptian history be taught in schools  and
universities.



27 Editorial New Spaces,  Old Debates,  The Washington  Post, April  29, 1996,  A16.  The
archives of  the  debate,  at  www.harpercollins.com/news/news.htm#athena  appear  to
have been deleted by Harper Collins.
28  See the account in Lefkowitz [1997] 122-54.
29  As quoted in Lefkowitz [1997] 132.
30 James  [1954].
31  E.g., Diop [1991].
32  Roth [1996] 324, cf. Shipler [1997] 210-1.
33  See Martel [1994] 40.


Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 31


Scholars have repeatedly pointed out that accounts  such  as  those  by James,
Garvey, and  Diop  are  marred  by  numerous  factual  errors  that  make  them
worthless as historical scholarship. For instance, claims  that Socrates studied
in Egypt and was initiated into the Egyptian Mystery System  are refuted by
ancient  testimonies:  Plato states  that  Socrates  never  left  Athens, except  on
military campaigns  against  Greek cities.34 Nevertheless,  these  errors  are  still
being repeated: in  a talk he delivered at  Wellesley  College in  February 1993,
Yosef A. A. ben-Jochannan  asserted  that Aristotle had  plundered  the  library
at Alexandria which contained the books of Egyptian philosophy.35 Of course,
this library was not founded before the end of the fourth century BCE, at least
20 years after Aristotle's death. Yet adherents to the theories delineated above
claim that the entire methodology and the standards of historical research  are
a result of the white conspiracy that tries to lower black self-esteem by robbing
blacks of their history and their identity.
Whoever encounters  such  theories  for the  first  time  will  probably  be  taken
aback and tend to react with impatience. It is difficult to analyze  this  belief in
a universal  conspiracy,  this  insistence  on  being  a  victim  of dark  forces  in  a
rational,  dispassionate  manner.  And yet, this  is what we have to do. Even  if
these assumptions  do  not  hold  water,  they  have  to  be  taken  seriously  as
expressions of a widespread  social  malaise.  Hence,  it  is  important  to grasp
the causes of this distrust. People outside of the US often know too little about
the recent history of blacks in America to reach this understanding.  Therefore,
I will give a very short summary of this history.

The Origins of Afrocentrist Ideas: Race Relations in the US

The  end  of  the  Civil  War  in  1865  and the passage  of  the Thirteenth
Amendment to the Constitution  abolished  slavery in  all  states  of the  Union.
The Fourteenth (1868) and  Fifteenth (1870) Amendments  granted  the  former
slaves equal civil rights, especially  the right  to  vote. However, large parts  of
the white ruling elites  in the Southern states resented these laws and  were not
willing to  accept  the  new  circumstances.  They  adopted  so-called  Black
Codes that refused blacks  the civil rights guaranteed by the Constitution. In
order to establish control over the former Confederate States, Congress placed
the South  under  military  command.  This  period,  which  is  known  as
Reconstruction, came to an  end in 1877. 36 Southern States soon returned to


34  Lefkowitz [1997] 144-5.
35  Lefkowitz [1997] 2.
36  See Foner [1988].


32 Thomas A. Schmitz


their antebellum  policies.  Racial  segregation  perpetuated  the predominance
of whites  in  every part  of social,  economical  and  political  life. Jim  Crow
laws  (the term is derived from a derogatory name  for black  people) inflicted
outrageous humiliations  on black  citizens,  segregating  schools,  parks,
cemeteries, theaters  and  restaurants,  denying  blacks  voting  privileges  and
reducing them to  the  role  of  second-class  beings.37 As  late  as  1896,  the
Supreme Court upheld the system  of separate  but equal  facilities  (Plessy v.
Ferguson). In reality, however, segregated schools  or other public  institutions
offered no  equal  opportunities;  instead,  they  clearly  were  a  form  of
discrimination.
Black activists had  begun to fight racial  segregation soon after World War II.
They achieved  a  number  of  important  legal  victories,  the  most  important
being Brown v. Board  of Education  of Topeka  (May 17,  1954),  in  which  the
Supreme Court reversed its decision of 1896 and ruled that segregated schools
violated the Fourteenth Amendment. Yet the white  establishment,  especially
in the  Southern  states,  was  still  unwilling  to grant  blacks  equal  rights.  The
following years  witnessed  the  long,  bitter  and  often violent  struggle  of
reactionary and racist whites against desegregation. To quote just one famous
example: in  September  1957,  the  governor  of  Arkansas,  Orval E.  Faubus,
obstructed a federal  court  order for integration  of  a  high  school  in  the  state
capital, Little Rock, and did not give up his  resistance  until  President Dwight
D. Eisenhower dispatched  1,000  federal troops to Arkansas.  Segregation was
formally abolished under  President Lyndon B. Johnson  with the Civil Rights
Act of 1964 and the Voting Rights Act of 1965.  Yet the Civil Rights Movement
had to pay dearly for this final victory: many of its members and activists  had
been imprisoned,  mistreated  by the  police  and  angry  whites,  or even killed
(such as Martin  Luther  King,  Jr.,  on  April  4,  1968).  And  cities  and
communities  throughout  the countries  fought many  years  against  the laws
ordering integration. To an  extent, the US is  still  trying  to  finish  the  process
that has been begun with the Civil Rights Act.38
Disappointment about  this  slow  progress  made  several  black  leaders
skeptical  of the non-violent  methods  of  the Civil  Rights  Movement.  These
disappointed activists  such  as  Malcolm  X  made black  nationalism  and
black power their rallying cry. They regarded whites  as their enemies  and
were convinced  that  blacks  would  never  be  able  to  escape  from
discriminations  unless they  had  a culture,  perhaps  even  a nation  of  their
own. These activists considered the historical myths of black thinkers such  as


37  See Litwack [1998].
38  See Higham [1997].


Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 33

James or Garvey a welcome instrument to bolster black self-esteem.  It is from
these circles  that the pseudo-histories  spread and  were accepted  as  truth by
blacks whose  distrust  of  the white  government  had  grown  into  huge
dimensions.
Yet, the long  struggle  for equal  rights  and  the stubborn  resistance  of  many
whites  affected  even  the larger part  of  the black  population  that  was  not
willing to  draw  such  radical  conclusions.  For  many years,  they  had
experienced  a  system  of justice  and  law  enforcement  dominated  by white
elites   that deprived  them of  their  rights and  treated  them as  inferiors.  As
Randall Kennedy has  argued  in  a  recent  book,  this  experience  contributed
enormously to  the  feeling  shared  by  many  blacks  that  politics,  laws,  the
courts and the police are merely instruments of white domination:39
For a long time, criminal law not simply  the biased  administration  of
law but the law itself was  the enemy of African-Americans.  In many
places, for several generations, it was a crime for blacks to learn  to read,
to flee  enslavement,  or  to defend  themselves,  their  families,  or  their
friends from physical abuse. It was a crime, in sum,  for blacks,  to do all
sorts  of things  deemed to be permissible  or admirable  when  done  by
others.  More  recently,  during the  civil rights era,  African-Americans
violated  criminal  laws  (although  many of  these laws  were
subsequently invalidated)  to uproot the Jim  Crow system. That is  why
so many  African-Americans  lionized  in  black  communities  have  had
criminal records.  The  list  includes  Martin  Luther  King,  Jr.,  Robert
Moses, Fannie  Lou Hamer, Rosa  Parks,  and  John  Lewis.  By using  the
criminal law  against  these  and  others  involved  in  resisting  racial
oppression, officials  have  destabilized  the  moral  meaning  of
conforming to law and violating it.
It is obvious why conspiracy theories are attractive in such a climate. They are
a way  of  explaining,  and  thus  making  more  tolerable, the  powerlessness
many  blacks  feel when they think of these hostile institutions.  And who  can
claim  that all these conspiracies  are mere figments  of the imagination?  It  is
hard to  imagine  what pathological  hatred  drove  the  then  director  of  the
Federal Bureau  of  Investigation,  J.  Edgar  Hoover;  it is  hard  to  believe  the
passion with  which  he  attempted  to  destroy  the  life  and  achievements  of
Martin Luther King, Jr. And yet, this conspiracy was all too real: Hoover really
had a  letter sent  to King which  suggested  he  commit  suicide  and  failed  to


39  Kennedy [1997] 26.


34 Thomas A. Schmitz

warn him of plots against  his  life.40 Other cases  are more difficult to assess.  I will quote  two  examples.  In  his  book  on  blacks  in  the  criminal  system,
Michael Tonry  quotes  a  study  showing  that  in  Georgia  "  blacks  who
killed whites were " twenty-two times more likely to be sentenced to death
than were  blacks  who  killed  blacks.41 Is  it possible  to  deny that  racist
prejudices play an  important  part  in this  variance?  Federal  law  in  the  US
requires  judges  to  treat  the  possession  of one  gram  of crack  cocaine  as
equivalent to the possession of one hundred grams  of powder cocaine.  While
defendants in  cases  involving  crack  cocaine  are  almost  invariably  black,
powder cocaine  used  to be the fashionable  drug for  (predominantly  white)
rich yuppies.42 Crack is hardly a hundred times more dangerous than powder
cocaine.  Is  the legal  disparity  between the two  drugs  an  example  of  racist
legislation? Legal  experts  deny this  accusation. 43 Yet  it is  easy  to  see why
many blacks  believe it  is  true, and  why  they  accept  even  more  outlandish
allegations. 44
" large percentages of black Americans  see contemporary crime and
drug policies as a near-genocidal effort by whites  to control blacks. "
A  New York  Times/WCBS-TV  poll  in  1990 found  that  29 percent  of
blacks (only 5 percent of whites)  thought  it was  true or might  be true
that the  HIV virus was  deliberately  created  in  a  laboratory  to  infect
black people, that 60 percent (16 percent of whites) believed it was  true
or might be true that government makes  drugs available  in  poor black
neighborhoods in order to harm  black people,  and  that  77  percent of
blacks believed  the government  singles  out  and  investigates  black
officials to discredit them.
It is easy to see why the climate of the fifties and sixties  fostered belief in such
theories. Kennedy's  observation  that  large  numbers  of  blacks  are  alienated
from the entire legal and political values of the American  society explains  the
almost visceral  distrust  that many  blacks  feel towards  the  standards  of the
white majority. The traumatic  consequences  of this  distrust  can  be observed
almost every day. When lawsuits pit blacks  against  whites, public  opinion  is
often sharply  divided  along  color  lines.  This  was  especially  visible  in  the
highly  publicized  case  of  the  black football  star  O. J.  Simpson  who  was


40  The chilling account of Hoover's machinations can now be found in Branch [1998]  528-9,
556-7; cf. Garrow [1981].
41  See Tonry [1995] 42, cf. Kennedy [1997] 328-50.
42  Tonry [1995] 41; Shipler [1997] 379-81.
43  See Kennedy [1997] 364-86.
44  Tonry [1995] 38.


Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 35


accused of having killed his (white) wife and was acquitted in October 1995, 45
but other cases, which are less well known outside of the US, gave evidence of
the same pattern of race loyalty. In 1990, Marion Barry, mayor of Washington,
D. C., was caught smoking  crack cocaine,  yet a majority of blacks  thought he
had been framed by white officials;  he was  reelected mayor in  1994.  In  1987,
Tawana Brawley, a black woman, claimed she had been raped by seven white
men; although  a grand jury decided that her story was  untrue, many  blacks
still are  convinced that  she  told  the  truth.46 The  most  violent  effects  of  this
calamitous situation  occurred  in  1992.  After  white  policemen  who  had
mistreated a black man were acquitted by a predominantly white jury, several
days of  furious  rioting  shook  the  city  of  Los  Angeles.47 Many  blacks
considered the trial and the acquittal unfair and saw  their deepest suspicions
about hidden racism in the legal system confirmed. And it would be difficult
to claim  that  they had  been entirely wrong:  images  of the  extreme brutality
that the police had used had been caught on videotape and  broadcast  all  over
the  country.  Accordingly,  a second  trial with a racially  less  uniform  jury
brought about the conviction  of the accused.  The conclusion  that racism  had
been  an important  factor in  the decision  the first  jury  had  reached  was
difficult to resist. And of course,  such  decisions  bring  back  memories  of the
scandalous injustices in the American legal system during the Jim Crow era.48
It is  understandable  that  this  black  distrust  extends  to  standards  in  the
sciences  and in scholarship  as well as to  the legal  and  political  system.  For
the underprivileged,  all  of  these  are  just  instruments  controlled  and
manipulated by  the  establishment,  instruments  whose  design  it  is  to
oppress and  intimidate  those who are not part of the elite. Again, those who
speak of the  eternal  truths  and  objective  criteria  of  scientific  and  scholarly
research should be aware that this  distrust  cannot  be dismissed  out of hand.
Not too long ago, objective research and racial science were used to prove
irrefutably the inferiority of all  non-white  races. Scholars  working in these
fields and  drawing  these  conclusions  were  as  convinced  of  the  validity  of
their work as  those  who  today declare  that  these  enterprises  should  not be
regarded as scientific research at all and that  their results  are void. Especially
people whose  own  education  in  such  matters  is  only  superficial  find  it
difficult to understand  why they should  trust the  results  of today's  scholars
any more than  those of yesterday. Unfortunately, great numbers  of blacks  in



45  Much ink  has  been spilled  on the  O.  J. Simpson case;  I  give  only  a  few  references:
Kennedy [1997] 286-92;  Shipler  [1997] 395-401,  esp.  397:  In  general,  two-thirds  of
whites thought Simpson was guilty, and two-thirds of blacks thought he was innocent.
46  On these and similar cases see Kennedy [1997] 7-8, 24-6; Shipler [1997] 324-7.
47  See Shipler [1997] 387-91.
48  See Kennedy [1997] 41-69. 36 Thomas A. Schmitz


the US still belong to this group because for economic and social reasons, they
are denied equal access to the educational system.

The Teaching of History and Identity Politics

One field in which the argument about accepted standards and the distrust  of
conventional criteria has been especially  strong is the study of history. Black
intellectuals have  been  pointing  to  historical  research  and  the  teaching  of
history in schools  as an  instrument  to subjugate blacks for a  long  time. In  a
book first  published  in  1933,  the  black  historian  Carter G. Woodson  (1875-
1950) writes,  The  educated  Negroes have  the  attitude  of  contempt  toward
their own people because " Negroes are taught to admire  the  Hebrew, the
Greek,  the Latin,  and  the Teuton  and  to  despise  the African.49 If  black
children, the argument goes, see their ancestors  in  their history classes  at all,
it will be as victims; hence, they cannot but feel inferior. It is thus a reasonable
demand that blacks be given their due share in history textbooks. They should
be shown not just as victims  and objects, but as subjects  of history, and their
contribution to American  and  world history ought  to be appreciated  so  that
black students can be proud of their own tradition and  have their own heroes
and role models.  A black,  African  Egypt50 and  the contributions  it made  to
human civilization are one important part of  this  effort to enhance  black self-
esteem.
Is it possible to insist  that such  historical  accounts  are untrue and  that  they
should not be taught, given the bleak conditions of life of large numbers  of the
black population,  given  the  poverty, violence  and  crime  that  many  blacks
have to face every day? Somebody holding the view that such  myths  ought to
be  banned  from  schools  can  easily  be  perceived  as  a nitpicker,  a pure
academic who sits  in his  ivory tower and has  lost touch with the realities  of
everyday life. Let's  be honest.  Suppose  that  teaching  Afrocentrist  myths  in
schools could save a mere ten or even five percent of black youths from social
decline,  poverty and  crime.  In  this  case, who  could  presume to  ban these




49 Woodson, The Mis-Education of the  Negro, quoted in Shipler [1997]  208;  cf. Early  [1994]. Similar views can be found in an  essay  written by Garvey in 1923,  see the quotation
in Lefkowitz, [1996] 7.
50 It should be mentioned that  Egyptians are not always  happy  with this  picture,  see  the
reaction of Egypt's cultural emissary to the US in 1988: This is an Egyptian heritage and
an  Egyptian civilization 100  percent. We are part  of  the  African  continent.  We  cannot
say  by any means that we are black  or  white.  We  are Egyptian,  with  our culture and
traditions and religions; quoted in Levine [1989] 11 n. 3; cf. Roth [1996] 315.


Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 37


myths and instead  teach  the historical  truth?51 Moreover, we have  to admit
that often, it would be irresponsible to answer for the absolute accuracy of this
truth, given the scarce  and  frequently ambiguous  documents  which  we have
to interpret.
However, we have to ask whether the underlying presupposition is valid. The
mechanism of influencing  the thought and  behavior of contemporary society
by manipulating  their  perception  of the  past  is  not  a  new  invention.  When
Plato thought about his ideal state in the fourth century BCE, he already made
use of this  instrument.  The  guards  and  all  citizens  of  his  state  have  to  be
persuaded that the earth brought them forth and that they are all brothers and
sisters.52 This  noble lie  will  teach them to fight for their  state  and  for each
other. Yet  Plato's  use  of  this  means  highlights  the  problems  it  entails.
Applying this method is possible  only in a  strictly  hierarchical  society  such
as Plato's ideal community, in which a small group  of philosophers  has  seen
truth itself and  the  highest  good. These  sages,  then,  are  allowed  to use  this
noble lie because they have absolute, certain knowledge of what is  best for the
state and  for its citizens.  In  a  democratic  society,  on  the  other hand,  such  a
manipulation of history is extremely problematic.  A democracy  is  based  on
rational and  open  discussion  and  on the  idea  that different  opinions  in
society ought to be mediated via debate, compromise  and  voting. Assuming
that some members of the body politic have more knowledge and  accordingly
a right to manipulate  their fellow citizens  is  suitable  for totalitarian  societies
only.
Therefore, critics  of Afrocentrist  teaching  have  time  and  again  asked  what
will happen  when young people who have been brought up in  this  fictitious
tradition some day discover that they have been told myths, not history. Will
this discovery  bolster  their  self-esteem?53 Furthermore, we have  to  question
whether  the  goal  of strengthening  blacks'  self-image  can  be achieved  this
way.  As  Nathan  Glazer writes,  What  little  evidence  we have  on  the
correlation between self-esteem  and  educational  achievement  is  murky and



51  Cf. the thoughtful remarks of Ray [1997] 3-4.
52 Plato, State 414 b-e. This passage had already been adduced by Lefkowitz [1996] 21.
53  See Jenkyns [1998] 52: There are good, high-minded arguments against the fabrication of
the past: we think it contrary to  our dignity to  shy away  from the truth, and  it  is  surely
condescending to other  peoples to suppose  that  they  cannot  manage  without  the
consolations of self-deception. But if high-mindedness fails to persuade, perhaps  we can
appeal to enlightened self-interest. One simple argument against heritage myths is  that  in
the long run, they do not work: you cannot fool people all of  the time; you have to  shout
ever louder to obscure the voice of  doubt,  and  the angriness of  much nationalist  rhetoric
is the angriness of fear.


38 Thomas A. Schmitz


inconclusive. 54 Not  only  is  the intrinsic  functioning  of  this  process
questionable, there is also every reason  to suspect  that the fierce debate about
the teaching of history is a mere pretense. Concentrating on such  issues  helps
politicians avoid the real problems that are at stake: the untenable economical
and social  conditions  many  blacks (and  whites)  still  have  to cope  with.  Yet
after the conservative  revolution of the eighties, it has  become increasingly
unpopular in the US to face such concrete problems when it is  so much  more
convenient  to  point a finger  at  symbols  with strong  emotional  appeal.55
Unfortunately, some blacks  have been taken in by this  strategy. However, K.
Anthony Appiah,  who teaches  philosophy  and  African-American  Studies at
Harvard University, is certainly right to point out, No amount  of knowledge
of the  architectural  achievements  of  Nubia  or  Kush  guarantees  respect  for
African-Americans. No  African-American  is  entitled  to  greater  concern
because he  is  descended  from  a people  who created  jazz  or produced  Toni
Morrison. Culture is not the problem, and it is not the solution.56
Despite such calls to remain cool-headed, the  question of how history should
be taught in American  high  schools  and  colleges has  been the field of one of
the fiercest battles in these culture wars.  In  the sixties,  civil rights activists
scrutinized the textbooks that were used to teach  history, and  they found that
they tended  to suppress  the  achievements  of  ethnic  or  religious  minorities
and of  women.  There  can  be  no  doubt  that  history  as  it was  taught  in
American (and,  for that matter, European) schools  gave a distorted vision by
privileging the white  male  view. Conservative  thinkers  often seem  to imply
that all the modern fuss about such matters will only serve to lower standards
and teach myths  instead  of hard  facts. However, Alexander Stille, in  a recent
review of history  textbooks, rightly  argues  against  a  nostalgic  vision  of  the
teaching of history in past decades:57
Before we bemoan  the  decline  of American history textbooks  "  we
must recall how biased  almost  all  children's  history  books were until


54  Glazer [1997] 54; cf. Chavez [1994] 5-6; Early [1994] 14-5.
55 Cf.  Gates  [1989]:  " it  sometimes seems  that  blacks  are  doing better  in  the  college
curriculum than they are in the streets or even on the campuses. A similar point  is made
by Levine [1992a]  453.  She writes about  the stolen-legacy-approach:  Thus the story
is told in terms that channel contemporary frustrations and anger away from their proper
objects toward imagined despoilment in classical antiquity.  See also  Walker [1994]  35-
6. Cf. Lilla [1998] 4-7, who compares the cultural revolution during  the sixties  and  the
economic  revolution  during the  eighties  and concludes:  the  cultural  and Reagan
revolution took  place  within a  single generation and  have proved to  be complementary,
not contradictory.
56  Appiah [1997] 36.
57  Stille [1998] 18.


Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 39


about thirty years ago. " there was  never a  golden  age  of textbooks.
" practically  all  of them are openly biased and  extremely narrow  in
their historical range. " The Indians  are often referred to as  savages'
who had to make way for civilization.  Some books take a tolerant view
of slavery, portraying Reconstruction  as  a time of black corruption and
disorder, and praising the rise of the Ku Klux Klan.
Yet he also  warns  against  going  too far  to  the  other extreme: That  a  black
man was among the first to die in the American Revolution is  certainly worth
attention; so is the fact that he had been ignored by previous textbooks. But the
heavy emphasis  on Crispus  Attucks to the neglect of other important  figures
is a  classic  example  of  the  current  tendency  to political  orthodoxy  and
homogeneity.
It is indubitably  justified  to demand  that  hitherto  neglected groups  such  as
ethnic minorities,  women  or  the  working  classes  be  given their  legitimate
share,  that  their  part  of  history  be  mentioned  and analyzed,  and most
American textbooks now  attempt  to right  past  wrongs  by emphasizing  the
historical  role of blacks  and  native Americans,  by telling  not  only  history,
but also herstory. European colonization  is no longer seen as  an  altogether
glorious achievement, and different perspectives are acknowledged. None but
the most extreme conservative critics  would reject this  revision of traditional
historical canons  that  Appiah  calls  liberal  multiculturalism. 58 Yet  some
adherents  of revisions  make larger  claims  and  end  up  with a position  that
Appiah terms illiberal  multiculturalism.  Not content with corrections  and
revisions  of  traditional historiography,  they  hold  that objective  history is
impossible:  all history  books  are  written by  the victors  and  serve  as  a
retrospective justification  for their deeds. Hence, they claim  that  every group
in society be allowed  to teach  its own version of history in order to define its
authentic identity  and  to  bolster  the  self-consciousness  of  its  members.
Afrocentrists are  merely  the  most  vociferous  proponents  of  these  identity
politics, and  attention in  this  highly  publicized  debate has concentrated  on
their teachings. Whenever history curricula  for school  districts  or states were
discussed,  the reaction focused in on Afrocentrist positions.  Two of the most
notorious debates, pursued over many  years and  in  many  media,  exemplify
this tendency:  the  controversies  about  the  African-American Baseline  Essays
adopted at Portland,  Oregon, and  about  the new  social  studies  curricula  in
New York State.59



58  Appiah [1997] 33.
59 On  the  Baseline Essays, especially  the  gross  factual  errors  they  contained,  see  Martel
[1994],  Shipler [1997]  196-200;  on the New York controversy see  Glazer  [1997]  22-33.


40 Thomas A. Schmitz


The Controversy about Historical Standards and Methods

Most Afrocentrists  claim  that  they are  not  merely telling  myths  in  order  to
heighten blacks' self-esteem, but that their version of history is true. Engaging
them in  a  scholarly  debate  has  proven  excessively  difficult  for many
traditional historians.  The  Afrocentrists'  line  of  defense  has  either  been  to
assert that a sinister  conspiracy  of white historians  has  constantly  worked to
conceal this  truth. Accordingly, they claim  that  lack  of documentation  does
corroborate, not  weaken  their  tenets  as  it  proves  the  machinations  of  this
conspiracy. 60 White  historians  have  distorted  or  destroyed  evidence  and
developed historical  methods  which  are  merely  tools  for oppressing  the
concealed truth. Or the  Afrocentrists  recur  to  the  relativistic  argument  that
there are several truths which  are all  equally valid. This  latter argument  can
be tied  to  a  widespread  feeling  of uneasiness  about  concepts  such  as
objective truth or historical facts.61 These sentiments  have been voiced in
many fields of the humanities (and even of the sciences)  since  the late sixties;
they are  attacks  against  the  hidden  agenda  and  political  implications  of
positivism and  historicism,  which  are  often  labeled  restrictive  and
ideological. Although it is impossible  to pinpoint  the  precise  origin  of these
attacks, we can  at least name  several developments that  have  contributed  to
their diffusion:
1. When Jacques  Derrida  published  his  Of Grammatology in  1967,  he
coined the well-known  phrase  There is nothing  outside of the  text.62
Derrida wanted to point to the difficulties we face when we try to reach
reality, the referents, via  the  linguistic  signs  of  a  text; he  certainly  did
not  want  to  deny the existence  of  the extratextual  world. Yet  later
accounts of  deconstruction  made  Derrida's  statement sound  more
unambiguous. As,  e.g., Vincent  B.  Leitch  writes,  The  world  is  text.
Nothing stands  behind.  "  There  are  no  facts as  such,  only
assemblages. There is always already  only interpretation.63 In  a world
One can also compare the debate about national history standards  in 1995-6,  see Glazer
[1997] 66-73 and Nash/Crabtree/Dunn [1997].



60  See Lefkowitz [1997] 137.
61  Bernal refers explicitly to the liberal loss of  faith  in the mystique science' and  the deep
suspicion of positivism since the 1960s (Bernal [1987] 437).
62  Derrida [1974] 158, cf. 163. See the original  French version, Derrida  [1967]  227  Il n'y a
pas de hors-texte, and 233 Il n'y a rien hors du texte.
63  Leitch [1983] 58. Against, see the more circumspect explanation in Norris  [1991]  146-58.
By acknowledging  this affiliation,  I  do  not  mean to  endorse  the  unacceptable
generalizations made by some conservative critics,  cf.  Early  [1994]  13:  "  the  rise  of
everyone from  Jacques  Derrida  to  Stephen  Greenblatt  has  been  just  as  important  to
Afrocentrism and its off-shoot, multiculturalism, as the political turmoil of the 1960s.


Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 41


where no facts  exist,  it  obviously  makes  no  sense  to ask  for historical
truths.
2. One variety of this belief which has been especially influential in the US
was developed  by  Stanley  Fish.  His  position  could  be  described  as
Deconstruction Meets  Reader-Response  Criticism. In  a  number of
widely read articles and  books, Fish  has  argued that it is impossible  to
differentiate between raw facts and their interpretations.64 Whenever we
look at something, we employ the strategies and  filters with which  our
interpretive community provides us. Of course, raw uninterpreted facts
do exist, yet we have no access to them because we cannot  choose to be
outside of all  interpretive communities  (the most  we can  do  is  to  see
something from more than  one perspective). Fish  does not address  the
problem  of how  criteria  could  be developed  that  would  allow  us  to
evaluate divergent interpretations. Hence, his  position  inevitably  leads
to an all encompassing  relativism  in  which  facts  are  inaccessible  and
the interpretations  of different interpretive communities  all  have  equal
truth-value.
3. In the field of historiography, the most important  arguments  have been
put forward by Hayden White. Since the seventies, White has published
a number of articles  and  books which  argue that historiography  ought
to  be  understood  and analyzed  as a  form of  rhetoric.  According  to
White, our perception and  description  of events is  directed by the rules
and laws of narrative. Historical  facts  are not given, they are construed
by the observer (and narrator) in  telling. Though White  has  repeatedly
defended himself against the objection of being a relativist and making
historical studies  helpless  against  revisionist  accounts  which  would,
e.g., deny  that  the  Holocaust  ever  happened,65 I  find  it difficult  to
understand how his arguments could avoid being relativistic. Whatever
his own intent, it is obvious that his position can be (mis-)used by those
who want to argue that all historical accounts have equal value.66
4. Finally, the theses of the historian  of science  Thomas  Kuhn67 have been
read as  showing  that  every  scientific  understanding  is  merely  one
possible paradigm  that can  be replaced by another one. If  scientific
theories can only be judged within the context of a particular  paradigm,


64  A point also made by Bernal, see Bernal [1991] 65.
65  E.g., White [1987] 76-82.
66  On White's theses, see Momigliano [1981] 259-68.
67  Especially in Kuhn [1970].


42 Thomas A. Schmitz

then in this  respect the scientific  theories of any one  paradigm  are  not
privileged over other ways of looking at the world, such  as shamanism
or astrology  or creationism.  If  the  transition  from  one  paradigm  to
another cannot  be judged by any external standard,  then  perhaps  it  is
culture rather than  nature  that  dictates  the  content  of  scientific
theories.68 Scholars  outside  of the  sciences  have  made  use  of Kuhn's
model  to  argue  that  there  is  no  such  thing  as reality,  and have
repeatedly claimed  that  if  hard  sciences  doubt about  the  truth,  it
follows  a fortiori  that the  humanities  should  abandon  all  hope  of
attaining truth. This discussion came to the attention of a wider reading
public in 1996, when Alan D. Sokal,  a physicist,  published  an  article in
the journal  Social Text that  purportedly showed  that  modern  physics
had given up  the  notion  of an unalterable reality.69 As  Sokal  himself
later revealed, this  article  had been a  spoof  meant to demonstrate  the
absurdity of all such claims.70 A highly publicized debate discussed  the
consequences of what is now widely known as Sokal's Hoax.71
Some conservative critics  have certainly drawn  an  exaggerated picture of the
influence of such relativistic beliefs in  the American  academe  (and have thus
fallen victim to  a  conspiracy  paranoia  of their  own,  with  the  dark  forces  of
some unspecified  leftism  threatening  to take  over  the  country).72 Such
opinions  were never undisputed, and  their proponents  certainly  constituted
only a  minority  of  American  intellectuals  and  academics.  Yet  we  have  to
acknowledge that these proponents  were unusually  vociferous and  canny  in
claiming a  high  degree of public  attention  for their  provocative theses.  The
nineties, however, have witnessed a considerable decline of academic  success
for such ideas. A malevolent observer might draw the conclusion  that at least
some of those  who  had  been eager to provoke  the  academic  establishment
calmed down  as  soon  as  they  had  themselves  become  part of  this
establishment. Furthermore, during the last years, there has been a number of
well-informed and  persuasive  attacks  on  the  kinds  of  relativism  described
above, in fields as diverse as the sciences, the law and the humanities.73


68 Weinberg [1998].
69 Sokal  [1996a].  Sokal's  article  has  been  reprinted  and  expanded  in  Sokal/Bricmont
[1998].
70 Sokal  [1996].
71  See Weinberg [1996].
72 This is visible in, e.g., Gross/Levitt  [1994]  or Ellis [1989].  For  classical  studies,  cf.  the
sweeping and vitriolic attack in Hanson/Heath [1998].
73  To quote just a few examples: Gross/Levitt/Lewis  [1996];  Farber/Sherry [1997];  Harris
[1996]. See also Crews [1998] and the ensuing debate in NYRB October 8, 1998, 53-6.  Of
course,  the debate  is  far  from  being over,  see the lively exchange  about  Gross/Levitt
[1994] between Gross/Levitt and Richard Lewontin in NYRB December 3, 1998, 59-60.


Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 43


Yet we find here a frequent phenomenon: ideas  gain  acceptance  with a wider
public precisely  at  the  moment  when they  are  abandoned  or strongly
modified by the experts in  the field, and  of course, they are accepted  in  their
most crudely  simplified  and  superficial  form. The  slogan  All  history  is
written by the victors;  there is  no  objective  truth  may  no  longer  be  taken
seriously by historians, yet it has become commonplace with some journalists
and advocates for special-interest groups. Such tenets are especially useful  for
any kind  of  revisionist  historiography.  Afrocentrists  use  these  slogans  to
dismiss not  only  the  results  of  traditional historical  studies,  but  also  their
methods, claiming  that  they are  merely  tools  of  oppression.  In  their  view,
every group has  a right to its  own  truth  that  cannot  be gauged  by allegedly
objective scholarly criteria. As Constance Hilliard said in an interview, Truth
isn't  something  you find  by marching  into  a  library  ";  you have  to open
your soul.74
For those  who  belong  to  the  academic  establishment,  it  is  not  easy  to
understand this  assault  on  scholarly  methods  and  to  argue  against  its
proponents. Of course,  Afrocentrists  and  their  adherents  can  always  claim
that someone  attacking  their  theses  is  merely  pleading  for his  or  her  own
interests, not trying to reach a truth whose very existence  they deny. I think
the most successful  strategy to reopen a discussion  that has  all  too often run
the risk of ending in complete mutual  misunderstanding  might be to appeal
not to  lofty  standards  and  allegedly  impartial  methodologies,  but  to
enlightened self-interest. I wonder if those who want to dismiss  all  standards
of objectivity, or to be more modest: all means  to negotiate  between different
claims  to truth, are really aware of the consequences  of what  they are  doing.
First  of all,  accepting  that  every group's  view of history  is  as  valid  as  any
other's means  throwing the door wide open  to new  racisms  of all  kinds75 
and  I  do not  accept  the premise  that  blacks  cannot  be racists  because  they
have not enough power to oppress  other groups.76 When Leonard Jeffries, an
Afrocentrist who  teaches  at  the  City  College  of  New  York,  differentiates
between creative African sun people and destructive, violent European ice


74 Dembner [1996].
75  See Lefkowitz [1997] 52.
76  This view is held, e.g., by Coleman Young, the mayor of Detroit, see Hacker [1992] 29; cf.
Shipler [1997] 460: Many blacks define racism as prejudice plus power, thereby  labeling
the practice  so that  it  lies  beyond  the  reach  of powerless  people  like  themselves. "
Many blacks  have used [this  definition] to  confer a  kind of  immunity on  themselves, a
permission to be  racist  without  admitting to it.  I  think  this  view should be  rejected
because it  entails  a  one-dimensional view of  power  that  cannot  be  accepted:  power
cannot be equated with institutionalized political might; it occurs at  all  points  of  society
in a decentralized way. Most blacks may have less power than most whites,  but they are
certainly not totally deprived of it.



44 Thomas A. Schmitz

people, this  is  ugly  and  abominable  racism; 77 when  Mary  Lefkowitz's
colleague at  Wellesley, Tony  Martin,  calls  her  books a Jewish  onslaught,
this is Antisemitism, a special form of racism.78 Critics of Afrocentrism rightly
point  out  that  its  theories  are  Eurocentric in  their  own way,79 as  can  be
observed in Bernal's  project and  the warm welcome Afrocentrists have given
it: It  is simply  another form of colonialism  to insist  that  the  Egyptians  and
Phoenicians have  value  only  if  they  taught  the  Greeks  civilization.' 80 As
Richard Jenkyns  writes,  no  one  cares  a  straw  that  Britain's  influence  on
ancient Greece  was  nil.  It  is  because  blacks  are,  seemingly,  outside the
traditional European story that Bernal wants to find them a place  in  that sun;
and however well-meaning this aim, it can hardly help being patronizing.81
Moreover, it  could  be argued  that  the  importance  of race  in  Afrocentrist
theories works  within  the  tradition  of  Romantic  or  even  racist  ideals  that
Afrocentrists try to eschew. Modern psychological  research  has  taught us the
importance  of memory  for our personal  identity. We perceive our past  as  a
meaningful narrative that explains why and how we became who we are; our
identity is formed by what we perceive as  the story line  of our life. This may
seem uncontroversial.  Yet the idea  that  our entire  personality,  our behavior,
talents and skills,  our whole life is shaped  by the history  of our people  or
race is a figment  of Romantic  ideology. Do only blacks  have the right to be
proud of the achievements  of other blacks;  can  Germans  and  only  Germans
understand  and appreciate Beethoven's  music;  may  only  Dubliners  read
Ulysses? These tenets strike me as  ludicrous  and, yes, racist, yet they seem to
underlie Afrocentrist  ideas.82 When  we accept  the theory  that  our group
defines our identity and  our truth,  there is  hardly  a  way  of avoiding  a  new
tribalism in  which  every dialogue  between  members  of  different  groups  is



77  On Jeffries' theories, see Hacker [1992] 28-9; Shipler [1997] 234; Gates [1991] 47: Bogus
theories of sun' and ice' people,  and  the invidious scapegoating of  other ethnic groups,
only resurrects the worst  of  19th-century  racist  pseudoscience which too  many of  the
pharaohs  of  Afrocentrism' have accepted  without realizing. In the meantime, the City
University of  New York (of  which  City  College  is  a  part)  has  brought legal  actions
against Jeffries who is  not allowed to  teach  his theories in the classroom any  more, see
Lefkowitz [1997] 172-4 and Glazer [1995] 14-40.
78  Martin [1993], cf. Ringle [1996]. On black Anti-Semitism, see Shipler [1997] 464-5.
79 E.g.,  Walker  [1994]  34-5:  "  Afrocentrism  actually  fails  to  transcend  European
categories of  race,  class,  and  culture. " Ultimately,  Afrocentrism  is  Eurocentrism in
blackface. It  repeats  what  it  sets  out to  repudiate.  Cf.  Roth [1996] 318,  Ray [1997] 4,
Lenz [1993].
80  Rogers [1996]  442;  cf.  Baines  [1996] 45;  Jenkyns  [1996] 419-20;  Jenkyns  [1998] 52;
McNeal [1993] 138-9.
81  Jenkyns [1996] 420; cf. Baines [1996] 45, Lefkowitz [1997] 156.
82  See Lenz [1993].


Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 45

impossible. 83 I am certainly in no position  to prescribe  or even suggest how
underprivileged and discriminated groups should react; I merely wonder if it
would not  be  wiser and  more  effective to  cheerfully  state  that  a  heritage
cannot be stolen, that the Greek (and the Kushite and the Chinese) civilization
belongs to all of us.84
However, the Afrocentrist claims entail calamitous consequences  not only for
society as  a  whole,  but also  for the  minorities  themselves.  This  can  best be
shown when we look at the example of the so-called Melanists.85 Adherents of
this theory claim that blacks process information differently from whites, and
that therefore, they should be taught in a different manner.  Again, we see that
race is the decisive factor. No one would deny that the scholarly  performance
of children  from  socially  disadvantaged  families  can  be  improved  when
teachers adapt  their methods to these  students'  special  needs,  e.g., by using
less abstract language  or  by  giving  strong  encouragement.  Yet  the entire
functioning of modern societies  is based on the consensus  that  all  men  are
created equal,  that  race  does  not  affect  our mental  capabilities.  The
emancipation of blacks  in the US would never have happened  if it had  been
impossible to convince large  numbers  of white  intellectuals  and  politicians
that a person's  dignity, freedom and  intellect does not depend  on  his  or her
skin color. Melanists  who  proclaim  a  new  essentialism  jeopardize  this
consensus and the  cohesion  of the entire society. If blacks  are fundamentally
different from  whites,  why  should  whites,  who  still  hold  more  social
privileges, be willing to share these privileges and grant blacks equal access to
political power  and  educational  facilities? It  is  but  a  small  step  from
accepting that blacks  think  in  a  different way  to believing  that  their mental
capabilities are inferior, as has convincingly been argued by David Nicholson
in 1990:  Material  given  to teachers  by the  Multicultural/Multiethnic
Education Office of the  Portland,  Ore.,  Public  Schools,  for  example,  quotes
psychologist Na'im  Akbar that  the  black  child  uses  language  requiring  a
wide use  of  many  coined  interjections  (sometimes  profanity)' an
observation  that  probably  would  be roundly  condemned  if  made  by a
white.86 Such  convictions  are  indeed  worthy  of  the  worst  white
supremacists. The  arguments  of  the  Melanists  are  yet  another  path  to  the
tribalization of the US described by Nicholson,87 and blacks have nothing to
win, but a lot to lose from this way of thinking.


83  See Minow [1997].
84  As has been suggested by Lefkowitz [1996] 22.
85  See Flint [1994], Ringle [1996], Shipler [1997] 234; cf. Hacker [1992] 171-2.
86  Nicholson [1990]. On the debate about  black  English or Ebonics,  see Shipler [1997]
75-8.
87  Nicholson [1990]; cf. Chavez [1994] 10.



46 Thomas A. Schmitz

This is not to say that all of Afrocentrism's aims and  interests are illegitimate.
Most scholars agree that if we subtract the conspiracy  paranoia  and unsound
scholarly methods, interest in and  teaching  of the  achievements  of Egyptian
and other African  civilizations  can  serve meaningful  purposes,  as  has  been
argued by the  Egyptologist Ann  Macy  Roth  in  one  of  the  most  thoughtful
contributions to the  entire  debate. She  rightly  reminds  us  that  some  white
extremists still entertain the absurd  idea that Africans  contributed nothing  to
human civilization. " the Pennsylvania chapters of the Ku Klux Klan give
each new  member  a  leather-bound  book  with  the  gilded  title  Great
Achievements of  the  Black  Race, which  is  filled  entirely  with  blank  pages.88
Even if white-supremacist  views such  as  this  one are today on the fringes of
American society,89 black children will inevitably encounter similar  opinions,
be it in scholarly  or literary works or in everyday hate speech. Knowledge of
the real (as opposed to invented) accomplishments  of African  peoples can  be
an immensely effective antidote against  such  absurd  and  racist  allegations.  I
would argue that in this context, it is unproblematic  to reclaim  ancient  Egypt
as a black  civilization.  The argument that Wilson  Moses has  put  forward,
In fact  many  of  the  Pharaohs,  if  transplanted  across  time  and  onto  the
Chattanooga  Choo-Choo  in  1945,  would have  a hard  time  obtaining  a
Pullman berth or being seated in a dining car,90 is indeed valid not because
the term black and white can be ascribed to the Egyptians then or now in
any meaningful  way  (see nn.  50  and  103),  but because it  demonstrates  the
utter absurdity of modern racist definitions of black, especially the one-drop-
rule that  makes  a  person  black  if  any  of his  ancestors  was  of African
descent.91
However,  even  such  a  mitigated version  of Afrocentrism  will  have  to  be
administered carefully lest it result in a vitriolic calculation  of which  race
gave which  contribution to humanity.  It can  only be a first  step  towards  the
acknowledgement  that  ultimately,  no one  can  derive prerogatives  from  the
accomplishments of his real or imagined forebears. And it is  to be feared that
arriving at  such  a reasonable  Afrocentrism  will  be  a long  and  arduous
process. The debate has become too emotional and sharp, and both sides have
become entrenched in their mutual  distrust. Bernal's   book, to which  we will
now come back, is unfortunately a case in point.



88  Roth [1996] 317.
89 However, prejudices that  blacks  are lazy  and somehow less  intelligent than  whites  die
hard, see  Shipler  [1996]  278  and  ibd. 283-8  on  the  enormous  debate  about
Herrnstein/Murray [1994].
90  Sundiata [1996]; cf. Roth [1996] 319.
91 See  Njeri  [1992].  On  the  one-drop-rule,  Shipler  [1997]  112  rightly remarks:  In  this
regard, the United States remains firmly locked in the eighteenth century.


Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 47


Bernal's  Place in the Debate

Although Bernal  claims  that  he  reached  his  conclusions  before he  became
aware of the work of early proponents of Afrocentrist theories such  as George
G. M. James,  he sees these scholars  as  his  intellectual  harbingers  (see Bernal
[1987]  401-2).  And  it is  easy  to  perceive  the common  elements:  like the
Afrocentrists, Bernal  believes  in  a  sinister  conspiracy  of  white  (Aryanist)
historians that  has  obliterated the  truth;  like them  he  is  convinced  that  the
scholarly methods  developed in  the  nineteenth  century  are  merely  tools  to
accomplish this  goal.92  And  of course,  the  picture  he  draws  of the
Mediterranean during the bronze age coincides  with the Afrocentrist view of
history:  civilization  began  with  the  black peoples in  Africa;  it  has
subsequently been stolen by the Europeans.
Furthermore, our knowledge of the  background  will  help  us  understand  to
which audience  Black Athena is  addressed.  One  of  the  most  unfortunate
misunderstandings in the whole debate has  been the  tendency  to view it  in
terms of  progressive  vs.  conservative.  By  stating  that  the  political
purpose of Black Athena is, of course, to lessen  European  cultural  arrogance
(Bernal [1987]  73),  Bernal  gave  the  impression  of  being  a natural  ally  for
progressive thinkers involved in post-colonial projects. The fact that a number
of critical  responses  to  his  work was  published  in  conservative  periodicals
(such as  The New Republic or the Wall Street Journal) and  that  these  criticisms
were embraced by right-wing commentators (such as George Will93 and Roger
Kimball) contributed significantly to this impression. With what can be called
a visceral  reaction, academics  who consider  themselves  progressive  or  left-
wing seem to  have  taken  sides  in  this  debate.  Somebody  who  had  been
attacked by these  known  conservatives  had  to be right.  Accordingly,  Bernal
was praised by scholars like David Halperin, John Winkler and Froma Zeitlin
or Shelley Haley.94
Yet we  should  take a  closer  look at  what  Bernal  terms  a  matter  of  course.
When he writes that his  aim  is to lessen  European  cultural  arrogance,  we
have to ask whose arrogance he is referring to. Today, the (almost  obsessive)
need to  ground  one's  present  in  tradition  and  to  reclaim  an  (artificial)
Western civilization as one's own heritage is  an  American,  not a European
phenomenon. Bernal is  attacking  part  of the  academic  and  political  .lite  in
the US.  Yet  he  must  have  been  aware  that  the  cultural  arrogance  of  these



92  See Bernal [1987] 221 on source criticism.
93  Will [1996] 78.
94  Halperin/Winkler/Zeitlin [1990] 5; Haley [1993] 30 and 39 n. 10.



48 Thomas A. Schmitz

people  is  in  no  way  apt  to  be diminished  by his  hypotheses the  critical
reception of Black Athena has shown that  the  opposite  is  the  case;  criticism
against Bernal's  arguments has rather welded together conservative members
of the establishment. With this conveniently vague formulation, Bernal tries to
achieve an  altogether different aim:  he wants  to muster up support  from  his
own constituency  by presenting them  a  common  enemy.  It  is  depressing  to
see that  so  far,  a  number  of  liberal  academics  has  swallowed  this  bait.  I
would thus  argue  that Bernal's   aim  in  Black Athena is  not  an  attempt  to
convince by  making  verifiable  arguments,  but  an  appeal  to  emotions,
addressed to a specific audience.
Accordingly, I  would  suggest  that  large  parts  of  Black Athena ought  to be
analyzed according  to  rhetorical,  not  scholarly  standards. 95 In  his  book,
Bernal  is  not  primarily writing  for  those who  are  interested  in  the  early
history of  the  Mediterranean  and  want  to  know  more  about  the  relation
between Egypt  and  Greece;  instead,  the  public  he  is  aiming  at  is  already
certain  of the  truth  of his  theses  and  needs  to  be  reassured  with  attacks
against a  common  enemy.  It  is  within  this  framework  that  a  number  of
unusual characteristics  of  Black Athena can  be  understood.  I  give  a  few
examples only.

Bernal uses the term Indo-European to refer to the family  of languages,  but
he  often implies  that there is  such  a thing  as  a people  of Indo-European-
speaking Indo-Europeans  (Bernal  [1991]  67).  Using  the  term  Indo-
Europeans may  be  a  convenient  short-hand  to  avoid  the  cumbersome
speakers  of a  variety of Indo-European,  yet reviewers were right  to point
out that Bernal's  confusion  of linguistic  and  ethnic  (or even racial)  categories
is neither innocent nor inconsequential, 96 as  is shown  by his  use of the terms
Aryan or Aryanist. 97 Of course, he is aware of the  political  implications
these words have at one point, he makes  them  explicit  when  he speaks  of
the Aryanist  or even Nazi  image of the Indo-Europeans  as  a master  race'
(Bernal [1991]  322).  When  Bernal  calls  a scholar  Aryanist  or  even  the
extreme Aryanist  Francis Vian  (Bernal [1991]  192),  this  is  clearly  a form  of
hate speech  carrying  with  it  a  host  of  despicable  connotations:  these
scholars dream  of a conquering .lite (Bernal [1991]  348);  they succumb  to
the power  of  the  Aryanist  imagination  (Bernal  [1991]  465)  and  to  the


95 Cf.  Assmann  [1992]  929:  Meiner Meinung nach  geh.rt Black Athena zum 
politischen,
nicht zum wissenschaftlichen Diskurs.
96  Jasanoff/Nussbaum [1996] 180.
97 Against  Bernal's   use  of  these  words,  see  the  protest  of  Coleman  [1996]  290;  on  the
modern history of the term Aryan see Wieseh.fer [1990].


Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 49

irresistible  appeal  of  linking  the arrival  of  the Indo-Europeans  to  the
arrival  in  Greece of the  chariot that  symbol  of the  master  race'  (Bernal
[1991] 399).  The  same insinuation  can  be  observed  when  Bernal  counters
Lefkowitz's demonstration  that  Socrates was  an  Athenian  citizen  with  the
statement that he did not necessarily have an  impeccable  European lineage.98
Again, the  adjective  impeccable  surreptitiously  intimates  that  Lefkowitz
would consider African ancestors some kind of fault.
As we  have seen,  Bernal  depicts  these  scholars  as  not  merely  holding
opinions differing  from  his  own,  but  also  as  being  fascist  proponents  of
Aryan supremacy. This rhetorical strategy can be seen at work when Bernal
writes  about  the supposedly  Egyptian  scarabs  found  in  the tomb of  the
Frankish king  Childeric: a contemporary  French scholar  who doubts  their
existence is insidiously  connected with the fascist  Vichy r.gime, for no  good
reason as  Palter  rightly  says,  this  is  not  only  farfetched but approaches
defamation. 99 This  strategy  of  calumniating  other  scholars  reaches  its
unsavory  climax  in  the  heading  of chapter  9  of Bernal  [1987],  The  Final
Solution of the Phoenician Problem. This sly reference to Hitler's  genocide of
the European Jews is  absolutely unacceptable,  and  I am deeply shocked that
the editors of Rutgers University Press let it pass.
Bernal is thus eager to convey the impression  that  what  he  is  writing  about
are not scholarly  controversies, but  acts  of war,  and  the  vocabulary  he  uses
strengthens this impression. Again and again, Bernal uses martial  metaphors
to describe discussions:  his  is  a world in which  reviewers want to blast  his
ideas out of the water,100 in which  hypotheses are blown sky high  (Bernal
[1991] 480),  hostile writers101 scrutinize  each  others'  work  in  a  hostile
way (Bernal [1987] 162) and scholars are guided  by emotions  of love (Bernal
[1987] 118) or hatred (Bernal [1987] 107). In brief, Bernal is constantly  catering
to the Afrocentrist  view that  somehow,  most  scholars  are  involved  in  some
kind of world-wide  conspiracy. 102 To give one particularly  obvious  example:
Bernal mentions in passing the  short-lived  Egyptian empire of Mohamed Ali
in the  early  nineteenth  century  (Bernal  [1987]  249-50).  He is surprised  that
this empire  is  not  referred to  in  the writings  of  ancient  historians  (Bernal
[1987] 250).



98 Bernal  [1994].
99  Bernal [1987] 466-7 n.  88;  Palter  [1996]  351.  See also  Weinstein [1992]  383  on Bernal's 
none-too-subtle intimations of racism and anti-Semitism on the part  of  those who hold
opposing views.
100  Quoted in Dembner [1996].
101  Bernal [1989] 32.
102  Cf. Tritle [1992] 308-9.



50 Thomas A. Schmitz

The failure on the part of contemporary  ancient  historians  to mention
the contemporary  Egyptian  successes  in  general,  and  conquests  in
Greece in particular, cannot be entirely explained  away on the grounds
that recent events are no  concern  of the  professional  historian,  or  that
there had been a complete rupture in Egyptian history with the coming
of Islam. " The reason for the double standard is obviously racist.
Again, this is patent nonsense, and it  is  slander.  We might as  well argue that
Bernal himself  is  a  racist  because  he  fails  to mention  Gamal  Abdel Nasser
(1918-70), the  founding  father  of modern  pan-Arabism. Absurd  allegations
like Bernal's  poison the  climate  of scholarly  exchange.  They are not meant  to
prove anything  or  to convince  anybody;  instead,  they want  to  score  points
with an audience that is already convinced of their own position's correctness
and their adversaries' maliciousness.
This  audience  is  constituted by Afrocentrists,  as  can  be seen  when  Bernal
refers to the  time when  a  black  pharaoh  received tribute from  the  known
world (Bernal  [1991]  475).  Bernal  himself  is  aware  that  this  image  is
misleading; in a discussion  of his  books, he said,  I  make  no  claim  that  the
Egyptians were black ".103 Yet he also  knows that it taps  into Afrocentrist
myths and will  appeal  to those who firmly believe in  these myths. The same
explanation holds for the ambiguity about the question whether the mistakes
of earlier  scholars  are  due  to  the  prejudices  of  the  Zeitgeist or  betray  the
machinations of a universal conspiracy. We have seen that the belief in such a
conspiracy is  part of the Afrocentrist lore. Again, Bernal knows that scholars
cannot help being influenced  by intellectual and  political  tendencies  of their
time;104  again  his  intimations  that  they  might have  known better,  yet
concealed this  knowledge  for  sinister  reasons  appeals  to  the  conspiracy
theories of Afrocentrists.105
Bernal  is aware  that  his  book and its  arguments  are  being  appropriated by
Black racists.  As he admits, some friends  reproached  him  for this  misuse
(Bernal [1991] xxii):



103 Bernal  [1989]  30.  Most  modern scholars  refrain  from  applying  the  terms  black  or
white to the ancient Egyptians, see Snowden [1996] 112-28, Weinstein [1992] 382
104  See, e.g., Bernal [1989] 28.
105 See  Liverani  [1996]  424:  [Bernal's ]  stress  on  a  Western  conspiracy'  instead  of  on
inevitable conditioning (for  which allowance must always  later  be made),  and  on racial
rather than  political  and  economic distinctions,  is  politically  disruptive and  historically
regressive.


Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 51

My answer  to this  is  that I am disturbed because I  hate  racism  of any
kind. I would prefer to be in my position  than  theirs, however, as  I am
infinitely  less  concerned  by black  racism  than  I  am  by white  racism,
and white racists,  directly or indirectly, make constant  use of orthodox
views of the classical world and the Aryan Model.
This  answer  is clearly  insufficient.  Levine is right to point  out  that  someone
claiming the  moral  high  ground  such  as  Bernal106 is  responsible  for  the
misuse of his arguments and ought to distance  himself  more unambiguously
from all  sorts  of  racism. 107 By  utilizing  inflammatory  and  consciously
misleading rhetoric  and  by  manipulating  the  evidence,108 Bernal  has
contributed to  an  exacerbation  of  the  debate  which  is  scientifically
unproductive and politically  disruptive as  Glen Bowersock remarked, there
is the disturbing  possibility  that we are attending a dialogue of the deaf.109
To a certain  degree, then, Bernal  is  one  of  a  few atypical  cult  authors  who
shamelessly exploit the fears and resentments of contemporary readers.110
Yet in a sense,  his success  proves Bernal  right. No book about the  history  of
the Mediterranean world in the bronze age has  ever attracted so much  public
attention. However, while  this  interest  is  certainly  to be welcomed,  Bernal's 
demagoguery has made it difficult to pursue the discussion  in  a cool-headed
manner. Unfortunately, in this he is  also  part of a major trend in  the US. The
year 1997  witnessed  not only  the  start  of  a  national  conversation  on  race
initiated by President Clinton, but also a growing resentment in  large parts  of
the population  against  measures  that  were  meant  to  remedy  the
consequences of past  discrimination  and  racism.  And for  the  first  time  in
several years,  this  resentment  resulted  in  actions  against  these  measures,
especially against  affirmative  action,  a  program  which  encourages  public
employers to  hire  members  of  minorities.  Already  in  1996,  voters in
California,  the largest  state  of the Union,  had  approved  of  Proposition  209
which abolished  affirmative  action  in  admissions  to  public  colleges  and
universities. In  the  following  years,  there  was  a  sharp  decline  in  minority
enrollment at  all state  universities.111 Similar  projects  are  expected  to  be



106 Cf., for  instance,  Bernal [1989]  25:  " the scheme set  out in Black Athena is  better  on
ethical grounds ".
107  Levine [1992a] 456-9; cf. Snowden [1996] 117.
108  For two especially clear examples, see Williams [1994].
109 Bowersock  [1996].
110  Moses [1994] 21. Cf. similar remarks by Ray [1997] 4.
111  See Holmes [1998a]; Bruni [1998] or the editorial Proposition 209  Shuts the Door,  The
New York Times April 4, 1998, A 12.



52 Thomas A. Schmitz

brought before the voters in Washington and other states.112 In  1998,  voters in
California abolished bilingual education by passing Proposition 227.
There has  been an enormous  controversy about affirmative action  in  the  last
years, and it is obvious that this issue will be on the agenda  for a long time.113
Polls show that Americans are deeply divided on these matters and  that their
opinion  about affirmative action  depends to a great extent on semantics,  not
facts.114
For example,  asked  their  views  on  programs  that  give  preferential
treatment to racial  minorities,  only  26 percent including  21 percent
of  whites  and 51 percent  of  blacks said  they  would  favor  such
programs.  Just 19 percent 15 percent of  whites  and  48  percent of
blacks said they would favor programs that impose  quotas for racial
minorities.
But asked their views about programs that make special efforts to help
minorities  get  ahead,  Americans  of  both  races  seemed vastly more
comfortable  with this  vaguer  language.  Fifty-five  percent  of the
respondents,  including  50 percent of whites  and  80  percent of blacks,
said they would favor such programs.
Of course,  the  effects  and  consequences  of  affirmative  action  and  similar
programs are  exceedingly  difficult  to  assess,  and  I  do  not  intend  to  pass
judgment on the public debate in the US. However, it is  clear  that most blacks
have  a  rather  clear view  of  what  is  happening:  for  many  of them,  the
abolishment of  affirmative  action  signals that  the  white  majority  is
abandoning them  and will  not  support  efforts  to  ameliorate interracial
relations. And to some extent, their fears seem justified. In  a recent book, the
sociologist Alan Wolfe comes to the conclusion that the history of America is
a history of generosity and caring  and that interracial  relations  are  good.115
This  is  self-congratulatory  and smug,  and it  will  foster  the  fears  of  many
blacks that all whites are satisfied with the  status  quo and  unwilling  to make
new efforts to overcome the consequences of past wrongs. As Andrew Hacker



112  See Holmes [1998b].
113  An immense flood of books and articles has been published on affirmative action; I quote
three review articles  that  give a  wealth of  further bibliographical references: Fredrickson
[1997]; Dworkin [1998a] and Dworkin [1998b].
114 Verhovek  [1997].
115 Wolfe  [1998].


Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 53

wrote in  a  rightly  acerbic  comment,  It  should  not  be surprising  that  most
writing about racial progress comes from white authors.116
As one black student at the University of California  at Berkeley put it, If  the
university does  not  want  people  like  me anymore,  that  means  I'm
unwanted.117 This  situation  warrants  pessimistic  expectations.  Narratives
that make  sense  of the  interracial  problems  by  blaming  racist  conspiracies
and bolstering  self-esteem  through  myths will  find  eager  listeners  and  are
bound  to  prosper.  These  will be  difficult  days for  sober reason  and
painstaking analysis  of  evidence.  There  is  thus  little  hope  that  the  debate
about Black Athena will soon be pursued in a less antagonistic mood.

The Relevance of the Debate for Germany

I  hope  to have  shown  the wider  implications  and  the social  and  political
background of Martin Bernal's  work and the discussion it triggered. I want to
close this paper by looking at the situation  in Germany. Classicists  in Europe
and particularly  in Germany have thus  far considered that  the debate about
Black Athena is a purely American  phenomenon  that does not affect them. As
far as I can see, no scholarly journal  in Germany has  reviewed Bernal's   book;
there was  only  one  (totally  dismissive)  review of the German  translation  of
Bernal [1987] in a national newspaper.118 It is indeed tempting to dismiss  this
debate as typically American extremism and return to our ivory tower, far
from the madding  crowd's  ignoble  strife. However, I  would  firmly  advise
against this reaction. For a number of reasons, I think the debate and  Bernal's 
positions  are  highly  relevant  to academics  in  Germany as well,  and I  am
convinced that we can and should learn from it.
Obviously, Germany  does  not  have  a  race  problem  comparable  to  the
situation in  the  US.  However,  ethnic  minorities,  especially  Turkish
immigrants, represent  an  ever  growing  part  of  the  population  and will
continue to grow during the next decades, if demographic  prognoses  can  be
trusted. Many Germans are still convinced that the integration of these people



116  Hacker [1998] 29.
117  Quoted in  Bruni  [1998].  Reactions were  similar after  California  abolished  bilingual
education, as  witnessed by  Terry  [1998]:  "  words like  racism,'  prejudice'  and
discrimination' often came up in interviews after Tuesday's balloting.
118 Schuller  [1992].  For  another,  largely  uncritical,  review  cf.  Sch.lzel  [1996].  Assmann
[1992], though not being a full scholarly review, is  the most thorough discussion of  Black
Athena that has appeared so far (however, Assmann's view that the general readership is
bored by Bernal's  theses (930), has proved to be completely wrong).



54 Thomas A. Schmitz

will not  be a  problem they  just  assume  that  all  immigrants  will  have  to
adapt to  the  German  way  of  living.  Multiculturalism  (often  in  the
abbreviated form multiculti) has become a familiar  slogan  in Germany, yet
most of the time it is used in a highly  polemical  way, as  a vision  of a  future
we do not  want.  Many  conservative  politicians  like  to  point  out  that
immigrants simply  have  to  forget  their  original  identities  and  become
German. One of the most vociferous proponents  of this  view has  been J.rg
Sch.nbohm (CDU), Secretary of the  Interior  (Innensenator)  of Berlin, who
complained that certain parts  of the city of Berlin do not feel like Germany
any longer and referred to German  civilization  as  a Leitkultur, i.e., the part
of civilization that serves as a model for all inhabitants of the country.119
If  we  look  at  the debate  about  multiculturalism  in  the US,  an  alarming
parallel becomes  obvious.  As  Nathan  Glazer  describes  in  his  latest book,
intellectuals and politicians in the 60s and 70s  (among whom Glazer  himself
had been  prominent)  expected  that  the integration  of  blacks  (and  other
minorities) would be unproblematic if not speedy. Yet the actual development
in the past three decades has proved this optimism wrong:120
If one had been asked at the time of the passage  of the Civil Rights  Act
in 1964  to project how matters  would  stand  thirty  years  in  the  future,
what well-informed  person  would  have  predicted the  degree  of
separation between blacks  and  whites  that now  exists  in residence,  in
economic conditions, in family patterns, in attitudes?
No matter  which  development we desire  for  our  society  here  in  Germany,
whether  we hope  for a  full-scale  assimilation  or  for some  sort  of  cultural
pluralism, we  certainly  all  wish  that these developments will  take place  in a
peaceful way,  without  causing  harm  or  discrimination  to  any  group.  This
means we  have  to  acknowledge  that  there  currently  is a  great  cultural
diversity and that especially the Islamic sections of our  society (which  are the
fastest growing)  are  unlikely  to  simply  drop  their  old  identities  and
assimilate. Instead,  they are  already  raising claims  that  their  religion  and
their history  be given  a  place  in  the German  educational  system.  Although
circumstances in the US cannot  be equated to those  in  Germany,  the  events
there suggest that a smooth  integration of these  people  is  impossible  unless
the society as a whole and the public  institutions  in  particular  make  special
efforts to facilitate this process. This would first require a consciousness of the
problems we face. Many citizens  and  politicians  still  like to pretend  that  the



119  See Schuller [1998] and Siemons [1998].
120  Glazer [1997] 123. Cf. Wicker [1996].


Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 55

demands  of the immigrants  will go away if we choose  to ignore them.  This
would  mean  repeating  the mistakes  that  have  been  made  in  the US.  It  is
simply na.ve to assume  that the return  to a  culturally  homogeneous  society
can be decreed. Cultural pluralism is here to stay, and  it is up to us to keep it
from balkanizing our society.
While these are general political lessons that we can  learn from the American
debates about  Afrocentrism  and  multiculturalism,  German  classicists  also
have special  reasons  to  take  up  Bernal's   challenge.  As  I  have  shown,  we
ought to  reject  his  sweeping  generalizations  and  exaggerations  about
eighteenth- and  nineteenth-century  scholarship:  not  all  classicists  and
historians in  this  period were racists  and  anti-Semites.  Yet  reviewers  have
rightly emphasized  that his  arguments  about  the  history  of scholarship  are
the most valuable aspect of his work.121 I would thus recommend  making  use
of his  work in  the  manner  described  by  Marchand/Grafton:  Perhaps  the
way  forward  will  be  to try  to take  Bernal's   questions  and  leave  aside  his
answers. 122
Classicists here  in  Germany  have  a  special  responsibility  to  pursue  these
questions. The  belief  that  race  is a  meaningful  category  for  analyzing
human behavior and history  was  widespread in  most  parts  of the  Western
world during  the  nineteenth  and  early  twentieth  centuries.  Yet  it  was  in
Germany that this belief shaped the policy of a whole nation  and  entailed  its
most catastrophic consequences.123 Ancient History and  the Classics  were no
exception, and numerous scholars  in our disciplines,  too, were influenced by
such prejudices. One of the most  infamous  theoreticians  of racial  science,
Hans F. K. G.nther (known as Rasse-G.nther),  published  a racial  history
of the Greek and the Roman people in 1929,124 and many teachers in German
High Schools and  Universities  eagerly accepted the racial  categories set forth
by such  scholars. 125 German  publications  on  the  ancient  world  betray the


121  E.g., Turner [1989] 104; Pounder [1992] 464; Burstein [1994] 12.
122 Marchand/Grafton  [1997]  31.  A  similar  approach  has  been  suggested by  Liverani,
[1996] 427: We will keep and we like " his baby,  but we must throw out all  his dirty
water. Cf. Stray [1997] 231.
123 On  the  development  of  racial  (and  racist)  paradigms  in  German  historiography  see
Oberkrome [1993]  and  Weber  [1996];  cf.  the  other  contributions  in
Puschner/Schmitz/Ulbricht [1996] for the pervading influence of  such ideas  in all  parts
of society.
124  G.nther [1929]; cf. G.nther [1935].
125 On the  reception  of  racial  categories  in  historical  studies  in  general see  Sch.nw.lder
[1992] 111-9;  Wolf [1996] 185-200;  on Ancient History in particular  see  Binder  [1987]
44-50;  Apel/Bittner  [1994] 242-69;  Cancik [1982];  on archeology see Binder [1991] 20-
24. Recent studies have exploded the older view that this racism had  no influence on the



56 Thomas A. Schmitz

influence of these ideas  in many  different ways.  The  following  passages  are
no more than a few arbitrarily chosen  examples  to which  many  others could
be  added. They  are not chosen  because  they  are especially  spectacular  or
shocking but  because  they  show  that  racial  thinking  influenced  even
seemingly objective scholarship.
In 1931,  Max  Flu126 wrote  the article  Illyrioi  in  Pauly-Wissowa's  Real-
Encyclop.die der  classischen  Altertumswissenschaft, arguably  still  the  greatest
monument of  classical  scholarship.  Here  is  a  brief  extract  from  Flu's
treatment: Racial  affiliation.  Anthropomorphic  measurements  have
demonstrated  the inaccuracy  of the assertion  made  in  older  studies  that  the
I[llyrians] were short,  brachycephalic  people  of  dark  complexion  ".  The
dark  complexion, which is  alien  to  the  Nordic race  to  which  they  belong,
must  certainly  be ascribed  to  the  strata  of populations  that  the  I[llyrians]
encountered while advancing south.127 These words undoubtedly illustrate a
belief in racial science and an Aryanist (here the term is appropriate) vision  of
Nordic  races  advancing  south  and conquering  and displacing  racially
inferior peoples.128 Wilhelm Brandenstein's129 article Tyrrhener was  printed
in 1948, yet we can be certain that it had been written during the Third Reich.
Brandenstein shows the same  belief in  racial  science  when he writes that the
Tyrrhenians  belong to the Near-Eastern  race, viz. to the subcategory  with  a
sharp-boned nose (not the fleshy six-shaped  nose).130 Obviously, nobody in
1948, just three years after the end  of World War  II,  thought  it  necessary  to
correct such references to races which are measurable  by the form of the nose
(assumptions about  racial  traits  had  played  an  important  part  in  Nazi
propaganda against the Jews).
teaching of  Classics  in High Schools,  see,  e.g.,  Kirchner [1939];  cf.  Binder  [1987]  55-8;
Apel/Bittner [1994] 299-323, 345-357 and Fritsch [1982].



126  Fluss contributed numerous articles, especially on prosopographical subjects, to PW in the
20s and 30s.
127  Fluss  [1931]  326-7:  Rassenzugeh.rigkeit. Die  Unrichtigkeit der  Behauptung .lterer
Forschung ",  die  I[llyrier]  als  kleine  Leute  von  dunkler  Komplexion  und  kurzer
Sch.delform anzusehen,  haben  anthropometrische  Erhebungen ergeben ".  Die  ihrer
Zugeh.rigkeit zur  nordischen  Rasse  fremde  dunkle  Komplexion  ist  jedenfalls  den
Bev.lkerungsschichten zuzuschreiben, auf  welche die  I.  bei  ihrem Vorstoe  nach  S.den
trafen ".
128 The same vision can  be found, e.g.,  in  Hofmann [1942]  2223,  where the  author  writes
about developed peoples  and  primitive races  (h.herentwickelte  V.lker  vs.
primitive Rassen).
129  Brandenstein (1897-1967)  was  professor  of Greek language at  the  University  of Graz,
where he continued to teach after the war.
130  Brandenstein [1948] 1917.


Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 57

Hans Herter was one of the most renowned Hellenists in Germany; he taught
at the  University  of  Bonn  well  into  the  1970s.  On  January  30,  1941,  the
anniversary  of the  Nazi  takeover  of power  (Machtergreifung),  the
University of  Bonn  offered  honorary  degrees  to  SA  Oberf.hrer  Landesrat
Hans  Joachim  Apffelstaedt and  to Hugo Scheur, publisher  to the  University.
On this occasion, Herter delivered the ceremonial lecture on the topic People
and Fatherland  as  Nordic  Experience  (Volk  und  Heimat  als  nordisches
Erlebnis). It was published the same year as a small  brochure.131 The booklet
details  the sequence  of  events:  Herter  spoke  after  the address  of  the
University's Rector; his lecture was followed by veneration of the F.hrer and
songs of the  nation  (F.hrerehrung  und  Lieder  der  Nation).  His  speech
celebrates the  Greeks  as  a  Nordic  race  and  emphasizes  the  close
consanguinity between Germans and Greeks.132
My last  example  is  a brief passage  from a work of Hermann  Bengtson, who
was one  of the most  important ancient  historians  in  Germany  after  World
War II.  Bengtson  writes  about  the famous  massacre  of  Italian  residents  in
Asia Minor  that  Mithradates VI  ordered in  88  BCE:  80,000  Italians,  men,
women and children, were butchered in the pogrom arranged by Mithradates,
a  crime that  could  only  have  been  planned  by the  mind  of an  Asian
barbarian. 133 The racism of this sentence is genuinely shocking. What is even
more shocking: Bengtson wrote these words in 1950, only a few years after his
fellow Germans  had  proved at Auschwitz  that they surpassed  every Asian
barbarian when  it  came  to  butchering  innocents.  Bengtson  did  not  even
hesitate to  use  the  word  pogrom,  which  (as  he  certainly  knew)  was
regularly used to denote anti-Semitic riots, of which  Germany had  witnessed
so many during the Nazi  years. Yet the most shocking  discovery for me was
the fact that this heinous  sentence has  been reprinted in every new edition of
Bengtson's extremely popular  Greek History, which  exists  in  an  inexpensive
edition that  most  students  of  the  classics  have  on  their  shelves.134 Did  no


131 Herter [1941].
132 Herter [1941]  13:  Unter  allen  Indogermanen sind es  nun aber  die  alten Hellenen, mit
denen uns eine besonders enge Verwandtschaft verbindet, und wir sind der .berzeugung,
dass  es gerade die nordische Dominante ihres Wesens ist, die gleichgestimmt die unsere
anspricht.
133  Bengtson [1977] 508: 80000 Italiker,  M.nner, Frauen und Kinder, fielen als  Opfer  eines
durch Mithradates  befohlenen Pogroms, wie es  nur im Hirne eines  asiatischen  Barbaren
erdacht werden konnte.
134 Bengtson [1986] 488-9.


58 Thomas A. Schmitz

editor,  no  publisher,  no  reviewer  or  reader  ever  think  twice about this
embarrassing monument of bigotry?135
Assessing the importance and meaning of  race  in  historical  studies  during
the first  half  of the  twentieth  century  is  a  complicated  issue.  Racial  science
was by no means  confined to Germany, and  not every scholar  who used the
word race  or  explained  historical  developments  by  applying  racial
categories was a Nazi or approved of the Holocaust.136 What we need, then, is
a careful analysis  of the different strands  of racial  science. We have  to study
their origins, forms and  developments.  In  every single  instance,  we have  to
ask whether  it  is merely  racial  or  racist.  We must  also  study  to  what
extent  even  seemingly innocent  uses of  racial  categories  contributed to
diluting scholarly  standards 137 and  strengthening  convictions  that  would
lead to the  Nazi  extermination  of inferior  races.  Moreover, we have  to be
careful to look at every single  scholar's  life and  work. Was he a racist  or was
he merely trying to further his  own career by demonstrating  his  allegiance  to
the  ruling ideology? Was  he  trying  to make  his  academic  discipline  more
acceptable to the rulers138 by adding  a  thin  veneer of buzzwords,  or was  he
willing  to give  up  his  scholarly  standards  in  order  to glorify  the  racist
doctrines that  the  Nazis  proclaimed?  And  we  have  the  right, even  the
responsibility to  ask  which  stance  scholars  took  after  the  war:  did they
explicitly retract their former statements,  did they pass  them  over in  silence,
or did they continue  publishing  similar  views, with minimal  adaptations  to
the changed political order?


135  Cf., however, the critical reference to this quotation in Bichler [1989]  80,  and  the general
remark of  Christ  [1996]  167:  " dort,  wo Bengtson pathetisch  wird, ist  die Lekt.re
peinlich.
136  To give a few examples:  articles  about  race  in antiquity could follow the Nazi  ideology,
as  do,  e.g.,  Schuchardt  [1933]; Geyer  [1935]; Erbt  [1936]; Gerlach  [1939];  Hommel
[1939]; Kraiker  [1939]  (Kraiker  also  published  a  number of  articles  in  the  infamous
periodical  Rasse). Or  they  could be  sober  and  cautious,  as,  e.g.,  Matz  [1939];  Fuchs
[1939]; Altheim [1941].
137  See Binder [1987]  47:  W.hrend der ganzen Zeit des  Dritten  Reiches ist  zu beobachten,
dass einzelne Hochschullehrer (entsprechendes gilt f.r Schulm.nner') ohne Not  .ber das
von offizieller Seite erwartete oder  geforderte Mass  hinausgingen und  damit  den  Druck
auf  Kollegen versch.rften,  die in  Forschung und Lehre zu keinen oder  nur zu geringen
Konzessionen bereit waren.
138  Despite Hitler's frequent references to Greek and Roman history in Mein Kampf, the Nazi
administration was  highly critical  of  teaching ancient history and  classical  languages in
High Schools,  see  Apel/Bittner  [1994]  283.  Therefore,  many  historians  found  it
important to  demonstrate the political  relevance of  their studies;  cf.  Badian  [1997]  7-8,
who draws some disquieting parallels to the current situation of classical studies.


Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 59

There can be no doubt about the fact that the Afrocentrist myths are racist and
that every scholar  has  a  moral  obligation  to say  so  and  to refute them.  But
whoever  claims  to  raise her  or his  voice for  the  ideals  of  science  and
dispassionate  search  after the truth,  is  also  obliged to decry the excesses  of
German classicists and to point out what  they really were: racist  propaganda
of the worst sort. And the case  of Bengtson's  Greek History demonstrates  that
we cannot  excuse  ourselves  by asserting  that  these  were just  a  few isolated
cases on  the  fringes  of our  discipline. 139 Other examples  could  be adduced.
One  of the  most  blatant  and  vicious  proponents  of racist  scholarship
during the Nazi era, Hans F. K. G.nther, reissued  his  absurd  pseudo-science
in the fifties.140 Scholars like Helmut Berve141 or Hans  Oppermann142 had  their
articles reprinted  after  the  war,  with  only  cosmetic  changes;  Fritz
Schachermeyr was  still  a  high  priest of racism  in the 60s.143 (Interestingly,
Schachermeyr, a convinced and unrepentant Nazi,144 is one of the few modern
scholars whom  Bernal  cites  approvingly,  see  Bernal  [1991]  375,  467.
Schachermeyr attributes  Nordic  spirit  to  the  Egyptians,  and  his  overall
view of history is precisely the Aryan model that Bernal repudiates.145)
It is  a  curious  phenomenon  that the  last  five  years have seen  a  renewed
interest in  the  Nazi  past  here  in  Germany  (and  elsewhere)  and  that  some
academic disciplines are only now coming to grips with their own role in  this
past. Yet despite the chronological  distance,  this process is  still fraught  with
difficulties. This  became clear when in September 1998,  a panel  on  the  topic
German Historians  in the Third Reich  was  organized  at  the  42nd  annual
convention of the German Historical  Association  (Deutscher Historikertag)
in Frankfurt. The  ensuing  debates  were very lively, to say  the  least.146 Even
now that most of those  who  were directly involved in  the  events have  long
since  died, their relatives and  children,  their students  and  assistants  are still
holding important  positions.  Given  the close  personal  relationship  between


139  A tendency to absolve the discipline as a whole while acknowledging that  very few  of
its members wrote embarrassing passages is present in Dihle [1997] 242.
140 G.nther [1956].  The  book  even was  dignified with  a  review  by  C.  Bradford  Welles,
Gnomon 30  (1958)  546-8,  which shows  no  doubts  about  the  fundamental  concepts  of
racial science.
141 Berve  [1949].
142  On Oppermann, see Faber [1991], Holzberg [1994] 293-4; Malitz [1998], esp. 541.
143 Momigliano  [1968]  45  quel  flamine  del  razzismo  che  continua  a  essere  Fritz
Schachermeyr. On Schachermeyr's work after  the war see Badian  [1976]  284-7,  Christ
[1982-3] 3.202; on his career in general Badian [1997]; Dobesch [1997].
144  See above, n. 143, and below, n. 151.
145  See  Schachermeyr [1933]  38  and  Schachermeyr [1944].  On  Schachermeyr's  view  of
Egypt, cf. Dobesch [1997] 14.
146  See Ullrich [1998], who mentions a number of recent books on the subject.


60 Thomas A. Schmitz

German Ph.D.-candidates  and  their  supervisors  (Doktorv.ter),
acknowledging the wrongs  of beloved teachers  still  does not  come  easy  to
some scholars.  Yet  a  new  generation  of  historians  seems  determined  to
pursue the truth in this matter.
Attempts to  explore  the  lives  and  works of  German  classicists  and  the
development  of classical  studies  from 1933 to 1945 had  been  rather  scarce
until recently. In the 1970s,  Volker Losemann,  a student of Karl Christ, wrote
a Ph.D.-thesis  on the development of the discipline  of Ancient History in the
Third Reich;147 Karl Christ himself  published  a number of smaller  studies on
similar topics.148 The fact that the only comparable  attempt for the  history  of
classical philology was  written by a high school  teacher and  was  published
in a  relatively  obscure  Belgian  periodical  is  certainly  not  accidental,  but
betrays a disturbing lack of interest.149 Yet during the last  years, this  situation
has started  to change  for classical  studies,  too. To quote just a few examples:
We  now  have studies  on the  general development  of  classical  studies  in
Germany in  the 20s  and  30s,  a book on the ancient  historian  Joseph  Vogt, a
collection of articles  on Werner Jaeger,  and  Cornelia  Wegener's  book on  the
history of the Institute for Classical Studies in G.ttingen.150
Yet the debate is still problematic, as the recent controversy about the work of
the ancient  historian  Joseph  Vogt (1895-1986)  demonstrates.  In  1943,  Vogt
edited a  volume  on  Carthage  filled  with  approving  references  to  racial
science. Three  of the  nine contributions  have  the term race  in  their  title;
none of  the  contributors  fails  to  quote  buzzwords  such  as  Rasse  or
v.lkisch. 151 Vogt's  own  introduction  declares  that  the  entire  volume  is



147  Losemann [1977].  Although  he concentrates  on  ancient  historians,  Losemann  also
mentions a number of philologists.
148  See Christ [1990], where references to Christ's older publications are given in the notes.
149  Nickel [1970], Nickel [1972].
150  Flashar  [1995]; Canfora  [1995]; N.f  [1986]; K.nigs  [1995]; Calder  [1992];  Wegeler
[1996].
151 Vogt  [1943].  The  contributions  are  Fritz  Schachermeyr,  Karthago  in
rassengeschichtlicher Bedeutung,  9-43  (by  far  the  most  chilling read);  Fritz  Taeger,
V.lker- und  Rassenk.mpfe  im westlichen Mittelmeer, 44-82;  Matthias  Gelzer,  Der
Rassengegensatz als  geschichtlicher Faktor  beim Ausbruch  der  r.misch-karthagischen
Kriege, 178-202.  For the other contributors' references to racial terms,  see,  e.g., Alfred
Heu, Die  Gestaltung des  r.mischen und des  karthagischen Staates  bis  zum Pyrrhos-
Krieg, 83-138,  87  Offenbarungen semitischen  Volkstumes,  Reinhard  Herbig, Das
arch.ologische Bild  des  Puniertums, 139-77,  145  das  rassische  Bild  der  punischen
Bev.lkerung,  Franz  Miltner,  Wesen  und Gesetz  r.mischer  und karthagischer
Kriegsf.hrung, 203-61, 221-2  v.lkische  und rassische  Veranlagung, Wilhelm Enlin,
Der Einfluss Karthagos auf  Staatsverwaltung und Wirtschaft  der  R.mer, 262-96,  280
semitisch-phoenikisches Blut,  Erich Burck, Das  Bild  der Karthager in  der  r.mischen


Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 61

dedicated to the problem of seeing the conflict between Rome and Carthage as
a racial war between the Nordic  Romans  and  the Semitic  Carthaginians
and that different traits of their character have to be explained  by their racial
structure.152 In  her study  of  Vogt,  K.nigs  poignantly  remarks  that  these
articles  were  written when  the extermination  camps  were  working  full
blast.153 In  his  review  of  K.nigs's  book,  J.rgen  Deininger  dismisses  as
irresponsible every connection  between Vogt's  projects  of racial  science
and the  Nazi  genocide  of  what  they  considered  Untermenschen. 154  I
wonder whether Prof.  Deininger  would  have  been  as  adamant  about
scholarly responsibility  had  he read Arnaldo Momigliano's  similar  remarks
about  Helmut  Berve: "  in  consequence  of the  activities  of the  party  to
which Berve belonged, my father, my  mother,  two uncles  and  three cousins
(one of whom with a little daughter of a few years) were murdered in  the gas
chambers at Auschwitz.155
Already in  1959,  at  a  time  when  Deininger  was  still  busy  thanking  his
venerated teacher  J.  Vogt,156 Momigliano  had  rightly emphasized  that  we
need to  understand  how  so  many  gifted  scholars  adhered  to  a  religion
which had its greatest sanctuaries  at Dachau  and  Auschwitz. 157 Deininger's
Literatur, 297-345, 319 st.mmische Eigenart " rassische Differenzierung. Of course,
I am not implying that  all  of  the contributors were Nazis  or racists;  careful  analysis  of
every single  article  and  its  author's  thought  and  intentions  is  needed.  Modern
assessments of the  volume and  its  contributions differ,  cf.  Christ  [1982-3]  3.163;  Christ
[1990] 92-5; Sch.nw.lder [1992] 215-6; Wolf [1996] 190-1.



152 Vogt  [1943]  7-8:  ist  dieser  folgenschwere Konflikt  durch das  Blutserbe  der  V.lker
bestimmt gewesen, durch die Tatsache also, dass dem wesentlich nordisch gepr.gten Rom
die Welt Karthagos gegen.berstand, deren Fremdheit sich aus der rassischen Struktur des
Puniertums ergibt?  "  Der  moderne  Forscher  "  versucht,  einzelne  Z.ge  dieser
Volkscharaktere mit dieser oder jener Komponente in der rassischen  Struktur der V.lker
in Verbindung zu bringen.
153 K.nigs  [1995]  222:  "  in  diesem  Jahr  liefen  die  Todesmaschinen  in  den
Konzentrationslagern auf Hochtouren.
154 Deininger [1997]  347:  " mit  einer derartigen Insinuation  eines  irgendwie bewuten
Zusammenhangs zwischen  der  Publikation  des  Karthago-Bandes  und  den
Vernichtungslagern [sind]  die  Grenzen  des  in  einer  wissenschaftlichen  Arbeit
Verantwortbaren wohl .berschritten. Nippel [1998] is less adverse, but still  skeptical  of
this connection. Against, see the thoughtful comments of Christ [1995].
155 Momigliano [1965]  839:  "  in  conseguenza  dell'attivit.  del  partito  a  cui  il  Berve
appartenava, mio padre, mia madre, due zii e tre  giovani primi cugini (una dei quali con
una figlioletta de pochi anni) furono uccisi nelle camere a gas di Auschwitz ".
156 Deininger [1965]  V:  Der  erste  Dank  geb.hrt an  dieser  Stelle  meinem verehrten Lehrer
Professor  Dr.  Joseph Vogt ".  Vogt was  Deininger's  dissertation  supervisor,  or
Doktorvater. We  can  only  speculate  on  who  took  the  absurd  decision  to  have  a
student of Vogt review K.nigs's book.
157  See below, n. 163.



62 Thomas A. Schmitz

refusal  even to consider this  connection  is  merely begging  the question.  It
becomes more and more difficult to accept the myth repeated a hundred times
after the war that most Germans knew nothing about what was going on in
the extermination  camps  in  the East, and  we have to  face  the  fact  that  these
projects of racial  science  coincided  with  and  reinforced  the  convictions  of
those determined to destroy inferior races.  Like  Deininger,  many  students
of the generations born during or shortly after World War II  experienced their
professors such  as Vogt as masterly  scholars  and  venerated teachers,  not  as
propagandists for the  Nazis.  Yet younger scholars  are  indubitably  right  to
emphasize that  we have to abstract  from personal  relationships  and  that the
analysis  of this  dark chapter of German  intellectual  history has  to be carried
on.
Of course, for those born after the war, it is  difficult to judge the reasons  and
motives by  which  people  in  a  given  historical  situation  were  driven,  as
Albrecht Dihle's  thoughtful review of Wegeler's  study  points  out.158 Though
Dihle's remarks  are  certainly  true,  we  must  be  careful not  to  draw  the
conclusion that any judgment should be avoided.159 It is sometimes  necessary
to emphasize  that  even people  whose  conscience  was  good and  who  were
convinced that  they had the  best moral reasons  for their  behavior,  in  effect
helped the  barbarian  ideology  of  the  Nazis.  Moreover,  we  have  to
acknowledge that  our  discipline  (very  much  like  the  entire  society  in
Germany) failed in the years immediately  after the war, when it would have
been easier  to pass  this  judgment.160 Dihle's  argument  that  there  just  were
more important things to do sounds  defensive.161 Bernal's   volumes are full of
unjustified generalizations  and  hence  invite  classicists  in  Germany  to close
the  ranks  and  come  to  the  rescue of  their  discipline's  honor. Yet  such  an
automatic collective reaction would certainly be wrong, and  it will  ultimately
disserve  classical  studies if  we  classicists  fail  to set  to this  task,  we  will
warrant  the  suspicion  that  we  still  endorse the  racist  views of  our
predecessors, and  outsiders  are  certain  to ask  embarrassing  questions.
Instead of accusing those who pursue such questions  of befouling their own
nest (Nestbeschmutzer), we should accept the challenge of Black Athena by
filling the gaps  and  doing  more  research  about  the history  of our field. We
158  Dihle [1997] 234: Das Urteil  des  nachgeborenen Historikers jedoch ist  in diesem Punkt
auf die  Auswertung  stets  unvollkommener und interpretationsbed.rftiger  Zeugnisse
angewiesen. Cf. Malitz [1998] 519.



159  A similar point has been made by Maier [1981].
160 See Wolf [1996]  15-20;  Bichler [1989],  Christ [1996]  186-7.  On the  German way  (and
failure) of  dealing with the Nazi  past  in the decade  following the end of  World War II,
see now the brilliant study of Frei [1996].
161  Dihle [1997] 240-1.


Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 63

have to face  the  unsavory  past  of  our  discipline  and  its  involvement  with
racial science,  colonialism,  Eurocentrism  and all  sorts  of  political
ideologies. Marchand/Grafton rightly remind us that we need to explain  the
discipline's silences on questions of burning contemporary interest, as well as
the official pronouncements  of men like Helmut Berve, Richard  Harder, and
Fritz Schachermeyr. 162 As Momigliano  emphasized,  it is important  to study
the texts  of  Nazi  historians  in  order  to  understand  why  intellectuals
succumbed to this ideology.163
However, I would argue that it is even more important  to explore the hidden
influences  of  these  forces than  to  uncover the concrete wrongdoings  of
individuals. To what extent did the widespread belief in the superiority of the
Caucasian race or the conviction that there is some special  affinity between
Greek and German  language  and thought  influence  intellectuals  who  were
far from being racists or chauvinists? It is in this regard that Lefkowitz indeed
underestimates  the complexity  of  the issues  involved,  as  Haley  rightly
argues.164 When Lefkowitz says  that  it  is  possible  to misinterpret  the  facts,
either through  ignorance  or malice,  or  when  she  asks  Had  our  teachers
deceived us,  and  their  teachers  deceived them?,165 she  focuses  on  just  two
ways of error. Yet we have  to  ask  ourselves  if some  prejudices  are  not  so
deeply implanted  in our minds  that it will  be extremely difficult to get rid of
them.
I  will  provide  a  personal  example. In 1996,  the first volume  of  a  new
encyclopedia of the classical world appeared in Germany; this  project will  in
time supplant the Kleine Pauly, though on a much  larger scale.  In  the Preface
to  the whole  project,  the editors,  Hubert  Cancik  and  Helmuth  Schneider,
define early  Greece  as  a  civilization  on  the  border  of  late  Oriental
civilizations. 166 When  I  read these words, I  intuitively felt  that  they  were
somehow inappropriate  because  there  was some  fundamental  difference
between Greek  civilization  and  the adjacent  civilizations  of  the Near  East
(and from conversations with classicist friends, I know that  I am not alone  in



162  Marchand/Grafton [1997] 31.
163 Momigliano [1959]  707-8:    in  verit.  opportuno  che  "  gli  storici  nazisti  siano
conosciuti in tutte le loro fasi di pieno nazismo,  pre-nazismo  e post-nazismo.  Il nazismo
 un fenomeno che va studiato sui documenti originali perch. solo essi possono aiutarci  a
comprendere come intellettuali di  non poca  abilit.  abbiano  aderito  a  una  religione, che
ebbe i suoi maggiori santuari a Dachau e Auschwitz.
164  Haley [1993] 39 n. 10.
165  Lefkowitz [1996] 4-5.
166 Cancik/Schneider [1996]  VI: Das  (klassische)  Altertum ist  hier konzipiert  als  Epoche
des Kulturzeitraumes M.diterran.e,' die fr.hgriechische als sp.torientalische Randkultur
".


64 Thomas A. Schmitz

this feeling).  I  still wonder  whether  this reaction  is  due  to  some  kind  of
understanding or merely to prejudices and ideologies that I have internalized.
Furthermore, we  should  ask  ourselves  whether  the  notion  that  Germans
were somehow constitutionally better equipped to understand  the Greeks,167
which originated  in  the  18th  century  and  was  often  exploited  during the
Third Reich,168 does not still influence our work without our being aware of it.
I would  suggest  that  we pursue such  questions.  To do so,  however, would
also require  a  reappraisal  of  the  history  of  scholarship.  Although  most
scholars today would agree that it is more  than a  slightly  frivolous  pastime
to be pursued on Sundays  when one is  tired of the real historical  work and
does not  have  enough  energy  to  read the  books,  only  to  browse  through
them,169 it is  still  in danger of turning into learned gossip  about  the  private
lives of  our  predecessors  or  psychological  biography  (or  worse  still,
hagiography).170 It may be important to publish a famous  scholar's  postcards
to his mother-in-law, yet we have to see the history of classical scholarship  as
part of a general histoire des mentalit.s or intellectual history. Only then can we
begin to understand  where  our own  unconscious  presuppositions  originate
and attempt to achieve a less biased view.
I am aware that it is  easier  to make such  lofty demands  than  to pursue these
goals. All  sorts  of  political,  departmental,  personal  and  practical  reasons
speak against  it. However, much  is at  stake.  In  Europe, the  importance  and
the place of classics has been disputed in the last twenty years, to an  extent of
which many  American colleagues  are  unaware.  The  enormous  response  to
Black Athena demonstrates  that  the  civilizations  of  the  ancient  world  still
arouse interest far beyond the  circles  of academics  and  professionals  in  the
field, that they still  constitute  a  heritage  which  many  people  aspire  to. This
entails a  huge  responsibility  for  those who  profess this  discipline.  The
admonitions of Molly Myerowitz Levine are worth quoting here:171



167 Norton [1996] 406.  Norton quotes remarks by Martin Heidegger made in 
1966  that  still
uphold this view.
168 I  give  a  few  randomly  chosen  examples:  Leits.tze  des  deutschen  Altphilologen-
Verbandes zur  Neugestaltung  des  humanistischen  Bildungsgedankens  auf  dem
Gymnasium, Neue Jahrb.cher f.r Wissenschaft und  Jugendbildung 9  (1933)  570-2,  Berve
[1934] 269, Drexler [1939] 5, Oppermann  [1939]  165,  Herter [1941]  13.  Cf.  Momigliano
[1968] 45. This entailed the view that, e.g., Semitic people would  not  be able  to  reach an
understanding of Nordic civilizations, see Christ [1990] 168-71.
169 Momigliano [1959]  708:  " prendere la  storia  della  storiografia come un passatempo
domenicale, per quando si  stanco del vero lavoro storico  e non si  ha  energia sufficiente
per leggere i libri, ma solo per sfogliarli.
170  See the remarks of Henrichs [1995] 424-5.
171 Levine [1992b] 217-8.


Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 65

The distortions are usually more often the result of good intentions than
they are of deliberate self-serving.  But if something  needs fixing  all  the
good will in the world cannot substitute for the lack of a proper tool. We
classicists, of all  people, should  recognize the enormous  labor entailed
in putting together bits and pieces of evidence about long gone events in
far away places often in languages no one can read, or without words at
all, in an attempt to create some reasonable  picture of the past. Instead
of decrying the distortions,  or dismissing  them as  popular  and  thus
undeserving of our attention, we should  put our  collective  shoulder  to
the wheel, using  our training  where and when and how it needs  to be
used.
We classicists  have  a  moral  obligation  to respond  to the  challenge  of  Black
Athena,  and as I  have  tried  to  show,  this  moral obligation  is  particularly
urgent in Germany. We cannot afford to ignore it.


Bibliographical References

Altheim, Franz. 1941. Indogermanisches Erbe in Rom, Die Antike 17: 49-59.
Apel, Hans  J.rgen/Bittner,  Stefan.  1994.  Humanistische Schulbildung  1890-
1945. Anspruch  und  Wirklichkeit  der  altertumskundlichen  Unterrichtsf.cher
(Studien und  Dokumentationen  zur  deutschen  Bildungsgeschichte  55),
Cologne.
Appiah, K. Anthony. 1997.  The Multiculturalist  Misunderstanding,  NYRB
October 9: 30-36.
Assmann, Jan.  1992.  Sentimental  Journey  zu  den  Wurzeln  Europas.  Zu
Martin Bernals Black Athena,' Merkur 522: 921-31.
Badian, Ernst. 1976. Some Recent Interpretations of Alexander, in  Alexandre
le Grand.  Image  et  r.alit. (Fondation  Hardt,  Entretiens 22),  Vanduvres,
279-301.
Badian, Ernst.  1997.  In Memory  of  Fritz  Schachermeyr,  AJAH 13  (1988
[1996-97]) 1-10.
Baines, John. 1996.  On  the  Aims  and  Methods  of  Black Athena, in
Lefkowitz/Rogers [1996] 27-48.
Bengtson, Hermann.  1977.  Griechische Geschichte  von den  Anf.ngen  bis  in  die
r.mische Kaiserzeit5, Munich [first edition 1950].
Bengtson, Hermann.  1986.  Griechische Geschichte  von den  Anf.ngen  bis  in  die
r.mische Kaiserzeit, Sonderausgabe, 7th printing, Munich.
66 Thomas A. Schmitz
Bernal, Martin. 1987. Black Athena. The Afroasiatic Roots of  Classical  Civilization,
vol. 1: The Fabrication of Ancient Greece 1785-1985, New Brunswick  [seventh
printing 1991].
Bernal, Martin. 1989. Black Athena and the APA, in Peradotto/Levine [1989]
17-38.
Bernal, Martin. 1991. Black Athena. The Afroasiatic Roots of  Classical  Civilization,
vol. 2: The Archaeological  and Documentary Evidence, New Brunswick  [third
printing 1993].
Bernal, Martin. 1992. Response to Edith Hall, Arethusa 25: 203-14.
Bernal, Martin.  1994.  Socrates'  Ancestry  in  Question,  Academic Questions
(Summer 1994) 7.
Berve, Helmut.  1934.  Antike  und  nationalsozialistischer  Staat,
Vergangenheit und Gegenwart 24: 257-72.
Berve, Helmut. 1949. Gestaltende Kr.fte der Antike. Aufs.tze zur griechischen  und
r.mischen Geschichte, Munich.
Bichler, Reinhold. 1989. Neuorientierung  in der Alten Geschichte?  in Ernst
Schulin/Elisabeth M.ller-Luckner  (eds.),  Deutsche Geschichtswissenschaft
nach dem Zweiten Weltkrieg (1945-1965) (Schriften des Historischen  Kollegs.
Kolloquien 14), Munich, 63-86.
Binder, Gerhard.  1987.  Einf.hrung,  in  Gerhard  Binder  (ed.),  Saeculum
Augustum 1.  Herrschaft  und  Gesellschaft (Wege  der Forschung  266),
Darmstadt, 1-58.
Binder, Gerhard.  1991.  Einf.hrung,  in  Gerhard  Binder  (ed.),  Saeculum
Augustum 3. Kunst und Bildersprache (Wege der Forschung  632),  Darmstadt,
1-30.
Binder, Gerhard. 1993.  Augusteische  Erneuerung': Kritische Anmerkungen
zu einem Schlagwort  der Klassischen  Altertumswissenschaften  im  20.
Jahrhundert, in Christoff Neumeister (ed.), Antike Texte  in  Forschung  und
Schule. Festschrift Willibald Heilmann, Frankfurt, 279-99.
Bowersock, Glen.  1996.  Review  of  Lefkowitz/Rogers  [1996]  and  Lefkowitz
[1997], The New York Times Feb. 25: G 6.
Branch, Taylor.  1998.  Pillar of  Fire. America in  the  King  Years 1963-65, New
York.
Brandenstein, Wilhelm. 1948. Tyrrhener, in PW 14: 1909-1938.
Bruni, Frank. 1998.  Blacks  at Berkeley Are Offering No Welcome  Mat,  The
New York Times May 2: A 1.
Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 67
Burkert, Walter.  1992.  The Orientalizing  Revolution.  Near  Eastern  Influence  on
Greek Culture in  the  Early  Archaic  Age, Cambridge, MA [first published  in
German, Heidelberg 1984].
Burstein, Stanley. 1993. Review of Bernal [1991], CPh 88: 157-62.
Burstein, Stanley.  1994.  The  Challenge  of  Black Athena: An  Interim
Assessement, Ancient History Bulletin 8.1: 11-17.
Calder, William M. III (ed.). 1992. Werner Jaeger Reconsidered.  Proceedings  of  the
Second Oldfather Conference, Held on the Campus of  the University  of  Illinois  at
Urbana-Champaign, April  26-28,  1990 (Illinois Classical  Studies
Supplement 3), Atlanta.
Cancik, Hubert. 1982. Antike Volkskunde 1936, AU 25.3: 80-99.
Cancik, Hubert/Schneider, Helmuth. 1996.  Vorwort, in  Cancik/Schneider
(eds.), Der Neue Pauly. Enzyklop.die  der Antike, Altertum Bd. 1, Stuttgart, V-
VII.
Canfora, Luciano.  1995.  Politische Philologie.  Altertumswissenschaften  und
moderne Staatsideologien, Stuttgart [originally published in Italian, 1989].
Chavez, Linda.  1994.  Preface: The Myth of Self-Esteem,  in  Miller  [1994]  5-
10.
Christ, Karl.  1982-3.  R.mische Geschichte und  Wissenschaftsgeschichte, 3  vol.,
Darmstadt.
Christ, Karl. 1990. Neue Profile der Alten Geschichte, Darmstadt.
Christ, Karl.  1995.  Homo Novus. Zum  100.  Geburtstag  von  Joseph  Vogt,
Historia 44: 504-7  [a  shorter  version  appeared  in  Frankfurter Allgemeine
Zeitung, June 23, 1995, 12].
Christ, Karl.  1996.  Griechische Geschichte und  Wissenschaftsgeschichte (Historia
Einzelschriften 106), Stuttgart.
Coleman, John  E.  1996.  Did  Egypt Shape  the  Glory That  Was  Greece?  in
Lefkowitz/Rogers [1996] 280-302.
Crews, Fredrick. 1998. The Mindsnatchers, NYRB June 25: 14-9.
Deininger, J.rgen.  1965.  Die Provinziallandtage  der  r.mischen  Kaiserzeit  von
Augustus bis zum Ende des dritten Jahrhunderts n. Chr. (Vestigia 6), Munich.
Deininger, J.rgen. 1997. Review of K.nigs [1995], Gymnasium 104: 345-8.
Dembner, Alice.  1996.  Afrocentrism  Debated at  Wellesley  Teach-in,'  The
Boston Globe May 2: 87.
Derrida, Jacques. 1967. De la grammatologie, Paris.
Derrida, Jacques. 1974. Of Grammatology, Baltimore.
68 Thomas A. Schmitz
Dihle, Albrecht. 1997. Review of Wegeler [1996], GGA 249: 227-44.
Diop, Cheikh Anta. 1991. Civilization Or  Barbarism. An Authentic Anthropology,
Brooklyn, N.Y.
Dobesch, Gerhard. 1997. Allgemeine W.rdigung, AJAH 13  (1988  [1996-97])
11-55.
Dornseiff, Franz. 1959. Antike und alter Orient. Interpretationen2, Leipzig.
Drexler, Hans. 1939. Die Antike und wir, Die Alten Sprachen 4: 1-18.
Dworkin, Ronald.  1998a.  Affirming Affirmative Action, NYRB October 22:
91-102.
Dworkin, Ronald. 1998b. Is  Affirmative Action Doomed? NYRB November
5: 56-60.
Early, Gerald. 1994. The Anatomy of Afrocentrism, in Miller [1994] 12-5.
Ellis, John M. 1989. Against Deconstruction, Princeton.
Erbt, Wilhelm.  1936.  Die  Alte Geschichte,  Vergangenheit und  Gegenwart 26:
617-28.
Faber, Richard.  1991.  Faschistische  Vergil-Philologie:  Zum  Beispiel  Hans
Oppermann,  Hephaistos 10: 111-33.
Farber, Daniel  A./Sherry, Suzanna.  1997.  Beyond All  Reason.  The  Radical
Assault on Truth in American Law, New York.
Flashar, Hellmut  (ed.). 1995.  Altertumswissenschaft in  den  20er  Jahren.  Neue
Fragen und Impulse, Stuttgart.
Flint, Anthony.  1994.  Black  Academics  Split  on  Afrocentrism,  The Boston
Globe Sept. 27: 1.
Flu, Max. 1931. Illyrioi, in PW Supplement 5: 311-45
Foner, Eric.  1988.  Reconstruction. America's  Unfinished  Revolution  1863-1877,
New York.
Fredrickson, George  M.  1997.  America's  Caste  System:  Will  It  Change?
NYRB October 23: 68-75.
Frei, Norbert. 1996.  Vergangenheitspolitik.  Die Anf.nge der  Bundesrepublik  und
die NS-Vergangenheit, Munich.
Fritsch,  Andreas.  1982.  Der Lateinunterricht  in  der  Zeit des
Nationalsozialismus. Organisation, Richtlinien, Lehrb.cher, AU 25.3: 20-
56.
Fuchs, Siegfried. 1939.  Zur Frage  der  Indogermanisierung  Griechenland,
Neue Jahrb.cher f.r Antike und deutsche Bildung 2: 165-74.
Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 69
Garrow, David  J.  1981.  The FBI  and Martin  Luther  King,  Jr.  From  Solo  to
Memphis, New York.
Gates, Henry  Louis  Jr. 1989.  Whose  Canon  Is  It,  Anyway?  The New York
Times Feb. 26: G 1.
Gates, Henry  Louis  Jr.  1991.  Beware  of  the  New  Pharaohs,  Newsweek
September 23: 47.
Gerlach, Kurt. 1939. Aischylos und die v.lkisch-politische Wirklichkeit, Die
Alten Sprachen 4: 68-70.
Geyer, Fritz. 1935.  Zur Bedeutung der Rassemischung  f.r die  Entwicklung
Roms, Vergangenheit und Gegenwart 25: 1-15.
Glazer, Nathan.  1995.  Levin,  Jeffries, and  the  Fate  of Academic  Freedom,
The Public Interest 120 (Summer 1995) 14-40.
Glazer, Nathan. 1997. We Are All Multiculturalists Now, Cambridge, MA.
Gordon, Pamela.  1993.  On  Black Athena: Ancient  Critiques  of  the  Ancient
Model' of Greek History, CW 87: 71-2.
Green, Tamara  M. 1989.  Black Athena and  Classical  Historiography:  Other
Approaches, Other Views, in Peradotto/Levine [1989] 55-65.
Gross, Paul R./Levitt, Norman. 1994. Higher Superstition. The Academic Left and
Its Quarrels with Science, Baltimore.
Gross, Paul R./Levitt, Norman/Lewis, Martin W. (eds.). 1996.  The Flight  from
Science and  Reason  (Annals  of the  New  York  Academy  of Sciences  775),
New York.
G.nther, Hans  F. K. 1929.  Rassengeschichte  des hellenischen  und  des r.mischen
Volkes, Munich.
G.nther, Hans  F. K. 1935. Der Einschlag  nordischer  Rasse  im hellenischen
Volke, Vergangenheit und Gegenwart 25: 529-47.
G.nther, Hans F. K. 1956. Lebensgeschichte des Hellenischen Volkes, P.hl.
Hacker, Andrew. 1992. Two Nations. Black and White, Separate, Hostile, Unequal,
New York.
Hacker, Andrew. 1998. Grand Illusion, NYRB, June 11: 26-9.
Haley, Shelley  P.  1993.  Black  Feminist  Thought  and  Classics:  Re-
membering, Re-claiming, Re-empowering,  in Rabinowitz/Richlin  (1993)
23-43.
Hall,  Edith. 1992.  When Is  a Myth Not a Myth?  Bernal's   Ancient  Model,'
Arethusa 25:  181-202  [quoted after the  reprint  in  Lefkowitz/Rogers  [1996]
333-348].
70 Thomas A. Schmitz
Halperin,  David M./Winkler, John  J./Zeitlin,  Froma I. 1990.  Introduction,
in Halperin/Winkler/Zeitlin  (eds.),  Before Sexuality.  The Construction  of
Erotic Experience in the Ancient Greek World, Princeton, 3-20.
Hanson, Victor Davis/Heath,  John.  1998.  Who Killed  Homer?  The  Demise  of
Classical Education and the Recovery of Greek Wisdom, New York.
Harris, Wendell  V. 1996.  Literary Meaning.  Reclaiming  the  Study  of  Literature,
New York.
Henrichs, Albert. 1995.  Philologie  und  Wissenschaftsgeschichte:  Zur  Krise
eines Selbstverst.ndnisses, in Flashar [1995] 423-57.
Herrnstein, Richard  J./Murray, Charles.  1994.  The Bell  Curve.  Intelligence  and
Class Structure in American Life, New York.
Herter, Hans. 1941. Rheinische Friedrich-Wilhelms-Universit.t in Bonn, Ansprache
des Rektors Karl F. Chudoba  zur Feier des 18. und 30.  Januar verbunden mit der
Verleihung der akademischen Ehrenb.rgerrechte an SA-Oberf.hrer Landesrat Dr.
Hans Joachim  Apffelstaedt  und  Verleger  Hugo  Scheur  am  30.  Januar  1941.
Festvortrag des Professors Hans Herter: Volk und Heimat als nordisches  Erlebnis,
Bonn.
Higham, John. 1997. America's Three Reconstructions,  NYRB November 6:
52-6.
Hofmann, Max. 1942. Paeligni, in PW 18.1.2: 2227-71.
Holmes, Steven A. 1998a.  The  Nation:  Re-Rethinking  Affirmative Action,
The New York Times April 5: D 5.
Holmes, Steven  A.  1998b.  Washington  State  Is  Stage  for  Fight  Over
Preferences, The New York Times May 4: A 1.
Holzberg, Niklas.  1994. Horaz  und  seine Deutsche  Schule.'  Resultate und
Perspektiven einer nationalen Forschungstradition, Lampas 27: 290-304.
Hommel, Hildebrecht.  1939.  H.  St.  Chamberlain  und  die  Griechen,  Die
Alten Sprachen 4: 249-72.
James, George G. M. 1954.  Stolen Legacy.  The  Greeks Were  Not  the  Authors  of
Greek Philosophy,  But  the  People  of  North  Africa,  Commonly  Called  the
Egyptians, New York.
Jasanoff, Jay  H./Nussbaum,  Alan.  1996.  Word  Games.  The  Linguistic
Evidence in Black Athena, in Lefkowitz/Rogers [1996] 177-205.
Jenkyns, Richard.  1996.  Bernal  and  the  Nineteenth  Century,  in
Lefkowitz/Rogers [1996] 411-420.
Jenkyns, Richard. 1998. Cards of Identity, NYRB April 23: 49-52.
Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 71
Kennedy, Randall. 1997. Race, Crime, and the Law, New York.
Kirchner, Ernst.  1939.  Klassische  und  rassische  Stoffauslese,  Die Alten
Sprachen 4: 139-41.
K.nigs, Dietmuth. 1995.  Joseph Vogt. Ein Althistoriker in der Weimarer Republik
und im  Dritten  Reich (Basler  Beitr.ge  zur  Geschichtswissenschaft  168),
Basel.
Kraiker, Wilhelm.  1939.  Nordische  Einwanderungen  in  Griechenland,  Die
Antike 15: 195-230.
Kuhn, Thomas S. 1970. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions2, Chicago.
Lefkowitz, Mary  R.  1996.  Ancient  History,  Modern  Myths,  in
Lefkowitz/Rogers [1996] 3-23.
Lefkowitz, Mary R. 1997.  Not Out of  Africa. How Afrocentrism Became an Excuse
to Teach Myth as History2, New York.
Lefkowitz, Mary R./Rogers, Guy MacLean  (eds.). 1996.  Black Athena Revisited,
Chapel Hill.
Leitch, Vincent B. 1983. Deconstructive Criticism. An Advanced Introduction, New
York.
Lenz, John R. 1993. Review of Bernal [1991], Free Inquiry 13.4: 54-5.
Levine, Molly Myerowitz. 1989.  The  Challenge  of  Black Athena to Classics
Today, in Peradotto/Levine [1989] 7-16.
Levine, Molly Myerowitz. 1992a.  The Use and  Abuse of Black Athena, AHR
97: 440-60.
Levine, Molly  Myerowitz.  1992b.  Multiculturalism  and  the  Classics,
Arethusa 25: 215-21.
Lilla, Mark. 1998. A Tale of Two Reactions, NYRB May 14: 4-7.
Litwack, Leon F. 1998. Trouble in Mind. Black Southerners in the Age of  Jim Crow,
New York.
Liverani, Mario.  1996.  The  Bathwater  and  the  Baby,  in  Lefkowitz/Rogers
[1996] 421-7.
Losemann, Volker.  1977.  Nationalsozialismus und  Antike.  Studien  zur
Entwicklung des Faches Alte Geschichte 1933-1945 (Historische  Perspektiven
7), Hamburg.
Maier, Franz Georg. 1981. Review of Losemann [1977], Gnomon 52: 215-6.
Malitz, J.rgen. 1998. R.mertum  im Dritten  Reich':  Hans  Oppermann,  in
Peter Kneissl/Volker  Losemann  (eds.),  Imperium Romanum.  Studien  zu
Geschichte und Rezeption. Festschrift Karl Christ, Stuttgart 1998, 519-43.
72 Thomas A. Schmitz
Marchand, Suzanne/Grafton,  Anthony.  1997.  Martin  Bernal  and  His
Critics, Arion 5.2: 1-35.
Martel, Erich. 1994.  What's  Wrong with the  Portland  Baseline  Essays?,  in
Miller [1994] 37-42.
Martin, Tony.  1993.  The Jewish  Onslaught.  Despatches  from the  Wellesley
Battlefront, Dover, MA.
Matz, Friedrich. 1939. Die Indogermanisierung  Italiens,  Neue Jahrb.cher f.r
Antike und deutsche Bildung 2: 32-47.
McNeal, R. A. 1993. Review-Discussion: Bernal Once Again, AJAH 10  (1985
[1993]) 137-54.
Miller, John J. (ed.). 1994. Alternatives to Afrocentrism, Washington.
Minow, Martha. 1997.  Not Only for Myself.  Identity, Politics, and the Law, New
York.
Momigliano,  Arnaldo. 1959.  Review of Helmut Berve, Storia Greca, Bari 1959,
RSI 71:  665-72  [quoted after the reprint in Terzo Contributo  alla  storia degli
studi classici e del mondo antico, vol. 1 (Storia e letterattura 108), Rome 1966,
699-708].
Momigliano, Arnaldo.  1965,  Chiarimento,  Athenaeum 44:  441-3  [quoted
after the reprint in  Sesto Contributo alla  storia degli  studi classici  e  del  mondo
antico vol. 2 (Storia e letterattura 150), Rome 1980, 837-40].
Momigliano, Arnaldo. 1968.  Prospettiva 1967  della  storia Greca, RSI 80:  5-
19 [quoted after the reprint in Quarto Contributo alla  storia degli  studi classici
e del mondo antico (Storia e letterattura 115), Rome 1969, 43-58].
Momigliano, Arnaldo.  1981.  The  Rhetoric  of  History and  the  History of
Rhetoric: On Hayden  White's  Tropes,  Comparative Criticism 3:  259-68
[quoted after the reprint in  Settimo contributo alla  storia degli  studi classicsi  e
del mondo antico (Storia e letteratura 161), Rome 1984, 49-59].
Morris, Sarah  P.  1989.  Daidalos  and  Kadmos:  Classicism  and
Orientalism,' in Peradotto/Levine [1989] 39-54.
Moses, Wilson J. 1994. In Fairness to Afrocentrism, in Miller [1994] 16-22.
N.f, Beat.  1986.  Von Perikles  zu  Hitler?  Die  athenische  Demokratie  und  die
deutsche Althistorie bis 1945 (PhD-diss. Zurich), Bern.
Nash, Gary  B./Crabtree,  Charlotte/Dunn,  Ross  E.  1997.  History on  Trial.
Culture Wars and the Teaching of the Past, New York.
Nicholson, David.  1990. Afrocentrism'  and  the  Tribalization  of  America.
The Misguided Logic of Ethnic  Education  Schemes,  The Washington  Post
September 23: B 1.
Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 73
Nickel, Rainer.  1970.  Der Mythos vom Dritten Reich  und  seinem  F.hrer  in
der Ideologie  des  Humanistischen  Gymnasiums  vor  1945,  Paedagogica
Historica 10: 111-28.
Nickel, Rainer.  1972.  Humanistisches  Gymnasium  und
Nationalsozialismus. Erziehung  zum  Rassenbewutsein  im
altsprachlichen Unterricht vor 1945, Paedagogica Historica 12: 485-503.
Nippel, Wilfried. 1998. Review of K.nigs [1995], Gnomon 70: 373-5.
Njeri, Itabari.  1992.  The  Chauvinism  We Hate  Isn't  Our Path,  Either.
Afrocentrism: Is  It Any Wonder  That  a  People  So  Marginalized  Would
Turn to Black Nationalism, The Los Angeles Times Feb. 28: B 7.
Norris, Christopher. 1991. Deconstruction. Theory and Practice2, London.
Norton, Robert  E. 1996.  The  Tyranny  of  Germany  over  Greece?  in
Lefkowitz/Rogers [1996] 403-410.
Oberkrome, Willi.  1993.  Volksgeschichte. Methodische  Innovation  und  v.lkische
Ideologisierung in der deutschen Geschichtswissenschaft 1918-1945, G.ttingen.
Oppermann, Hans. 1939.  Warum  heute  noch  Gymnasium,  Die Alten
Sprachen 4: 161-71.
Palter, Robert. 1996. Eighteenth-Century  Historiography  in Black Athena, in
Lefkowitz/Rogers [1996] 349-402.
Peradotto, John/Levine,  Molly Myerowitz (eds.). 1989.  The Challenge  of  Black
Athena (Arethusa, special issue).
Pounder, Robert L.  1992.  Black Athena 2:  History  without  Rules,  AHR 97:
461-4.
Puschner, Uwe/Schmitz,  Walter/Ulbricht,  Justus  H.  (eds.).  1996.  Handbuch
zur V.lkischen Bewegung 1871-1918, Munich.
Rabinowitz, Nancy  Sorkin/Richlin,  Amy (eds.). 1993.  Feminist Theory  and the
Classics, New York.
Ray, John.  1997.  How  Black  Was  Socrates?  Times Literary  Supplement
February 14: 3-4.
Ringle, Ken. 1996.  A  Professor's  Collision  Course.  Classics  Scholar  Mary
Lefkowitz Shakes  Up Academia  With  Her Critique of Afrocentrism,  The
Washington Post June 11: E 1.
Rogers, Guy  MacLean.  1996.  Multiculturalism  and  the  Foundations  of
Western Civilization, in Lefkowitz/Rogers [1996] 428-43.
Roth, Ann  Macy.  1996.  Building  Bridges  to Afrocentrism.  A  Letter to my
Egyptological Colleagues, in Gross/Levitt/Lewis [1996] 313-26.
74 Thomas A. Schmitz
Schachermeyer, Fritz.  1933.  Die  nordische  F.hrerpers.nlichkeit  im
Altertum. Ein Baustein zur Weltanschauung des Nationalsozialismus,  in
Humanistische Bildung  im  nationalsozialistischen  Staat (Neue Wege  zur
Antike 9), Leipzig, 36-43.
Schachermeyr, Fritz.  1944.  Indogermanen und  Orient.  Ihre  kulturelle  und
machtpolitische Auseinandersetzung im Altertum, Stuttgart.
Sch.lzel, Arnold. 1996. Review of Bernal [1987], Das Argument 38: 437-9.
Sch.nw.lder, Karen.  1992.  Historiker und  Politik.  Geschichtswissenschaft  im
Nationalsozialismus (Historische Studien 9), Frankfurt.
Schuchardt, Carl. 1933. Die  Indogermanisierung  Griechenlands,  Die Antike
9: 303-19.
Schuller, Wolfgang.  1992.  Die  schwarze  Welle  rollt.  Ersch.tternde
Ableitungen: War  Hellas  eine  Neger-Kultur?  Frankfurter Allgemeine
Zeitung Sept. 29.
Schuller, Konrad.  1998.  Wo  die  Bulette  verliert,  wittert  Sch.nbohm  das
Ghetto. Berlins  Innensenator  und  die  Ausl.nderpolitik,  Frankfurter
Allgemeine Zeitung June 15: 5.
Shipler, David  K. 1997.  A Country  of  Strangers. Blacks  and  Whites  in  America,
New York.
Siemons, Mark. 1998.  Stil  macht  den  Mann.  J.rg  Sch.nbohms  Kampf  um
eine neue Hauptstadt-.sthetik, Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung July 27.
Snowden, Frank  M.  Jr.  1996.  Bernal's   Blacks'  and  the  Afrocentrists,  in
Lefkowitz/Rogers [1996] 112-28.
Sokal, Alan  D.  1996a.  Transgressing  the  Boundaries Toward  a
Transformative Hermeneutics of  Quantum  Gravity,  Social Text
(Spring/Summer 1996) 217-52.
Sokal, Alan  D.  1996b.  A Physicist  Experiments  with  Cultural  Studies,
Lingua Franca (May/June 1996) 62-4.
Sokal, Alan D./Bricmont, Jean. 1998. Intellectual Imposters, London.
Stille, Alexander. 1998. The Betrayal of History, NYRB June 11: 15-20.
Stray, Christopher. 1997.  Review of Lefkowitz/Rogers  [1996]  and  Lefkowitz
[1997], Journal of Hellenic Studies 117: 229-31.
Sundiata, Ibrahim.  1996.  Afrocentrism:  The  Argument  We're  Really
Having,  Dissonance September  30
[http://way.net/dissonance/sundiata.html].
Ex Africa lux? Black Athena and the debate about Afrocentrism in the US 75
Terry, Don.  1998.  The  Reply,  It  Turned  Out, Was  Bilingual:  No,  The New
York Times June 5: A 12.
Tonry, Michael. 1995. Malign Neglect Race, Crime, and Punishment in America,
New York.
Tritle, Lawrence  A. 1992.  Black Athena. Vision  or Dream  of Greek Origins?
LCM 17.6: 85-96  [quoted after the reprint in Lefkowitz/Rogers [1996]  303-
30].
Turner, Frank  M.  1989.  Martin  Bernal's   Black Athena: A  Dissent,  in
Peradotto/Levine [1989] 97-109.
Ullrich, Volker. 1998.  Sp.te Reue der Zunft. Endlich  arbeiten  die  deutschen
Historiker die braune Vergangenheit ihres Faches auf, Die Zeit September
17: 53.
Verhovek, Sam  Howe. 1997.  In  Poll, Americans  Reject Means But Not Ends
of Racial Diversity, The New York Times December 14: A 1.
Vogt, Joseph (ed.). 1943. Rom und Karthago. Ein Gemeinschaftswerk, Leipzig.
Walker, Clarence E. 1994.  The Distortions  of Afrocentrist History, in Miller
[1994] 32-6.
Weber, Wolfgang.  1996.  V.lkische  Tendenzen  in  der
Geschichtswissenschaft, in Puschner/Schmitz/Ulbricht [1996] 834-58.
Wegeler, Cornelia. 1996.    wir  sagen ab  der internationalen  Gelehrtenrepublik.
Altertumswissenschaft und  Nationalsozialismus Das  G.ttinger  Institut  f.r
Altertumskunde 1921-1962, Vienna.
Weinberg, Steven. 1996. Sokal's Hoax, NYRB Aug. 8: 11-15.
Weinberg, Steven. 1998.  The  Revolution  That  Didn't  Happen,  NYRB
October 8: 48-52.
Weinstein, James W. 1992. Review of Bernal [1991], AJA 96: 381-3.
Welles, C. Bradford. 1958. Review of G.nther [1956], Gnomon 30: 546-8.
West, Martin L. 1971. Early Greek Philosophy and the Orient, Oxford.
West, Martin  L. 1997.  The East  Face of  Helicon.  West Asiatic  Elements in  Greek
Poetry and Myth, Oxford.
White, Hayden. 1987. The Content of the Form. Narrative  Discourse and Historical
Representation, Baltimore.
Wicker, Tom. 1996. Tragic Failure. Racial Integration in America, New York.
Wieseh.fer, Josef. 1990.  Zur  Geschichte  der  Begriffe Arier'  und  Arisch'  in
der deutschen  Sprachwissenschaft  und Althistorie des 19. und der ersten
H.lfte  des  20. Jahrhunderts,  in  H.  Sancisi-Weerdenburg/J.  W. Drijvers
76 Thomas A. Schmitz
(eds.)., Achaemenid History 5: The Roots of  the European Tradition.  Proceedings
of the 1987 Groningen Achaemenid History Workshop, Leiden, 149-65.
Will, George F. 1996. Intellectual Segregation, Newsweek Feb. 19: 78.
Williams, L. Pearce. 1994.  Why  I  Stopped  Reading  Black Athena,  Academic
Questions 7 (6-1-1994) 37.
Wolf, Ursula.  1996.  Litteris et Patriae. Das Janusgesicht der  Historie (Frankfurter
Historische Abhandlungen 37), Stuttgart.
Wolfe, Alan.  1998.  One Nation,  After All. What Middle-Class  Americans  Really
Think about:  God,  Country,  Family, Racism,  Welfare,  Immigration,
Homosexuality, Work, the Right, the Left, and Each Other, New York.
PD Dr. Thomas A. Schmitz
Christian-Albrechts-Universit.t Kiel
Institut f.r Klassische Altertumskunde
Leibnizstr. 8
D24098 Kiel
Germany
e-mail: thschmitz@email.uni-kiel.de

    Source: geocities.com/duarta