A Case Study of Racist Extremism and Disintegrative Social Sanctioning

Todd Ferguson

Sociology 166-571A: Seminar in Deviance and Social Control

Professor Lucia Benaquisto

Department of Sociology, McGill University

December 14, 2000

 

 

INTRODUCTION TO THE CASE STUDY

Anti-Racist Action (ARA) is an anti-racist social movement with a number of traits that distinguish it from other anti-racist social movements. Its origins and continued involvement in North American youth subcultures, along with its distinctively decentralized, anti-hierarchical, and informal organizational structure already separate it from the vast majority of anti-racist groups. Also noteworthy is ARAâs devotion to the social problem of extreme racism -"highly personal attacks on others who are perceived as culturally or biologically inferior" typically characterized by "derogatory slurs and minority name-calling" (Fleras and Elliott: 72). This type of racism constitutes a form of deviance considered by ARA members to be "so dangerous·that they bring special sanctions to bear against it." (Erikson: 6). In fact, the willingness and even eagerness of members to confront extreme racists face-to-face separates Anti-Racist Action from more moderate anti-racist groups. It is also a key factor in their most controversial strategies and tactics.

One such tactic employed by ARA chapters in Chicago, Louisville, Minneapolis, Montréal, and Toronto has been the use of "outings" ö organized rallies in the neighbourhoods of racist extremists where ARA activists go door-to-door naming the targeted racist and informing his or her neighbours about his or her activities. Posters, complete with the racistâs photo and home address are put up on lamposts and placed in mailboxes. At the end of an outing, ARA members gather outside the home of the racist to inform them of the eveningâs activities.

As a manifestation of an external conflict between racists and anti-racist activists, outings have as their ultimate goal the internalization of controls governing behaviour

(Wehowsky, 1978: 74). The means employed to achieve this goal is shame. Outings are a ritualized form of shame sanctioning with a surprising historical lineage. In addition to detailing this lineage, this investigation of ARAâs outings will examine the social control dimensions of shame sanctioning; the tactical use of this particular form of shame sanctioning; its usage in relation to ARAâs views regarding the effectiveness of official social control agencies; criticisms of this type of shame sanctioning and the relevance of these criticisms to outings specifically.

AN OUTING

A deviant person has violated explicit or implicit rules of conduct by which members of their society are expected to govern their behaviour. If the deviant behaviour in question is considered serious enough, other people may come together in a "highly intricate process" of assembling "in a common posture of anger and indignation" to "express their outrage and bear witness" against the deviant activity and individual in question (Erikson: 4-6).

Charles Tilly describes precisely such a ritual in his depiction of the charivari. In this traditional form of French protest, a group of protestors "assemble in the street outside a house; make a racket with songs, shouts and improvised instruments
such as saucepans and washtubs·the words and actions are mocking, often obscene. They describe and condemn the misdeeds of the house's residents." (30).
ARAâs outings are very similar to the French charivaris. The term "outing" derives from a tactic of the radical gay and lesbian movement in which they would

publicly name a celebrity or politician whose homosexual orientation was not known to the general public. In both cases, activists bring forth discrediting information about their target ö information which the target carefully manages to avoid stigmatization (Goffman, 1963: 51). But while gay and lesbian activists out celebrities as part of their strategy to normalize homosexuality by reducing the stigma associated with it, anti-racists out nazis specifically to subject them to stigma and shame.

For ARA, an outing begins when a target has been agreed upon. Ideally, the targeted individual will be an extreme racist with a recent history of violent acts whose photograph and criminal record are in possession of the ARA chapter. While the photograph and criminal background information are useful for making the case against the target on the posters to be put up during the outing, ARA chooses particularly "bad" extreme racists based on recent violence they may have committed as a way of dealing with the most serious problems relating to extreme racism that the community faces.

On the chosen evening for the outing, ARA members gather with members of other radical anti-racist social movements and invited people from the neighbourhood. A description from Chicago ARA outlines what occurs once the party has assembled:

First, teams of anti-racists fanned out through the neighbourhood, going door-to-door with a flyer that exposed the naziâs identity and activities. The flyer also called for the neighbours to take a stand against racism and provided ideas on how the community could unite to create climate of diversity of resistance to prejudice.

 

After covering the neighbourhood, the teams rejoined to march on the naziâs house, chanting loudly and brining a militant presence to their very doorstep. This demonstration forcefully sent the message that we know who they are, where they live, and what theyâre up to ö and that it wouldnât go unchecked. (Author Unknown, 2000: 2).

 

A key factor here is that the demonstration occurs in the targeted racistâs neighbourhood, culminating in a noisy display right outside their house. This demonstrates a recognition by ARA that for their targets, home functions as a "back region - a place, relative to a given performance, where the impression fostered by the performance is knowingly contradicted as a matter of course," but where "the performer can reliably expect that no member of the audience will intrude." (Goffman, 1959: 112-113). One of the goals of the outing, then, is to intentionally intrude on this space and lay bare the contradictions between the racistâs back region and front region performance. By informing neighbours about the racistâs performance as an extreme racist (a performance typically hidden from them), while simultaneously making the "safe space" of home into a front region in which the racist is unprepared to perform his role as a racist, ARA brings to the fore matters that are likely to cause shame in their target because of their disclosure. (Ibid.: 70). By confronting extreme racists in the back regions of their homes, ARA is further likely to discredit racistsâ self-conceptions, which "may deeply involved his ego in his identification with a particular part, establishment, and group." (Ibid.: 143).

 

SHAME, GUILT AND OUTINGS

 

Guilt is considered "a form of self-criticism that results from a comparison of one's action with internalized standards...resulting from violating personal standards...guilt is defined as a feeling of negative self-regard and does not need an audience." (Bierbrauner: 184). The key to guilt as an internalized means of social control

is that it operates as "an emotional expression following a violation of internalized moral codes·wholly independent of others' knowing of the violation." (Karp: 279-280).

Guilt and the a priori knowledge about what one should feel guilty about must be learned through socialization processes. In this way, we "are inculcated with the patterns of conduct demanded by society; fears are instilled in them: conditioning by means of threats or punishments creates displeasure and suppresses unwanted expressions of desires." (Wehowsky: 68). If the effectiveness of guilt to control behaviour can be construed as a major objective of social control, the process by which we learn to feel guilt is often one of shaming.

Unlike guilt, shame can be defined as "a reaction to criticism of others and a fear of rejection and withdrawal of love, resulting from the existence of a real or imagined audience of one's misdeed." (Bierbrauner: 184). The sanctions involved in shame are external, rather than internal, and depend upon the presence of an audience. Specifically, shameâs power lies in the fear of losing social esteem or social status because of violating a social proscription. (Karp: 280; Wehowsky: 75). In this manner, "shaming has functioned as a means of social control for centuries ö certainly as long as reference to

"guardian angels" has created an omniscient audience in the minds of children. (Elias: 134).

Viewing outings as an attempt to instill a sense of guilt in the offending racist by first activating shame in them makes sense, particularly given their focus on the offenderâs home. Braithwaite notes that "shaming is more likely to be heeded when undertaken by a loved one, whose respect and affection it would be more painful to lose," (167), and that "·sanctions imposed by relatives, friends or a personally-relevant collectivity have more effect on criminal behaviour than sanctions imposed by a remote legal authority·because repute in the eyes of close acquaintances matters more to people than the opinions or actions of criminal justice officials." (69). By making the targeted racistâs home address a matter of public knowledge, ARA seems aware that the stigma they hope to inflict upon them will likely also affect family members who may live with the offender. Rather than concerning themselves with the injustice of tarring all residents with the same brush, ARA appears to be attempting to stimulate familial involvement in sanctioning the offender through mutual implication. Families are "the key social units which take responsibility for reintegrating the convicted offender." (Ibid.: 63), and this mutual implication may compel the offenderâs family to sanction the offenderâs behaviour.

 

THE EMPLOYMENT OF SHAME SANCTIONING

 

Karp notes that "retribution reaffirms the moral order." (278). Kai Erikson provides a comprehensive description of this process in his book Wayward Puritans. For Erikson, communities sanction the deviants among them through rituals that move the

deviant "out of his normal position in society, transferring him into a distinctive deviant role." These rituals "provide a formal confrontation between the deviant suspect and representatives of his community; they announce some judgement about the nature of the deviancy, and they perform an act of social placement, assigning him to a special role which redefines his position in society." (Braithwaite: 18; Erikson: 15). The shaming ritual also clearly informs members of a community about the boundaries of acceptable behaviour in a means more readily-understood than if it was conveyed in abstracted language. (Erikson: 11). This conveyance carries with it a deterrent effect on all who witness the stigmatization and misfortune placed upon the outcast. (Braithwaite: 20).

Shaming rituals have power because of how we form our conceptions of self. Individuals evaluate their social position in relation to others based largely on the opinions of others. Social identity theory posits that individuals construct the self partially on the basis of group membership, which makes any threat of rejection by the group also a threat to self-identity. Shaming sanctions threaten the social position of individuals by threatening to injure or sever the social bond between the individual and the group, diminishing the deviantâs social status and ultimately threatening their social self and self-identity. (Karp: 277-280).

Outings are a specific style of shaming ritual, involving what Karp calls "public exposure penalties," the central component of which "is to bring the crime to the attention of the public so that the public may respond with shaming." (281). This process invokes the power of the "unofficial, informal, face-to-face, interpersonal regulation in which we routinely engage one another" (Millman: 253) in the hopes of

eventually causing an internal association of the behaviour with shame and embarrassment within the individual. (Wehowsky: 69). The trauma of being labeled as a violent racist in the very-public ritual of the outing may be enough to force the labeled person "to look at herself and she may not like what she sees. Then she may be forced to rehabilitate herself." (Braithwaite: 20). For ARA members, being a violent neo-Nazi is something they wish to make their targets feel guilt about by first feeling shame about it, caused by shaming sanctions invoked in their interpersonal relations with their friends, family, and neighbours. The role of these important others in sanctioning the individual is crucial to an outingâs success because "the feeling of shame is clearly a social function molded according to the social structure" (Elias: 138) ö meaning that these actors are far more likely to successfully invoke shame in the outed individual.

 

OUTINGS AS CHALLENGES TO OFFICIAL SOCIAL CONTROL

 

Many scholars have noted a gradual shift "from primary means of social control, such as the family, the neighbourhood, and the community, to secondary means, such as the police, the press, the political machine, and the courts." (Pitts: 383: emphasis mine). Charles Tilly "shows the opening of a breach between bourgeois law and the law of popular custom," as commencing in 18th-century France, with "the intervention of the police in a nonviolent charivari." (32). It is interesting to note that, some two centuries later, Montreal police mirrored the actions of the gendarmes in Tillyâs example, when they intervened in an ARA-organized non-violent outing, arresting two participants. (Maddux: 2).

As a result of this shift, most people now assume "that the regulation of sanctions and norms, whether or not they are made explicit, belong to the realm of the legal system." (Bierbrauner: 184). By selecting violent offenders as targets for outing campaigns, ARA is in effect questioning the legal systemâs ability to ensure compliance to the norms of society. This sentiment is clearly read in an ARA press release that asks if Montreal police "cannot protect Montréalers from racist violence, or prevent the murder of people like Christian Thomas by violent, organized fascists known to them, or even bring such murderers to justice, who will do their job for them?" (ARA Montreal: 2).

There appears to be a general cynicism and suspicion regarding the role and effectiveness of the police and the legal system among ARA members similar to the manner that middle-class white residents saw the police in Andersonâs study of a changing inner-city neighbourhood. (131). Here we see another crucial distinction between other anti-racist organizations. While moderate anti-racist groups press for legislative and other forms of political change and work closely with the police, Anti-Racist Action rejects working with the polity. Like Waters' new citizens movements of France (181), ARA demonstrates a genuine mistrust and hostility towards existing political structures and attempt to work in complete autonomy from political parties and institutions. Their unifying document states that ARA does not "rely on the cops or the courts," (Author Unknown, 1998). Another factor not to be ignored is ARA's hostile analysis to the polity itself as a racist institution. ARA chapters claim that racism "is

perpetrated by the government and its internal army of cops." (Author Unknown). This may in part explain the adoption of the tactic of outings.

In this context, outings may be seen as attempts to re-assert informal social control mechanisms in areas of life where formal social control agencies claim exclusive jurisdiction. Primary groups such as family, friends and neighbours have an advantage over the impersonalities of the criminal justice system in that "their sanctions are pervasive in their incidence and impact and that even the deviant is usually highly motivated to maintain group membership." (Pitts: 389). Informal sanctions can also have a stronger affect on deviant behaviour "than sanctions imposed by a remote legal authority·because repute in the eyes of close acquaintances matters more to people than the opinions or actions of criminal justice officials." (Braithwaite: 69). ARA may claim that by attempting to reassert the importance of such informal sanctions, they may be more effective at curbing racist extremist violence than the efforts of official social control agencies will be, and even that they may be able to prevent such violence, whereas official social control mechanisms are likely to only come into play after violence has occurred.

However, all this is not to say that ARA wishes to claim the exclusive rights of using informal shame sanctioning as the sole means with which to contend with violent racist extremists. It is more probable that the movement takes a somewhat pragmatic approach, recognizing that the police and the criminal justice system do have a role to play. Even their unifying documentâs statement about not relying "on the cops or the courts" is immediately qualified by the statement that "this doesnât mean we never go to

court." (Author Unknown, 1998). Evidence does suggest that informal social control mechanisms such as outings can complement and enhance the efforts of formal social control mechanisms. Bierbrauner notes that the legal system is most effective when it is based "on more subtle forms of social control like group pressure." (182). Braithwaite concurs with this assessment, going so far as to claim that "potent shaming directed at offenders is the essential necessary condition for low crime rates." (4). Perhaps when both ARA and the police come to view outings as complementary to the efforts of the criminal justice system will their effectiveness truly manifest.

 

 

 

 

CRITICISMS OF SHAME SANCTIONS AND THEIR APPLICABILITY TO OUTINGS

 

In his compelling argument for reintegrative shaming, Braithwaite cautions that "shaming can be counter-productive if it is disintegrative rather than reintegrative ·shaming controls crime when it is at the same time powerful and bounded by ceremonies to reintegrate the offender back into the community of responsible citizens." (4). The criticisms of shaming sanctions are numerous, however some of these criticisms may not be wholly applicable to the outing as employed by ARA.

A major criticism of most shaming sanctions is their disintegrative consequences. The goal of shame sanctioning is the desistence of the offending behaviour, desistence which "is related to dissociation from delinquent peers and reintegration into conventional adult relationships, while persisters maintained delinquent friends." (Gulotta: 156-A). The irony is that many of the characteristics of shaming sanctions may ultimately discourage this disassociation and reintegration. One problem is the

irreversible nature of shaming sanctions. The deviant is ushered into the deviant position by a decisive and often dramatic ceremony, yet is retired from it without public notice, and therefore, without the communityâs permission to resume a non-deviant role and normal life. (Erikson: 16). While ARA mounts a noisy and attention-getting demonstration that encourages community stigmatization of a targeted racist when it engages in an outing, there are no equivalent rituals should the offender collaborate with authority, accept the stigmatized role she is placed in, and attempt to make amends.

This omission can even lead to further commitment to the offending behaviour through what Merton describes as a "self-fulfilling prophecy," as the offenderâs opportunities to return to a non-stigmatized role are now greatly reduced. (Erikson: 17). One consequence of this effect is to push the outcasted offender further towards or into a criminal or deviant subculture. (Braithwaite: 68; Karp: 283). Once ostracized through shame sanctioning, "the offender's opportunities for successful conventional existence are reduced and the offender seeks the company and approval of other outcasts" (Karp: 284) in subcultures that may "supply the outcast with the opportunity to reject her rejecters, thereby maintaining a form of self-respect." (Braithwaite: 14).

Further involvement in a deviant subculture may have precisely the opposite effect hoped for by those who participate in the shaming ritual. Critics have claimed that oppositional subcultures help their members reject the dominant moral order by rewarding noncomformity and delinquency (Karp: 284); use their status as outcasts to turn the tables on social control agents by "rejecting the rejectors" (Braithwaite: 55); and

can even make offenders impervious to shaming, for they do not have a position in the community worth preserving." (Karp: 287).

These effects of shame sanctioning and stigmatization are not guaranteed, however. Just as a deviant is not deviant continuously, but engages in conventional behaviour most of the time, the rejection of the moral order by the oppositional subculture is far from total. Subcultural members, for the most part, abide by the norms and standards of behaviour also salient in conventional society. In addition, the offenders signified as deviants are never complete outcasts. This would be an over-simplification that ignores the multiplicity of relations, roles and identities of all individuals. Only rarely is any offender completely ostracized.

One reason ARA conducts outings is to reveal discrediting facts hidden by extreme racists from their neighbours and, often, members of their own families. That extreme racists keep their controversial views hidden and become extremely upset when this information is made public during an outing testifies to the importance of their position in the community, no matter how marginal it may be. It also speaks to the communitarian aspects still present in communities in the highly individualized present-day North America.

In fact, "If a person cares nothing about the disapproval of others, shame is a useless tool," (Karp: 288), be it of the disintegrative or reintegrative variety. "But such a person is extremely rare·the trick is to increase the stake of the offender in the larger community." (Ibid.). Outings play on the stakes the offender has in the larger community

by attempting to involve actors relevant to the offenderâs other roles and identities ö be they family members, loved ones, or neighbours.

Much then appears to be dependent on the degree to which a community can be described as communitarian. Effective shaming works best when individuals "are enmeshed in multiple relationships of inter-dependency; societies shame more effectively when they are communitarian." (Braithwaite: 14). But shame sanctioning by peers and intermediate groups simply "cannot work in an individualist culture" (Ibid.: 171), because it is the threat of social exclusion, "of not being regarded as a worthy member of the community, that is the primary sanction in a shame penalty." (Karp: 280).

Are shame sanctions ineffective because of the individualistic and alienating nature of modern North American society? Braithwaite has noted how the high interdependency and highly-developed communitarianism of Japanese society enhance the effectiveness of reintegrative shaming. (62). While North American society is not nearly as interdependent or communitarian as Japanese society may be, the two are not polar opposites, either. This fact is evidenced by the high concern Americans place on the opinions of others, as well as the development of consciences through social interaction, normative influence and the internalization of standards in both societies. (Karp: 290). The extreme concern shown by targeted racists when subjected to an outing evidences that North American society is still communitarian enough for shaming to be effective to some degree. The success of outings hinges partially on this concern deriving from the targeted individual defining her identity at least partially "in terms of their ingroup, such as family or local community," because in these cases "the latter will

have a major influence on their conduct, whereas individuals who feel that they are free from tight social control may be less influenced by social values and norms from their immediate social environment." (Bierbrauner: 183).

Some other reasons to question the effectiveness of outings as shame sanctioning stem from the fact that it is racist extremists who are targeted. Erikson has noted that communities judge deviant individuals by sifting and responding to a few deviant details among an array of conventional behaviour. (6-7). The problem with shaming sanctions, according to Braithwaite, Karp and others, is that such penalties "blur the distinction between moral condemnation of the act and of the actor. (Karp: 286). This point is emphasized in Braithwaite's model of reintegrative shaming, in which it is crucially important to ensuring "that the deviance label is applied to the behaviour rather than the person, and that this is done under the assumption that the disapproved behaviour is transient, performed by an essentially good person." (55).

It is very difficult to describe someone who strongly, even primarily, self-identifies as a neo-Nazi as "an essentially good person." The line between the disapproved behaviour and the individual's very identity in these cases is highly indistinct. This close relationship between the deviant behaviour and the self-identity so cherished by the deviant individual explains why the humiliation inflicted through shame sanctioning may generate anger rather than remorse in the offender, thus enabling the racist "to shift his or her self-concept from victimizer to victim." (Karp: 286). This is reflected again and again in racist extremist literature, which typically portrays white males as victims and the so-called white race as an endangered species.

The informal nature of a shaming ritual like the charivari or its modern-day version, the outing, can cause concern regarding the possibility of the innocent suffering the shame and stigma meant for the guilty. Braithwaite claims that "informal means of control are, because of their informality, probably more likely to convict the innocent." (158). This is precisely the kind of criticism leveled against ARA for outing racists, which members of more moderate anti-racist organizations have characterized as attempts to "create disorder and take the law into their own hands."(Author Unknown, 1996). It has already been noted that ARA may partially hope that some of the shame and embarrassment they inflict by informing neighbours about the exact residence of an extreme racist will be shared by their target's family, in the hopes that this may spur the family to action. But is it fair to force family members to share this shame? This question seems difficult enough without including the possibility on acting on wrong information. When I asked members of one ARA chapter embarking on an outing how they knew that the occupants of a targeted house were racist extremists, they informed me that they had heard second-hand from people that the occupants held racist beliefs and had recently assaulted some people. At the outing's climax the group knocked on the door of the targeted nazi, after spending two hours distributing posters with his photo and address on them throughout the neighbourhood, only to be told by his brother that he no longer lived there. The next week, rumours circulated that a large group of bat-wielding men converged on the house just days after the outing.

While Braithwaite is correct to point out this shortcoming of all informal means of social control, he provides no evidence that formal social control mechanisms are more

apt to prosecute and persecute only the guilty. In fact, given much-publicized wrongful conviction cases in both Canada and the United States, and the more severe consequences of the criminal justice system, there may be a stronger case to be made for informal sanctioning over formal sanctioning.

Another common criticism of outings is that they may well encourage violence instead of discouraging it. The logic behind this criticism is that extreme racists will attempt to compensate for the humiliation suffered during the outing by re-establishing their discredited identity as racist "warriors" as quickly as possible, by stepping up their violent activities. Only one of the five ARA chapters contacted reported an increase in violent activity after outing a racist - members of the Louisville chapter were attacked by ten neo-Nazis the day after outing one of them. However, some ARA members pointed out how such a reaction can be construed as evidence of the tactical success of their outing ö the racists targeted were obviously affected enough to come after ARA members in retaliation, which was argued as being better than having them randomly attack their more "usual" targets for violence ö people of colour, gays and lesbians, and others.

Despite these numerous criticisms of outings and other forms of disintegrative shame sanctioning, the reintegrative shaming model does not necessarily stand as an option beyond criticism itself, and the question of how to deal with racist extremists illustrates some of these criticisms well. When an offender faces shaming sanctions, they have three possible responses to choose from - "they may protest their innocence; admit guilt but demonstrate that the action did not in fact cause harm (the norm, not the violation, is unjust); or accept responsibility for causing harm." (Karp: 286). The former

choice is a non-collaborative response, in the latter two, the offender collaborates and cooperates to some extent with the social control agents who are attempting to label and stigmatize her. For reintegrative shaming to work, the offender must not choose the former option - they have to adopt a repentant role. (Braithwaite: 165).

The reintegrative shaming model works in two stages; in the first stage, the deviant is subjected to shaming and expressions of disapproval for their behaviour. This stage is followed "gestures of reacceptance into the community of law-abiding citizens." (Braithwaite: 55). Throughout both stages, communication between the offender and the community must be maintained "to facilitate apology and recompense." (Ibid.: 161). But these offers of reacceptance are conditional upon the offenderâs offering of apology and recompense ö something rarely, if ever, offered by neo-Nazis. This is unsurprising, given the degree of importance given to their self-identity as neo-Nazis, "proud Aryan warriors," etc. Braithwaite himself concedes that "the citizen is ultimately free to reject these attempts to persuade through social disapproval." (9). If the role and identity valued most by the deviant individual is an oppositional one, reintegrative shaming is not an option and the only hope to persuade the individual to comply with the behaviour boundaries of the community may be to threaten other social bonds, roles and identities with disintegrative shaming sanctions.

 

CONCLUSION

 

Outings serve as both public ritual and shame sanction in a way rarely seen since the days of the French charivari. To amass a large group of people who loudly proclaim the misdeeds of an offender to the offenderâs neighbours and from the offenderâs very

doorstep seems to smack of vigilantism and to go against societal norms surrounding privacy and fair trial. However, in actively engaging and organizing outings, Anti-Racist Action is re-invoking a primary means of social control that has gradually been replaced by the secondary means of the bourgeois, formalized rule of law. In doing so, ARA is making a statement about the saliency of neighbourhood communitarianism and social interdependency. They may also be reinforcing communitarianism and interdependency by encouraging community members to come together and participate in the ritual of behavioural boundary definition.

Outings are essentially highly-public disintegrative shaming rituals. Because of the lack of reintegrative qualities, they are readily-criticized as doing more harm than good. But perhaps due to the non-collaborative nature of their intended targets, it is difficult to devise a workable reintegrative shaming strategy to employ against racist extremists. In any event, it is obvious that formal social control techniques do not work by themselves. Perhaps any effort at bringing back informal shaming sanctions, be they disintegrative or reintegrative, can help ensure the safety of everyone within the community.

 

 

 

 

 

APPENDIX A - The Four Points of Unity of the Anti-Racist Action Network

The Anti-Racist Action Network consists of people from all different backgrounds, with a lot of different viewpoints. With over 150 ARA chapters out there, it's not surprising that no two are alike!

What we all agree on, however, is the following:

1) WE GO WHERE THEY GO: Whenever fascists are organizing or active in public, we're there. We don't believe in ignoring them or staying away from them. Never let the nazis have the street!

2) WE DON'T RELY ON THE COPS OR THE COURTS TO DO OUR WORK FOR US: This doesn't mean we never go to court. But we must rely on ourselves to protect ourselves and stop the fascists.

3) NON-SECTARIAN DEFENSE OF OTHER ANTI-FASCISTS: In ARA, we have lots of different groups and individuals. We don't agree about everything and we have a right to differ openly. But in this movement an attack on one is an attack on us all. We stand behind each other.

4) We support abortion rights and reproductive freedom. ARA intends to do the hard work necessary to build a broad, strong movement against racism, sexism, anti-Semitism, homophobia, discrimination against the disabled, the oldest, the youngest and the most oppressed people. WE INTEND TO WIN!

 

 

 

 

 

SOURCES

 

Anderson, Elijah. Streetwise : Race, Class, and Change in an Urban Community. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press), 1990.

 

Anonymous. "On The Prowl: Anti-Racist Action And Developing Anti-Fascist Strategies In Toronto" Antifascism in Canada (Spring 1996) pp. 36-43.

 

Anti-Racist Action Montréal, "ARA Outs Another Neo-Nazi" Press Release, May 22, 1999.

 

Anti-Racist Action Montréal, "Cops Ignore Racist Ties To Murder, Charges Anti-Racist Group" Press Release, August 8, 2000.

 

Author Unknown, " The Battle of Saint Paul," fr. Fighting Words: The Street Zine of Anti-Racist Action Minneapolis, pp. 2-3.

 

Author Unknown. "Anti-Racist Action : Introducing the ARA Network." (Fall 1998).

 

Author Unknown. "What Is ARA?" Toronto Anti-Racist Action web page.

http://www.web.net/~ara.

 

Author Unknown. "The 411 on ARA" Minneapolis Anti-Racist Action web page. http://www.oocities.org//CapitolHill/Lobby/2853/411.html

 

Author Unknown. "Smash The World Church Of The Creator! Create Anti-Racist Resistance." The Alarm ö Newsletter of Chicago Anti-Racist Action. No. 3, Spring 2000.

 

Bernstein, Mary. "Celebration and Suppression: The Strategic Uses Of Identity by the Lesbian and Gay Movement" American Journal of Sociology. 103:3, pp. 531-565.

 

Bierbrauner, Gunter. "Reactions To Violation Of Normative Standards: A Cross-Cultural Analysis Of Shame And Guilt." International Journal of Psychology. Vol. 27, No. 2. April, 1992. pp. 181-193.

 

Braithwaite, John. Crime, Shame and Reintegration. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 1989.

 

Elias, Norbert. The History of Manners ö The Civilizing Process: Volume I. (New York: Pantheon Books), 1978.

 

Erikson, Kai T. Wayward Puritans: A Study in the Sociology of Deviance. (New York: Wiley), 1966.

 

 

 

Sources contâd.

 

Fleras, Augie and Jean Leonard Elliott, Unequal Relations: An Introduction To
Race, Ethnic and Aboriginal Dynamics in Canada.
(Scarborough: Prentice Hall),
1996.

 

Goffman, Erving. The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life. (Garden City: Doubleday Anchor), 1959.

 

Goffman, Erving. Stigma: Notes on the Management of Spoiled Identity. (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall), 1963.

 

Gulotta, Ronald Gerard. "Persistence and Desistence in Delinquent Careers: A Test of Braithwaite's Reintegrative Shaming Theory." Dissertation Abstracts International. Vol. 55, No. 1. July 1994, p. 156-A.

 

Karp, David R. "The Judicial and Judicious Use of Shame Penalties." Crime and Delinquency. Vol. 44, No. 2, April 1998, pp. 277-294.

 

Maddux, George. "White Power Outage." The Montreal Mirror, November 30 ö December 7, 2000.

 

Millman, Marcia. "She Did It All For Love: A Feminist View of the Sociology of Deviane." Sociological Inquiry. 1975, Vol. 45, No. 2-3, pp. 251-279.

 

Pitts, Jesse R. "The Concept." fr. Social Control.

 

Tilly, Charles. The Contentious French. (Cambridge: Harvard University
Press), 1986.

 

Waters, Sarah. "New Social Movement Politics in France: The Rise of Civic Forms of Mobilisation" West European Politics. 21:3, pp. 170-186.

 

Wehowsky, Andreas. "Making Ourselves More Flexible Than We Are - Reflections On Norbert Elias." New German Critique. Vol. 15. Fall, 1978, pp. 65-80.