The Free Market Environmentalism Case
Against Intellectual Property.

This article started out as an argument for why private intellectual property rights were wrong. It has evolved into a more general theory about what government legitimately -- for those of you who believe minarchy is justified -- should be allowed to protect and what it shouldn't. I'll still use the example of the inappropriateness of intellectual works deserving the designation of private property to prove my point, and then I'll generalize.

In conversation with objectivists who support IP, Libertarians who oppose IP have sometimes stated, "How can you defend IP with-out government?"

To this the objectivist has stated, "I don't know. I'm not an anarcho-capitalist." Thus dismissing the question as irrelevant because government exists to protect our property, and thus government protection of IP must be legitimate. She mistakenly assumes that only anarchists are opposed to IP, and that minarchists support it.

But indeed, the question of whether a particular type of property is defendable with-out government is very relevant. As we shall see.

To pull a page from Free Market Environmentalism (FME), there are three characteristics that a type of good needs in order to become deserving of the distinction 'Private.'  Private Property must be definable, defendable, and tradable.

Private Property Rights must be definable: "The physical attributes of the resource must be specified in a clear and concise manner; they must be measurable." (20)

This should be obvious. Everybody has a right to defend their property right? But, if property rights can't be defined, how do you defend it? How do you defend something if you don't know exactly what it is you're defending? If you don't know exactly what's yours and what isn't? How do you trade something if you don't know exactly what it is you're trading?

In spite of it's obviousness, I think many libertarians don't think much about it. They just assume that because government is instituted to protect our right to own private property (in the classical liberal tradition), that government should protect anything baring the name property. We all know however, that government loves to engage in NEWSPEAK. In other words, just because government calls something private property, doesn't mean it is. Why would government do this? To expand its power and legitimacy. If it can hoodwink you into believing that many things are property which really aren't, it can make you think expanding its police powers and other defense agencies are completely appropriate.

Private Property Rights must be defendable:
A rectangular survey may define surface rights to land, but conflicts are inevitable if there is no way to defend the boundaries and prevent other incompatible uses. Barbed wire provided an inexpensive way to defend property rights on the western frontier; locks and chains do the same for parked bicycles. But enforcing one's rights to peace and quiet by "fencing out" sound waves may be much more difficult, as will keeping other people's waists out of the groundwater supply. Whenever the use of property cannot be monitored or enforced, conflicts are inevitable and trades are impossible." (20) i

This is not to say that you only have those rights you're personally able to defend. It just means it needs to be possible to defend it. You need to be able to monitor the boundaries so its possible for you to know whether or not transgression has occurred. If it's not possible for you to know whether or not transgression's occurred, it's not possible to even try an figure out when, where, and who is doing the transgressing. You can't even investigate, simply because, in your mind, you'd have no reason to. This isn't to say that stealing is OK if the person you're stealing from can't know they've been stolen from. It's to say; if it's impossible to know, it's not private property to begin with. It's also not very tradable. If it's not possible to know from one day to the next if a certain type of property has diminished or not (Not necessarily do to theft, but maybe to bugs, or some natural phenomena), you can't know how much you have to trade. Thus, if you can't monitor a certain type of property, you can't trade it. Monitoring doesn't need to be extensive. You just need to be able to know, from one time to the next if you have the same amount of something as you did previously. Perhaps another way to put is, is that it needs to be "countable."

This is basically a more refined way of stating the classical liberal ideal of homesteading, in the tradition of Hume. For our purposes homesteading is simply, "Marking the property as yours." (See, Against Intellectual Property, for a more expansive discussion of homesteading..)

Private Property Rights must be tradable.
In contrasts to the costs of measuring and monitoring resource uses, which are mainly determined by the physical nature of the property and technology, the ability to exchange is determined largely by the legal environment. Although well-defined and enforced rights allow the owner to enjoy the benefits of using his property, legal restrictions on the sale of that property preclude the potential for gains from trade. Suppose that a group of fishermen values water for fish habitat more highly than farmers value the same water for irrigation. If the fishermen are prohibited from renting or purchasing the water from the farmers, then gains from trade will not be realized and potential wealth will not be created. Moreover, the farmer will have less incentive to leave the water in the stream." (20-21) ii

Another thing that libertarians sometimes don't understand is that property rights are dynamic. They evolve as needs, wants, and new technologies evolve. "It is useful to reiterate the importance of the evolution of property rights and the common law. As clean water and air become more valuable, entrepreneurs have a greater incentive to define and enforce rights to the resources." (150)

Thus it is individuals in the market that decide whether a specific type of property is worth defining. It is the market that figures out the definitions of rights. Property rights may be defined differently in different geographies simply because the geography is different. To quote Walter Prescott Webb, author of The Great Plains,

The Easterner, with his background of forest and farm, could not always understand the man of the cattle kingdom. One went on foot, the other went on horseback one carried his law in books, the other carried it strapped round his waist. One represented tradition, the other represented innovation; one responded to convention, the other responded to necessity and evolved his own conventions. Yet the man of the timber and the town made the law for the man of the plain; the plainsman. finding this law unsuited to his needs, broke it and was called lawless. [206, quoted from FME (27)]

This is not to say that life was violent in the West, it's just to say that property rights were defined differently. Specifically the way water rights were defined in the east didn't make sense in the west. Waterfall was less; streams and rivers were fewer. Water was scarcer, therefore, definitions of what constitutes water property rights needed to be more precise. iii
 
In conversation with libertarians and objectivists in particular who believe in intellectual property, I've often taken a page from Steven Kinsella's Against  Intellectual  Property. Mainly, we should reject utilitarian arguments as they have no basis in morality. I've used his argument that Private Property rights are for allocating scarcity, and that since ideas aren't scarce they aren't deserving of the designation of private property.

I'm countered with. "So, I'm not allowed to use utilitarian arguments even though the basis of private property rights are utilitarian?" Of course, it's quite debatable from a utilitarian standpoint whether or not IP does benefit society, iv but that misses the point. This individual was saying that appealing to scarcity was utilitarian in and of itself. It took me awhile to know out how to respond to this.

Now I know.

1) The only legitimate function of government is the collective (socialized) manifestation of self defense. Libertarians, minarchists and anarchists alike understand this. It was the theory Thomas Jefferson used to write the Declaration of Independents.

. . .We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created  equal, that  they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable  Rights, that among  these are Life, Liberty and the pursuit of  Happiness. --That to secure these  rights, Governnments are instituted  among Men, deriving their just powers from  the consent of the  governed. . .

Each individual has the right to life, liberty, property, and the pursuit of happiness. Government was instituted to defend these rights. Remember that. Defend is key.

2) It's the entrepreneurs, investors, and other individuals in the free market who figure out how to define property rights. When a certain type of property starts becoming scarce, it gives individuals incentives to figure out more precise definitions of ownership. The scarcer the type of property, the more refined the definition becomes. Thus it is scarcity that gives people incentive to figure out property right definitions. With-out scarcity private entrepreneurs would not go through the expense of figuring out how to define property rights to something. Thus, scarcity is important, but only because with-out it people wouldn't figure out definitions. And if you can't define a certain type of property, how can you know what you have? It's a logical absurdity. "I own something, but It's impossible for me to know what exactly this 'something' is, and even if  it weren't, its impossible for me to know exactly you how much I own."

Since the only legitimate function of government is to defend our rights, It doesn't have a legitimate right to defend them until after the market has (at the very least) figured out methods to define and monitor them. Free people in the market can't ask government to defend our property rights if we don't even know what those property rights are. To think otherwise would be absurd.

See, government is our servant, and we (individuals) are its master. Government morally isn't allowed to do anything that individuals can't do. It's not morally justified to defend a property right that its masters can't define. Can the master command his servant to defend that which the master knows not what?

Only AFTER the market has figured out definitions for a certain type of private property right does government have justification to defend it. (The anarchist would say collective defense isn't justified either. But we're assuming the minarchist stance for the sake of argument.)

Thus government is illegitimate in many of the types of "property" rights it defends. The reason is these private property right definitions didn't evolve in the market, but were imposed by government legislative fiat. This is inherently immoral. The only legitimate purpose of government is to defend private property. It's not allowed to define it. Imagine would kind of totalitarian world we'd live in if government were allowed to define our property rights. In fact this is the basic misunderstanding that most people have. They think that it's government that grants us our rights. This is false. We already have rights prior to the existence of government. The classical liberal theory of Lock, and others was that we already have pre-existing rights and that government is instituted to defend those rights. By that theory, if we don't have rights in the first place, what's the point of government? I fail to see the distinction between government granting rights and government defining them. If government could define our rights. It could (and would) define them away into oblivion.

That means that not only is government protection of intellectual property immoral, but also government protection of spectrum space, wild-life (hunting and fishing licenses which basically imply that government owns it), air (pollution regulations), noise regulations, etc.

Think about how much freer we would be be if government didn't invent property right definitions through legislative fiat to expand its 'legitimacy' by protecting them. Defining such things through fiat, disincentivizes the market from evolving and figuring out definitions that make sense. In fact many times by fiatly defining rights, government redistributes wealth ('give' to one at the plunder of someone else) if local customs are leaning to different definitions of private property then the government imposes.

Thus the question of how a certain type of property can be defined and defended, or could have evolved, with-out government is just as relevant to the minarchist as it is to the anarchist about what types of entities are deserving of the designation private property. If it couldn't have evolved with-out government, it shouldn't be allowed with government. Simply because government shouldn't be allowed to do anything that free people can't do.

Tracy Saboe

 i As an aside the free market HAS figured out how to define and monitor ground water and aquifer rights in places where such rights have been allowed to develop. Not in the US where most state and local governments claims ownership of the water, but in places where government has stayed out of the way on this particular issue, the market has worked it out. Scotland is probably the best example of how private markets for various types of private water property rights have evolved..

ii This is also potentially an argument for market anarchism because political law intrinsically, by its bureaucratic nature, cannot evolve to account for the dynamic changes in new technologies, and peoples needs and wants like the market does. But that's a different argument.

iii This is also why, if government is to exist, it needs to exist as locally as possible. It is for this reason, I believe the existence of Federal, and State governments are completely illegitimate. They are so far removed from the customs of the locals that they're intrinsically incapable of codifying law that makes sense to every locality in the state, much less the country.

iv See also, "Patents Are An Economic Absurdity" and "The Libertarian case against Intellectual Property Rights." Also Steven Kinesella's IP page.

Home