The
Age of Reason
Frank
Manuel
The
Enlightenment owes its substance to the thought of a relatively small group of
eighteenth-century philosophes who came from many countries but were centered in
France. Although they often argued among themselves, there was a set of
approaches and propositions upon which most of them agreed. In the following
selection Frank E. Manuel, a historian of ideas from Brandeis and New York
University, analyzes the philosophes'new moral outlook, an outlook that seems
particularly modern.
Consider:
How the primary documents support or contradict Manuel's interpretation; the
ways in which the moral outlook described here is overly optimistic and naive;
the elements of this outlook that make the most sense to you for today's world.
Despite
their sharp cleavages and varying interests, there was a common ground on which
all the intellectuals could stand, and from their inconsistent and even
incompatible tendencies there emerged a moral outlook distinct from that of the
previous age. The eighteenth-century philosophers popularized general precepts
of conduct which in time were widely accepted in most civilized societies. They
made aggressive war look odious and mocked the ideal of military glory. They
preached religious toleration, free speech, a free press. They were in favor of
the sanctions of law to protect individual liberties and they were against
tyranny which governed by caprice. They wanted equality of all citizens before
the law and they were opposed to any recognition of social distinctions when men
were brought to justice. They abhorred torture and other barbaric punishments
and pleaded for their abolition; they believed that punishment should fit the
crime and should be imposed only to restrain potential malefactors. They wanted
freedom of movement across state boundaries both for individuals and articles of
commerce. Most of them believed that it did not require the threat of eternal
torment in hell to make moral ideas generally accepted among mankind. They were
convinced that the overwhelming number of men, if their natural goodness were
not perverted in childhood, would act in harmony with simple rules and the
dictates of rational principles without the necessity for severe restraints and
awful punishments.
In
summary, though the philosophes did not solve the problem of the existence of
evil and suffering in the world, they did manage to establish in European
society a general consensus about conduct which is evil, a moral attitude which
still sustains us. Despite their subservient behavior toward some of the
European despots and the social anarchy ultimately inherent in their doctrines
of absolute self-interest, the eighteenth-century men of letters did formulate a
set of moral principles which to this day remain basic to any discussion of
human rights. The deficiencies of their optimistic moral and political outlook
are by now visible, but they did venture the first bold examination of reality
since the Greeks and they dared to set forth brandnew abstractions about man and
the universe. They taught their contemporaries to view the institutions of
church and state in the light of reason and to judge them by the simple
criterion of human happiness.
The
Party of Humanity:
The
Struggling Philosophes
Peter
Gay
There
are major disagreements among historians who study the Enlightenment and the
philosophes. One group holds that the philosophes were shallow, destructive
dilettantes who enjoyed rubbing shoulders with the elite while poking fun at
eighteenth-century institutions and practices. Another group holds that the
philosophes were sincere, thoughtful intellectuals who braved much to express
many of the most important precepts of the modern world. Peter Gay takes into
account both of these views in his highly respected interpretations of the
French Enlightenment, The Party of Humanity: Essays in the French Enlightenment.
In the following selection, Gay focuses on the psychological underpinnings of
much of the philosophes' struggle.
Consider:
What was so difficult about the philosophes' struggle; any connections between
what Gay terms the "struggle of the philosophes" and their "two
enemies 11 ; what historical or institutional changes the philosophes would have
supported, according to Gay.
The
philosophes had two enemies: the institutions of Christianity and the idea of
hierarchy. And they had two problems: God and the masses. Both the enemies and
the problems were related and woven into the single task of rethinking their
world. The old questions that Christianity had answered so fully for so many men
and so many centuries, had to be asked anew: What as Kant put it - what can I
know? What ought I to do? What may I hope?
Science
itself did not answer these questions. It only suggested - ever more insistently
as the century went on -that the old answers were wrong. Now, the philosophes
were products of Christian homes and Christian schools. If they became enemies
of Christianity, they did so not from indifference or ignorance: they knew their
Bible, their catechism, their Church Fathers, their apologetics. And they knew,
because it had been drummed into them early, the fate that awaits heretics or
atheists in the world to come. Their anticlerical humor therefore has the bitter
intimacy of the family joke; to embrace materialism was an act of rejection.
The
struggle of the philosophes was a struggle for freedom. They did not fully
understand it, but to the extent that they did understand it, they knew their
situation to be filled with terror and delight. They felt the anxiety and
exhilaration of the explorer who stands before the unknown.
To
use such existentialist language may seem like a rather portentous way of
describing men noted for their sociability and frivolity. It is of course true
that the philosophes did not suffer alone: they had the comforting company of
elegant salons and of respectable philosophical forebears.
Yet
even the supple Voltaire, who had been initiated into unbelief by fashionable
teachers, was not free from the symptoms of this struggle. Much of his mockery
was a weapon in a grim fight, and a device to keep up his own morale. Much of
his philosophical rumination on free will reveals the persistence of a
troublesome inner conflict. . . .
I
am not simply arguing that the philosophes were less cheerful than they appeared
in their social roles-most of us are. Nor that they suffered personal crises
-philosophers, especially young philosophhers, often do. I am arguing that the
philosophes' anguish was related to the crisis in their Christian civilization;
that (to use different language) whatever childhood experiences made them
psychologically vulnerable in adult life, their obsessions, their
selfquestionings, their anxieties, were poured into their religious, moral, and
political speculation.
The
Heavenly City of the Eighteenth-Century Philosophers
Carl
Becker
Another
point of interpretive division among historians of the Enlightenment centers on
how modern and secular the philosophes were. Nineteenth- and earlytwentieth-century
historians argued that the philosophes were more modern than medieval and indeed
drew more from the classical pagan world than from the medieval world. This view
still predominates among historians of the period. A famous challenge to this
view was made some fifty years ago by Cornell historian Carl Becker. His book,
The Heavenly City of the Eighteenth-Century Philosophers (1932), became the most
influential book on the subject, although today it is no
longer
as popular as it once was. In the following selection from this work, Becker
presents the substance of his thesis.
Consider:
The ways in which the philosophes were more medieval than modern; the support
Becker offers for his argument that there was much Christian philosophy in the
philosophes' writings; how Gay or Manuel would react to Becker's interpretation.
We
are accustomed to think of the eighteenth century as essentially modern in its
temper. Certainly, the Philosophes themselves made a great point of having
renounced the superstition and hocus-pocus of medieval Christian thought, and we
have usually been willing to take them at their word. Surely, we say, the
eighteenth century was pre6minently the age of reason, surely the Philosophes
were a skeptical lot, atheists in effect if not by profession, addicted to
science and the scientific method, always out to crush the infamous, valiant
defenders of liberty, equality, fraternity, freedom of speech, and what you
will. All very true. And yet I think the Philosophes were nearer the Middle
Ages, less emancipated from the preconceptions of medieval Christian thought,
than they quite realized or we have commonly supposed. . . .
But,
if we examine the foundations of their faith, we find that at every turn the
Philosophes betray their debt to medieval thought without being aware of it.
They denounced Christian philosophy, but rather too much, after the manner of
those who are but half emancipated from the "superstitions" they
scorn. They had put off the fear of God, but maintained a respectful attitude
toward the Deity. They ridiculed the idea that the universe had been created in
six days, but still believed it to be a beautifully articulated machine designed
by the Supreme Being according to a rational plan as an abiding place for
mankind. The Garden of Eden was for them a myth, no doubt, but they looked
enviously back to the golden age of Roman virtue, or across the waters to the
unspoiled innocence of an Arcadian civilization that flourished in Pennsylvania.
They renounced the authority of church and Bible, but exhibited a nalve faith in
the authority of nature and reason. They scorned metaphysics, but were proud to
be called philosophers. They dismantled heaven, somewhat prematurely it seems,
since they retained their faith in the immortality of the soul. They
courageously discussed atheism, but not before the servants. They defended
toleration valiantly, but could with difficulty tolerate priests. They denied
that miracles ever happened, but believed in the perfectibility of the human
race. We feel that these Philosophers were at once too credulous and too
skeptical. They were the victims of common sense. In spite of their rationalism
and their humane sympathies, in spite of their aversion to hocus-pocus and
enthusiasm and dim perspectives, in spite of their eager skepticism, their
engaging cynicism, their brave youthful blasphemies and talk of hanging the last
king in the entrails of the last priest - in spite of all of it, there is more
of the Christian philosophy in the writings of the Philosophes than has yet been
dreamt of in our histories.
Eighteenth-
Century Europe: Enlightened Absolutism M. S. Anderson
Historians
have long debated exactly how much the Enlightenment influenced monarchs of the
time. Traditionally there has been considerable acceptance of the view that
monarchs such as Joseph II of Austria and Frederick II of Prussia were
enlightened. In recent years this view has been seriously narrowed and
questioned to the point where many historians feel that enlightened despotism
and enlightened absolutism are no longer terms that can usefully be applied to
these eighteenth-century monarchs. M. S. Anderson, of the London School of
Economics and Political Science, supports this newer critical view. In the
following selection he analyzes the limited ways in which eighteenth-century
monarchs can be considered enlightened.
Consider:
The characteristics of enlightened despotism; why Joseph II (see the primary
documents in this chapter) and Frederick II (see primary documents in the
preceding chapter) might be considered enlightened despots; how enlightened
despotism differs from seventeenth-century absolutism and the "new
monarchs" of the sixteenth century.
It
is generally agreed that in the later eighteenth century, notably in the
generation from about 1760 to 1790, many of the monarchies of Europe began to
display new characteristics. In one state after another rulers or ministers
(Catherine 11 in Russia, Frederick 11 in Prussia, Gustavus III in Sweden,
Charles III in Spain, Struensee in Denmark, Tanucci in Naples) began to be
influenced, or to claim that they were influenced, by the ideas which economists
and political philosophers, notably in France, had been proclaiming for several
decades. This 'enlightened despotism' is in many ways an unsatisfactory subject
of study. Except in a few cases-notably those of the Archduke Leopold in Tuscany
(1765-90) and his better-known brother Joseph in the Habsburg dominions-it was
always largely superficial and contrived. Usually the policies actively pursued
by the enlightened despots, however warm the welcome they gave to new theories
of government and administration, ran to some extent in traditional channels.
All
of them attempted to improve the administration of their states, especially with
regard to taxation, and to unify their territories more effectively. Many of
them attempted or at least envisaged judicial reforms, notably by the drawing up
of elaborate legal codes. The code of civil procedure and the penal code issued
by Joseph II in 1781 and 1787, and above all the great Prussian code of 1791,
the outcome of many years of labour during the reign of Frederick II, are
outstanding examples. With few exceptions the enlightened despots hoped to
achieve their ends by increasing their own authority and the power of the
central government in their states. But with the partial exception of the desire
for legal reform none of these ambitions was new. In differing ways they had
been seen in the activities of the 'New Monarchs' of the sixteenth century and
in those of Louis XIV and his contemporaries; they were to be seen once more,
with greater intensity and effect, in those of Napoleon 1. Some elements of
novelty can, it is true, be detected in the attitude of several rulers and
governments of the later eighteenth century. In particular the growing
humanitarianism. which I enlightened' thought and writing had done much to
foster, was now inspiring efforts to abolish judicial torture and greater
consideration than in the past for the interests of such groups as orphans and
old soldiers. But there were few rulers whose policies in practice represented
more than the development of ambitions cherished by their predecessors. Thus
Frederick II made little real alteration in the administrative system bequeathed
him by his father; and most of his territorial ambitions, notably in Poland,
were also inherited. Most of the changes which Catherine 11 attempted or
contemplated in Russia -the secularization of church lands in 1764, the reform
of local government in 1775, the codification of the law, attempted particularly
by the unsuccessful Legislative Commission of 1767 -had been suggested during
the reigns of her predecessors. What distinguished Frederick and Catherine from
Frederick William I and Peter the Great was not so much their policies as their
explicit justification of them (especially in the case of Catherine) in terms of
advanced contemporary thought. It was this appeal to intellectual and moral
standards rather than to those of mere expediency that made these rulers appear
to be doing something new. And this appeal was essentially spurious. No ruler of
any major state could allow his policies to be dictated by theory, however
attractive. The history, geographical position, and resources of the state he
ruled, the power or weakness of its neighbours, and a host of other factors, set
limits to what he might reasonably attempt in either internal or external
affairs. Joseph 11 spent his reign in a continuous series of efforts to improve
the administration of his territories and the condition of his subjects. More
than any other major ruler of the period he was truly inspired by the theories
of government then current in enlightened Europe. Yet his disregard of realities
in his relations with the Hungarians, with the inhabitants of his Netherlands
provinces, and with the Catholic church, and the failure and near-collapse to
which this disregard had led by the end of his reign, were the supreme proof
that, as always, there was an 'order of possible progress I in politics and all
other aspects of life in the eighteenth century, and that this order could be
disregarded only to a very limited extent.
Chapter
Questions on the Enlilghtenment
Chapter
Questions on the Enlightenment
1.
What core of ideas and attitudes most clearly connects Enlightenment
thinkers as revealed in these sources? How do these ideas relate to
eighteenth-century society and institutions?
2.
What policies would an eighteenth-century ruler have to pursue to fit to
the greatest degree the ideas and assumptions of Enlightenment thinkers? What
hindrances were faced by monarchs who wanted to be more enlightened?
3.
What ideas and attitudes of Enlightenment thinkers do you think remain
valid for the problems facing today's world? What Enlightenment ideas and
attitudes no longer seem valid or appropriate?