Introduction
Scientific
Revolution
One
of the most important intellectual revolutions of Western civilization occurred
in the seventeenth century. Building on some sixteenth-century breakthroughs and
a more deeply rooted interest in the workings of the natural world, a small
elite of thinkers and scientistsDescartes, Galileo, Newton, Kepler, Bacon, and
Boyle-established the foundations for the modern sciences of astronomy,
mathematics, physics, and chemistry. Although at first their work was known to
only a few, their ideas spread widely during the eighteenth century.
In
the process of developing the modern sciences, these thinkers challenged the
established conception of the universe as well as previous assumptions about
knowledge. This ultimately successful challenge, now known as the scientific
revolution, had a number of key elements. First, the view of the universe as
being stable, fixed, and finite, with the earth at its center, gave way to a
view of the universe as moving and almost infinite, with the earth merely one of
millions of bodies, all subject to the laws of nature. Second, earlier methods
for ascertaining the truth, which primarily involved referring to traditional
authorities such as Aristotle, Ptolemy, and the Church, were replaced by methods
that emphasized skepticism, rationalism, and rigorous reasoning based on
observed facts and mathematical laws. Third, although these thinkers remained
concerned with their own deeply held religious beliefs, the general scientific
orientation shifted from theological questions to secular questions that focused
on how things worked.
The
primary documents in this chapter emphasize two broad questions that faced these
seventeenth-century scientists. First, how can one ascertain the truth? The
answers of Descartes, Galileo, and Newton are examined. Second, what is the
proper line between science and scriptural authority? Galileo, who came most
directly into conflict with Church authorities, and Newton, who like most other
scientific thinkers of the period remained religious, provide us with clues.
The
secondary documents concentrate on the nature and causes of the scientific
revolution. In what ways was seventeenth-century science different from the
science of earlier centuries? What explains these differences? What were the
specific psychological, social, and cultural motives of seventeenth-century
scientists?
Most
of these intellectual developments were known to only a few throughout Europe.
In the eighteenth century these scientific ideas and methods became popularized
as part of the intellectual ferment of the Enlightenment.
Why
Was Science Backward in the Middle Ages?
Michael
Postan
The
scientific advances of the seventeenth century are commonly considered
revolutionary because of their contrast with the previous state of science. One
way to gain insight into the origins of the seventeenth-century developments is
to look at earlier periods to see whether something was missing then that
explains this contrast. In the following selection Michael Postan takes this
approach, focusing specificallu on the lack of scientific incentives in the
Middle Ages.
Consider:
Why scientific incentives were lacking in the Middle Ages; the typically
medieval traits that discouraged the men of the Middle Ages from scientific
exploration; how the concerns and problems faced by Galileo relate to this
argument.
It
is generally agreed that the Middle Ages preserved for the use of later times
the science of the ancients. Therein lies both the scientific achievement and
the scientific failure of the medieval civilization. . . . What the
Middle
Ages took over they did not very much enrich. Indeed so small was their own
contribution that historians of science are apt to regard the Middle Ages as
something of a pause. . . .
Thus
some advance on planes both purely intellectual and technical there was; yet
taken together and placed against the vast panorama of medieval life, or indeed
against the achievements of Greek and Hellenistic science in the fourth century
B.C., or with the scientific activity of the seventeenth century, all these
achievements are bound to appear very poor. Why then this poverty?
To
this question many answers can be and have been given. But what most of them
boil down to is the absence in medieval life of what I should be inclined to
call scientific incentives. Students of science sometimes differ about the true
inspiration of scientific progress. Some seek and find it in man's intellectual
curiosity, in his desire to understand the workings of nature. Others believe
that scientific knowledge grew and still grows out of man's attempts to improve
his tools and his methods of production; that, in short, scientific truth is a
by-product of technical progress. I do not want here to take sides in this
particular controversy; what I want to suggest is that the Middle Ages were
doubly unfortunate in that both the inspirations, the intellectual as well as
the practical, failed more or less.
The
easiest to account for is the intellectual. The Middle Ages were the age of
faith, and to that extent they were unfavourable to scientific speculation. It
is not that scientists as such were proscribed. For on the whole the persecution
of men for their scientific ideas was very rare: rare because men with dangerous
ideas, or indeed with any scientific ideas at all, were themselves very rare;
and it is indeed surprising that there were any at all. This does not mean that
there were no intellectual giants. All it means is that in an age which was one
of faith, men of intellect and spirit found the calls of faith itself - its
elucidation, its controversies, and its conquests - a task sufficient to absorb
them. To put it simply, they had no time for occupations like science.
In
fact they had neither the time nor the inclination. For even if there had been
enough men to engage in activities as mundane as science, there would still be
very little reason for them to do so. In times when medieval religious dogma
stood whole and unshaken the intellectual objects and the methods of science
were, to say the least, superfluous. The purpose of scientific enquiry is to
build up piecemeal a unified theory of the universe, of its origin and of its
working. But in the Middle Ages was that process really necessary? Did not
medieval man already possess in God, in the story of Creation and in the
doctrine of Omnipotent Will, a complete explanation of how the world came about
and of how, by what means and to what purpose, it was being conducted? Why build
up in laborious and painstaking mosaic a design, which was already there from
the outset, clear and visible to all?
So
much for intellectual incentive. The practical incentive was almost equally
feeble. Greater understanding of nature could not come from technical
improvements, chiefly because technical improvements were so few.
Medieval
occupations continued for centuries without appreciable change of method. After
the great period of initial development, i.e., after the late eleventh century,
the routine of medieval farming in the greater part of Europe became as fixed as
the landscape itself. In the history of the smithies, the weaving shops, or the
potteries, there were occasional periods of innovation, but taking the Middle
Ages as a whole technical improvement was very rare and very slow. For this
medieval economic policy was largely to blame. In the course of centuries
economic activities got surrounded with a vast structure of bye-laws and
regulations. . . . For bye-laws were as a rule based on the technical methods in
existence when they were framed; and once framed they were to stand in the way
of all subsequent change.
What
is more, so deeply ingrained was the spirit of protection that in every local
trade the technical methods were treated as a secret. . . . The men of the
Middle Ages were unable to do more than they did because they were lacking in
scientific incentive. What they achieved in advancing the practical arts of
humanity or in preserving and transmitting ancient learning, they did in so far
and as long as they were not typically medieval.
Early
Modern Europe:
Motives
for the Scientific
Revolution
Sir
George Clark
By
the seventeenth century, certain broad historical developments had set the stage
for individuals to make the discoveries we associate with the scientific
revolution. In addition, these individuals were motivated in ways that medieval
people were not and used the new and growing body of techniques, materials, and
knowledge to make their discoveries. In the following selection, British
historian Sir George Clark, a recognized authority on the seventeenth century,
examines some of the motives that led people to engage in scientific work.
Consider:
The distinctions Clark makes among different people engaged in scientific work;
why, more than thirteenth- or fourteenth-century people, these
seventeenth-century people had a "disinterested desire to know. "
There
were an infinite number of motives which led men to engage in scientific work
and to clear the scientific point of view from encumbrances; but we may group
together some of the most important under general headings, always remembering
that in actual life each of them was compounded with the others. There were
economic motives. The Portuguese explorers wanted their new instrument for
navigation; the German mine-owners asked questions about metallurgy and about
machines for lifting and carrying heavy loads; Italian engineers improved their
canals and locks and harbours by applying the principles of hydrostatics;
English trading companies employed experts who used new methods of drawing
charts. Not far removed from the economic motives were those of the physicians
and surgeons, who revolutionized anatomy and physiology, and did much more good
than harm with their new medicines and new operations, though some of them now
seem absurd. Like the doctors, the soldiers called science to their aid in
designing and aiming artillery or in planning fortifications. But there were
other motives far removed from the economic sphere. jewellers learnt much about
precious and semi-precious stones, but so did magicians. Musicians learnt the
mathematics of harmony; painters and architects studied light and colour,
substances and proportions, not only as craftsmen but as artists. For a number
of reasons religion impelled men to scientific study. The most definite and
old-established was the desire to reach absolute correctness in calculating the
dates for the annual fixed and movable festivals of the Church: it was a pope
who presided over the astronomical researches by which the calendar was reformed
in the sixteenth century. Deeper and stronger was the desire to study the
wonders of science, and the order which it unravelled in the universe, as
manifestations of the Creator's will. This was closer than any of the other
motives to the central impulse which actuated them all, the disinterested desire
to know.
The
Scientific Intellectual: A Psychological Interpretation of the Scientific
Revolution
Lewis
Feuer
The
traditional approach to the scientific revolution has been to view it from a
technological perspective, tracing the discovery and use of scientific
techniques before and during the seventeenth century. Postan and Clark in the
preceding selections deal with the motives that did or did not impel people to
engage in scientific work. In both cases a "common sense" view of
humans was assumed. In recent years scholars have become more sophisticated in
applying the social sciences to the scientific revolution. In the following
selection Lewis Feuer uses insights from modern psychology and social psychology
to explain what turned seventeenthcentury men to science.
Consider:
The spirit common to the scientific revolution and how this spirit was
manifested in what the scientists were doing; why Postan or Clark might be
unwilling to accept Feuer's interpretation.
That
the scientific revolution was the outcome of a liberation of curiosity all would
agree. The question, however, remains unsettled: What was the emotional
revolution in seventeenth-century thinkers which turned them into men of
science? What was the psychological revolution upon which the scientific
revolution was founded? Modern science, writes Lynn White, Jr., as it first
appeared in the later Middle Ages, "was one result of a deep-seated
mutation in the general attitude toward nature." The new science, he
continues, was an aspect "of an unprecedented yearning for immediate
experience of concrete facts which appears to have been characteristic of the
waxing third estate." What, then, was the character of this deep-seated
emotional mutation? What changes in attitude and feeling toward human thought,
sensation, and knowledge made possible the emergence of scientific
intellectuals? . . .
The
scientific intellectual was born from the hedonist-libertarian spirit which,
spreading through Europe in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, directly
nurtured the liberation of human curiosity. Not asceticism, but satisfaction;
not guilt, but joy in the human status; not self- abnegation, but self-
affirmation; not original sin, but original merit and worth; not gloom, but
merriment; not contempt for one's body and one's senses, but the hymn of
pleasure -this was the emotional basis of the scientific movement of the
seventeenth century. Herbert Butterfield has spoken of "a certain dynamic
quality" which entered into Europe's "secularization of thought"
in the seventeenth century.. ..
The
hedonist-libertarian ethic provided the momentum for the scientific revolution,
and was in fact the creed of the emerging movements of scientific intellectuals
everywhere. . . .
The
scientists of the seventeenth century swept away the miserable universe of
death, famine, and the torture of human beings in the name of God. They took a
world that had been peopled with demons and devils, and that superstition had
thronged with unseen terror at every side. They cleansed it with clear words and
plain experiment. They found an ethic that advised people to renounce their
desires, and to cultivate in a hostile universe the humility which befitted
their impotence, and they taught men instead to take pride in their human
status, and to dare to change the world into one which would answer more fully
to their desires. . . .
The
scientific movement in the seventeenth century was not the byproduct of an
increase of repression or asceticism. It was the outcome of a liberation of
energies; it derived from a lightening of the burden of guilt. With the growing
awareness that happiness and joy are his aims, man could take frank pleasure in
the world around him. Libidinal interest in external objects could develop
unthwarted; the world was found interesting to live in - an unending stage for
fresh experience. Energies were no longer consumed in inner conflicts. With an
awakened respect for his own biological nature, self-hatred was cast off.
Empiricism was the expression of a confidence in one's senses; the eyes and ears
were no longer evidences of human corruption but trusted avenues to a knowledge
of nature. The body was not the tainted seat of ignorance, but the source of
pleasures and the means for knowledge. Human energies, hitherto turned against
themselves, could reach out beyond concern for exclusive self.
The
Scientific Role: A Sociocultural Interpretation of the Scientific Revolution
Joseph
Ben-David
During
the seventeenth century, new institutions such as the Royal Society were formed
that helped create a sense of community and permanence among scientists. The
achievements of scientists were increasingly recognized, and scientists gained
both respect and acceptance into high social circles. These sociological aspects
of the scientific revolution are stressed in the following selection by Israeli
sociologist Joseph Ben-David. Ben-David argues that step by step scientists
gained legitimacy and permanence to the point where science became a
"self-perpetuating domain of culture. "
Consider:
How science was facilitated by nonscientific segments of society; how Ben-David
might have used the ideas of Feuer to support his argument; how Ben-David's
argument could be used to explain the previous lack of scientific achievement.
Traditionally,
natural science was subordinated to theology and philosophy. A first step
towards the modern efflorescence occurred when it began to become more
differentiated from theology and philosophy with respect to its subject-matter
and procedures. Even when this point was reached, science continued to be a
peripheral and secondary interest, but once its continuity was assured by its
patent singularity and the steadiness of the concern which it attracted, it
ceased to be subject to intermittent deterioration and there was even a
probability of some slow but regular accumulation of scientific knowledge. The
next step occurred when this peripheral subject, which had had a low status,
relative to other intellectual fields, came to be regarded by groups, with
class, religious and political interests opposed to the established order, as
intellectually more meaningful to them than the existing theological,
philosophical and literary culture. For these groups, the sciences became a
central part of their culture. Under these circumstances, men interested in
science were impelled to redefine their roles as philosophers in such a way that
science became increasingly central instead of peripheral to their conception of
what they were doing. With the enhancement of the wealth, power and status of
the classes which adopted an outlook sympathetic to science and in opposition to
the inherited outlook, the status of the new type of philosopher was elevated.
With the advancement of the status of scientific activity, the numbers of
intellectuals of the highest quality moving into the field increased. The final
steps occurred in the seventeeth century when the political success of the
classes adopting the scientistic outlook, combined with the intellectual success
of the new philosophers, led to a more elaborate organisation of science and the
establishment of scientific journals. In the course of these developments, men
who did scientific work came to regard themselves and to be regarded by others
as different from philosophers. They came to regard themselves as carrying on a
significantly distinctive category of activity, disjunctively separated from the
intellectual activity of philosophers and theologians. Increasing in numbers and
having more occasion to meet and discuss with each other, they developed their
own culture, their own norms and traditions in which their scientific work was
embedded. The motivation and curiosity sustained by the stabilised stimulus
inherent in such intensified and persistent scientific activity made for a
greater continuity in scientific development. With a larger number of persons
convinced of the value of science and devoting themselves actively and fully to
its cultivation, science became, in a sense, a self-perpetuating domain of
culture, and more independent than before of the variations in its environment.
A
further contributory factor was the relative openness and decentralisation of
the social system of European intellectual life. The Continent, including
England, constituted a cultural whole, as a result of the unity of the church
and its adoption of Roman traditions; persons and writings travelled across
political borders with relative ease. Ideas evolved in one place would be
readily appreciated in another. At the same time the various political units
were sufficiently different from each other to permit beginnings, which were
constricted in their places of origin (because they clashed with important
vested interests), to be developed elsewhere, where the same vested interests
were for some reason weaker.
Science
Questions
1.
What were the main ways in which the science of the seventeenth century
constituted a break from the past? What were some of the main problems facing
seventeenth-century scientists in making this break? How did they handle these
problems?
2.
How would you explain the occurrence of the scientific revolution in the
seventeenth century rather than in the sixteenth or eighteenth century?