Grappling With The Moral Octopus
El Chipo de Silicio (11 May 99)
I. The Nature of the Beast
The "Moral Octopus" is generically a certain theory of
the nature of ethics and specifically an annex or
appendix to a book called _The Abolition of Man_ by C.
S. Lewis, the Eng. Lit. figure and Anglican apologist.
My joke name for it is not Lewis's, needless to say.
Unfortunately a lot hinges on exactly what serious name
we give it. Lewis himself called it "Tao," with the
disclaimer that he didn't mean anything specifically
Chinese. Since his thesis was that the Moral Octopus is
universal, the disclaimer is obviously mandatory. He
also associated it with "Rta" in Sanskrit (which I
believe is mainly about ritual) and with "Torah" in the
Hebrew Bible. Closer to home, he consociated it with
"Natural Law," which is _obscurum per obscurius_ as far
as I am concerned. But all these expressions seem to be
mentioned mostly as abbreviations. The Octopus is in
fact "traditional morality" as conceived by people who
suppose that all traditions converge on (diverge from?)
one common morality. Since I don't see much merit in
that position, I'll just call it the Octopus.
The appendix to the book is there simply to indicate
roughly what this supposed convergence consists of,
that is, the elementary platitudes about right and wrong
that "everybody knows." The fact that there are eight
major rubrics and not seven or eleven is unimportant.
The Moral Octopus is therefore not comparable to the
Buddhist Eightfold Way for which there are elaborate
explanations of why exactly these eight things go
together and how they interact. It was, for Lewis, just
a sort of laundry list, and not even a practical one to
be taken to the cleaners; rather it was one drawn up to
give Martians an idea of what sort of a thing human
"laundry" is--by examples, not by rules and definitions.
II. De Divisione Temporum
Lewis wrote a whole book about Martians, but _The
Abolition of Man_ is not it. I invoke them in the
standard literary way as rational creatures without
terrestrial prejudices or even terrestrial background
information. The original target audience was not
persons remote in space, however, but persons separated
from CSL by a temporal sort of divide. Like most
schemes produced by dabblers in metahistory, _The
Abolition of Man_ gives us Three Ages. With Lewis these
are, unsurprisingly, to be classified as Good, Bad and
Worst. The are (1) the Good Old Days, when everybody
was (allegedly) a traditional moralist. Not, of
course, that they all always obeyed the Octopus, but
they all knew they should obey it--and there was no
question but that they knew about it. Then came (2)
Modern Times, which features several errors about morals
that CSL is concerned to correct in his little book.
The error most directly connected with moral zoology is
the view that "traditional morality" is not just all
there is to morality, that it is not absurd to speak of
a New Morality. He argues that "new" moralities are
simply fragmentary versions of the Octopus. Other errors
include the view that morality is "subjective and
trivial," the view that it can be based on reason, and
the view that it can be based on "instinct." All four
of these heresies will be considered separately below.
Finally, Lewis predicts (3) the Nightmare Future.
This part gives him the title of the book. What is to
be "abolished" turns out to be on the one hand the
Octopus and on the other hand Free Will. Futuristic
"conditioners" will decide how people should behave and
make very sure that they do so. We will not in days to
come "obey" the Octopus, we will be manipulated by drugs
or education or propaganda so as always to do what the
conditioners consider "right." Though the point is not
immediately pertinent to the Octopus Problem, it should
be mentioned that Lewis considers that these
conditioners will have severe logical problems about
"right," a word that makes sense only in terms of the
Octopus that they are determined to slay. (For CSL
fans, by the way, it should be noted that _That Hideous
Strength_ is by the author's own account an imaginary
picture of how man might be attempted to be abolished.)
III Cui Bono?
What is all this in aid of?
Not a hard question, of course. Lewis is interested in
these things only insofar as they conduce towards
Christojudaeanity. To read _The Abolition of Man_ as if
it were simply a treatise on anthropology is not very
clever, even though the appendix about the Octopus does
read somewhat like the weaker sort of anthropology,
with verbally parallel stuff from all over the map and
every known century set down side by side. To preach
his specific variant of Eastern Mediterranean
Monotheism, Lewis requires that everybody feel guilty
about having broken the moral law, having disobeyed the
Octopus. THAT is the problem his sort of
Christojudaeanity purports to be a solution to.
Only his specific sort: there are a number of different
things different tribes and ages of CJ's have wanted to
be "saved" from, Hell, Death, the Devil, temporal
enemies--as well as the Sin which is pertinent to the
Octopus Problem. And Sin comes in many flavors itself,
original and unoriginal, collective and individual,
moral and amoral. Lewis is a Protestant and Arminian
and Victorian sort of CJ, roughly speaking. I
emphasize the peculiarity and specificity of Lewis's
mythology partly because he himself loved to smudge
such things up as "mere Christianity," and partly
because of the pleasing though superficial paradox that
what his own religionist specificity happens to require
is ethical universalism.
His views are not, to be sure, completely peculiar. In
Islam the Mu`tazilites held quite similar views,
although those views were mostly destined to die out and
not flourish like Lewis's, which now infest a number of
denominations of Christojudaeans whose more ancient
adherents would have wanted nothing to do with such
stuff. Also, the Mu`tazilites were more theological
than Lewis (and most modern CJ's). They really did
care about God, just as they said. Taking that attitude
seriously seems to have become almost impossible to
understand nowadays, even amongst "religious" people.
The result is that originally theological ideas are
wildly misunderstood when read as anthropology. Notable
among such misreadings are two very closely connected
with the Octopus Problem, namely "original sin" and
"free will."
The Octopus Problem, for Lewis, was exactly to convince
people that EVERYBODY is guilty of original sin and
that EVERYBODY possesses free will. This is not quite
the same as the problem faced by every
(Pelagian/Arminian) CJ apologist in every age and land.
She need only convince her actual listeners that these
generalities apply to them personally. Maintaining them
in the abstract, and therefore as anthropological
propositions rather than pastoral theology, would be
only a very optional matter for her. But that matter
is what Lewis's book is centrally about.
IV. The Anthropological Octopus
Lewis does not come before us in _The Abolition of Man_
with an announcement that he will first establish the
credentials of the Octopus and then sell us
Christojudaeanity. Although it is obvious to everybody
where he is headed and there is no question of deceit,
nevertheless he claims that the Octopus exists quite
independently of "religion," and most of his snippets
are not from CJ sources. Since what he vends is not
religion or theology, what is it? I've already given
away my view that it is attempted anthropology, but we
must consider one other possibility. Might it not be
philosophy?
I think the answer is a very obvious NO, but I allow
that my views on what philosophy is like are eminently
contestable. Whatever Lewis is "really" doing, it
certainly looks like he is doing something "empirical"
or even "scientific" when he presents the Octopus.
"Here, ladies and gentlemen, are the FACTS about
traditional morality." says Lewis in effect.
"Modernizers may tell you that there a zillion
different moralities in the world, as many as there are
tribes or even as many as there are individuals, but if
you set aside the gaudy but superficial differences
about sexual behavior and religious ritual, you'll see
that everybody pretty much agrees about right and wrong,
at least up until just the other century when certain
European ex-Christians started making up _Ersatz_
moralities." (Spoofing is hard for me to resist, but I
think that's a tolerably accurate statement of the enemy
position.)
Now before we worry about whether that position is
sound or silly, I think we may agree about its
"empirical" nature, loosely speaking. Lewis is not
trying to REASON us into agreeing with him, he is
simply pointing and saying "Look at that!" Such
behavior is not, by my lights, philosophical. More
importantly, there is a long tradition of talking about
ethics philosophically, and although it contains all
sorts of discrepant things, it does not abound in
anything very much like this. Neither Plato nor
Aristotle nor the Stoics nor the earlier or middle
Christojudaeans nor Averroes nor the social-contract
liberals nor the human-rights liberals nor the
Utilitarian liberals nor the democratic liberals adopted
this "Just look!" approach to ethics. Indeed, I think
it could hardly have been adopted by anybody before
about 1850 when enough comparative and historical
material had been compiled and historical and
comparative thinking had come in. And that sort of
thinking, applied to this sort of subject matter, seems
to me well described as "anthropological."
The closest thing to it I know if in a really old book
is Herodotus, whose famous story about the Greeks
shocked at the Indians who ate their dead and the
Indians shocked at the idea of burying them uses
Lewis's sort of material to point in exactly the "wrong"
direction, towards an extreme "cultural relativism"
where Custom is completely arbitrary and can take almost
any form. After that there is the famous epigram in
Montaigne and then not much until "modern" (sc.
Enlightenment) times.
This reflection brings us to another point which,
though very plain, ought to be spelled out. Lewis is
not the first "modern" writer to use this sort of
material, and the ones who were first to use it were
writing in the other direction. In addition to being
"anthropological," Octopus Ethics is "reactionary" in
the strictest sense: it is set forth in response to
somebody else's innovation. Naturally everybody who
ever scribbled about ethics at all was well aware that
foreigners had lots of strange habits, but that
knowledge does not appear to have had anything much to
do with what they scribbled. When it did start to
matter, it mattered in what Lewis would consider the
wrong direction, it initiated a tendency he wrote to
correct. His writing may at times resemble older
material, but it must be read with a key distinction
always in mind: though he may seem to agree with older
writers, he is writing to refute a position they had
simply never heard of. Ignorance is one thing and
opposition quite another. Whenever modern authors
profess to be 'conservative" or "traditional," this
quite elementary reflection should come in at once and
problematize their fancied continuity with intellectual
predecessors.
(progress)
(regress)
(egress)
(e-mail)