|
Essay:
Hobbes
and the right to withdraw from the Commonwealth

Hobbes
and the right to withdraw from the Commonwealth
Hobbes had a generally poor view of man's
fate if left to his own devices. He described in Leviathan
a human beings natural state as one where s/he was
only subject to the 'rights of nature', that is to use
as much force as s/he saw necessary for self-protection
[ Hobbes
Ch XIV p 91] ,
and where natural inclinations are towards either war
or the acquisition of power. In such a situation, the
inevitable result is an unpleasant form of anarchy, where
the poor and weak suffer or die, the strong might succeed,
all men degenerate, and there is no means of prospering
as all energy is directed towards personal defence. In
such a state of being, there would be no industry, no
culture, no innovation. At best, a swift, short, violent
end to a life without anything to recommend it - as Hobbes
viewed it 'solitary, poore, nasty, brutish, and short.
[Hobbes ch XIII p 89]
With Hobbes' pessimistic view, the accompanying
'laws of nature', that man should 'seek peace, and follow
it', seems to have little hope of succeeding. Individuals
might form contracts with each other towards this end,
but there is nothing to hold men to their contracts, other
than fear of the consequences. So in this natural state,
we might be willing to covenant with other individuals
in the hope that, by doing so, we may obtain a measure
of security in our own lives.
But unless we go one step (or several steps)
further than this, we may be buying only a limited sense
of security for ourselves. Hobbes felt that the only way
that individuals could live a life without continual fear
of war was to be willing to hand over our individual rights,
either to one person, or to a group or Assembly of people,
and in doing so investing that person or group with enough
power to enforce peace. For him the only solution was
for men to covenant to form a commonwealth wherein all
men gave up their rights to one sovereign power, all consenting
to be governed by this sovereign. To ensure this power
was sufficient, it would not be enough for only a small
group of men or selection of families to simply band together
without covenanting, as this would be a temptation for
other groups of equal size to do the same, and would only
lead to threats of invasion and more violence[
ch XVII p 118].
Also, without power being vested in one person or assembly,
each individual member of the group would be following
his own reasoning, and not only would this prevent a united
action against a common enemy being taken, but would lead,
in times of comparative peace, to individual members turning
on one another. So, to be effective, a commonwealth would
consist of all men in a nation or society covenanting.
Once the commonwealth has been formed,
there is, according to Hobbes, an obligation on the part
of all who have covenanted to keep their contract. This
applies whether individuals have agreed to the covenant
by a means which we would see today as democratic, or
if the commonwealth has been imposed in some way. In this,
there is a difference between the more usual form of contract
between individuals, where there is the possibility of
withdrawing, particularly if the contract has been made
under duress. Usually, the amount of trust that individuals
can place in others keeping their word is limited. Hobbes
speaks of bonds as only enforceable by fear under normal
circumstances. If this is the case, then for the covenant
to form a commonwealth to be enforced, the power granted
to the sovereign would have to be absolute.
Unlimited power is a concept which we
have grown to associate with dictators and tyrants, yet
the state as set up in most nations has the type of sovereign
power Hobbes describes. Hobbes accepts that there may
be 'evil consequences' of such unlimited power, but the
absence of it would be far worse, a state of permanent
war It makes little difference in this situation whether
one individual has sovereignty or the institution of government,
there are very few areas on earth that an individual is
not at least nominally subject to sovereign power. Whether
the individual chooses or not, the framework of laws embraces
him/her from his birth, and by being born within a particular
country, in Hobbes view he has tacitly consented to the
covenant. The option to leave is there in theory, but
in practice an individual may be prevented by bureaucracy;
exit visas, and the difficulties of existing as a stateless
person may be insurmountable.
This idea of consent might be problematic;
there are types of consent in Hobbes' view which we would
today find it hard to agree with. An example would be
the invasion of the Falkland Islands by Argentina in 1982;
in Hobbes' eyes, the fact that the Governor of the Falklands
had at one stage surrendered to the Argentine commander
would have meant that all subject to his sovereignty,
ie the Falkland Islanders, had transferred their original
covenant with him/her to the new sovereign power, as is
the case with subjects of any sovereign power forced to
surrender to another. The wishes of the Islanders to remain
British would be immaterial. In this situation, an individual
who attempted to depose a conquering sovereign would be
just as much acting unlawfully as if s/he had acted against
his original sovereign.
Consent does not have to be active; an
individual has consented if s/he continues to live in
a nation where the system is such that the majority have
consented to a form of commonwealth. This seems to deny
even the right of protest, in Hobbes' words
For
if he voluntarily entered into the Congregation
of them that were assembled, he sufficiently declared
thereby his will (and therefore covenanted) to
stand to what the major part should ordayne; and
therefore if he refuse to stand thereto, or make
Protestation against any of their decrees, he
does contrary to his Covenant, and therefore unjustly.
[Ch. XVIII p 123]
It is difficult to see how this could
work in a democracy. If each government had sovereignty
for a fixed term, at the end of this term, would individuals
campaigning for any change be in breach of their Covenant?
The result would seem to be the original holders of office
being in power for life. Hobbes acknowledges some problems
with rights of succession, where they are not in the control
of the existing Sovereign, and the transfer of power from
one elected government to another has historically produced
problems even in ordered democracies (viz transfer from
the Heath to the Wilson government in Britain early 1974).
The momentary dissolution of the Covenant takes place
when governments are dissolved under less ordered circumstances,
and there would be some difficulty to ascertain where
an individual's obligation should lie.
If individuals are under obligation to the
sovereign power, with no automatic right to express their
dissent, are there limitations to their obligation? Has
an individual by consenting to the covenant whether explicitly
(eg by voting) or implicitly (by staying and living under
a states laws) given away all his rights? Can a sovereign
force his subjects, for example, to go to war? Interestingly,
Hobbes suggests that there are some limits, and that whilst
conscientious objection as we have understood it in recent
wars might not be legitimate, Hobbes accepts that neither
women, nor 'men of feminine courage' should be made to
fight.[
Ch XXI p 151] Conscientious objection,
rather than cowardice, is not an alternative, as an individual
hands over, as part of his consent to the covenant, the
right to decide what is good and what is evil. In that,
s/he is giving up the right to choose whether a particular
conflict is for the public good. An individual, whatever
his own conscience dictates, only has a right to refuse
to kill another human being at his sovereign's request
if his refusal does not 'frustrate the End for which the
Soveraignty was ordained' [Ch
XXI p 151] As the sovereignty was
certainly in part ordained to protest the state against
invasion by foreign powers, an individual's covenant includes
an implicit agreement to defend his country in any war
which his sovereign power has decided to involve him/her
in. And as kings and others in authority as individuals
are subject to passions directed towards 'partiality,
pride, revenge, and the like'[Ch
XVII p 117], historically an individual
can consider himself very fortunate if his generation
has not been legitimately conscripted to fight in defence
of his country.
This obligation might seem at odds with
the reasons for forming a commonwealth; if an individual
hopes to avoid war, to be able to enjoy peace and some
prosperity by giving up his rights, does the sovereign
have an obligation to him/her? There is no implicit obligation
for the sovereign to provide these conditions; there is
moreover, no sanction that can be applied, no punishment
for a sovereign by individuals. Although many states have
devised systems of checks and vetos to prevent sovereign
power turning into tyranny, this is not an aspect of Hobbes
idea of Commonwealth. War-crimes, for example, would not
be punishable, as any act 'in declared Hostility', no
matter how evil, is lawful. [Ch XXVIII
p 217] There is no means of legitimate
rebellion under Hobbes commonwealth should the sovereign
have failed to provide security, for once the covenant
has been made, all means ( no matter how seemingly democratic)
of changing the covenant, or making a new one, become
unlawful.
Hobbes view of political obligation seems
somewhat extreme when examined from the perspective of
a Western Liberal Democracy. In Britain, almost built
into our 'rights', by custom and usage, is the feeling
that whatever sovereignty we live under, we should be
critical of it; publicly on any and every occasion, in
the press, the media. Dependent on a variety of factors,
such as ethnic background or class position, an individual
may feel that the protest should take an active form,
such as the riots in various inner city centres since
the 1980s, or refusal to pay poll tax. It is difficult
to imagine absolute sovereign power being exercised. Yet
at the time Hobbes formulated his ideas, he had seen the
effects of the disintegration of commonwealth; civil war,
marauding armies, families set against each other. At
such a time of uncertainty, just as when periodic riots
erupt here and now, there is a great outcry for more law
and order.
Hobbes idea of sovereignty recognised
than human beings seem to have an instinctive need for
walls, in the shape of defined boundaries of acceptable
behaviour. Because we fear the result of the removal of
all restrictions, we accept the need for government, and
although critical of it, tend to live as if we accepted
being governed at times almost to excess in return for
peace and stability. We are critical of those we see as
examples of having broken the covenant in our own society
- and with liberty far more restricted than in Hobbes
day, this might include New Age travellers, peace protesters,
or trade unionists indulging in secondary picketing. It
seems impossible in 'civilised' society to be released
from the covenant, no matter how unwillingly we may have
entered into it.
Yet is Hobbes initial premise correct?
Without a commonwealth, are humans in their natural state
only concerned with pursuing self interest?
We are usually able to view the results
of extreme dissolution of commonwealth too often on our
television screens; Beirut one year's example, Bosnia
another's. On the other hand, we do not have to look back
further than a few years to find examples of the over-zealous
application of Hobbes principles in the shape of dictators,
and restrictive regimes, from Hitler to Pol Pot, Idi Amin
to Papa Doc. Singapore under Lee is the only immediate
example of a state "successfully" operating
with as limiting an idea of sovereignty and political
obligation as Hobbes advocates which comes to mind.
It might be that civilisation with its
emphasis on material wealth is what has brought about
the need for commonwealth. There are few societies left
to study which are still in an early enough stage of development
to determine whether a simple structure with no government,
and no legal system produces the hostile existence Hobbes
described. Some Aboriginal tribes have customs of valuing
sharing, rather than acquisition of power. It would appear
that until man develops an idea of property rights and
ownership, his violence is only a reaction to a perceived
threat, not a basic natural state. When all have little
or nothing of material value, there is no need for a commonwealth;
when most have little, but the few have much, there is
every need, and every danger for the few if the most should
decide to be released.
© 1993 Franni Vincent
|
|