(TMR
00.05.20)
<i>Understanding
Scholastic Thought with Foucault</i>. Philipp
Rosemann, ed. New York: St. Martin's Press, 1999. Pp.
xiv, 263.
$49.95.
0-312-21713-7
Reviewed by David
Metzger
Old Dominion
University
dmetzger@odu.edu
Over the course of six
studies, <i>Understanding Scholastic
Thought with
Foucault</i> provides a brief introduction to a
Nietzschean-Foucauldian-inspired
historical methodology (Study
1), an extended application
of that methodology to the study of
Scholastic philosophy and
its environs (Studies 2-5), as well as
an argument regarding the
relation of the medieval and the modern
(Study 6). The tenth volume in the innovative "New
Middle Ages"
Series edited by Bonnie
Wheeler, UST promises a theoretical
underpinning for a new
generation of medievalists wishing to
situate their work in the
growing field of cultural studies.
Unfortunately, scholars
already excited by the
carefully-considered
theoretical work of Karma Lachrie and Louise
Fradenburg may find
Rosemann's discussion of Foucault to be a bit
thin (for example, Rosemann
conflates the terms "postmodern" and
"poststructural" throughout
the book). And, in my opinion,
UST
does not provide a strong
complement to ongoing work on
nominalism (for example,
Richard Utz et. al) or even more general
work on "medievalism" (Can
one really speak about scholasticism
and modernity without
mentioning Jacques and Raissa Maritain?).
Study 1 promises a
description of Foucault's philosophy of
history and an exposition of
his postmodern historical
methodology. My chief concern here is that Rosemann
does not
really provide us with a
methodology. Study 1 does offer
some
statements about culture on
p. 25: a) "No culture creates itself
ex nihilo"; b) "Yet, as much
as by the positive values it
inherits from history, each
culture, civilization, tradition,
etc., is also characterized
by its Outside"; c) "The rejection of
the element not destined to
be the culture's other does not
create a relationship of
mere exteriority." But is a
methodology
merely the identification
and serialized illustration of
concepts? Is it enough to find medieval examples
for
statements/concepts Foucault
developed about culture in general?
Additionally, I am not
satisfied with the version of Foucault
that Rosemann provides in
Study 1. Rosemann does not
consider
alternative readings of
Foucault; his chief expository method is
an analogy between Foucault
and Nietzsche. And he writes
about
Foucault as if Foucault's
work were not itself a response to nor
a prompt for the work of
Foucault's contemporaries.
Study 2 ("Defining the
Scholastic Tradition") begins with a very
important question "Was
there a Scholastic Philosophy in the
Middle Ages?" Rosemann rewrites the question to read
"What (if
anything) characterizes and
distinguishes medieval intellectual
culture, beyond the mere
historical fact that it took place
during a period we call the
'Middle Ages'? And can the
term
'Scholastic' be used to
convey such distinguishing
characteristics?" (45). Again, these are interesting
questions,
but are they
Foucauldian? Do we need Foucault to
ask and answer
them? Rosemann's subsequent discussion of the
"doctrinal"
approach (exemplified by the
work of Mauruice De Wulf) and the
"formal" approach
(exemplified by Martin Grabmann) to answering
these questions would
suggest that these questions are not then
the beginning of a
Foucauldian discussion of the Middle Ages as
much as the beginning of a
Foucauldian discussion of modernity:
Why these questions
now? But this avenue is not
considered.
Rather, Foucault, it is
suggested, offers a superior approach.
We are told that the
doctrinal approach to the question "What
distinguished medieval
civilization" does not take into account
the richness and diversity
of medieval society (46), and the
formal approach to the
question yields a generalization
("Medieval thought centered
around one paramount issue -- the
reconciliation of authority
and reason") that is not peculiar to
medieval culture
(47).
What does Foucault
offer? Interestingly enough, the
transition
that Rosemann offers us for
his discussion of the advantages of a
Foucauldian approach does
not mention Foucault at all.
Rosemann
invites us "to try to
describe it [auctoritas/ratio: what
Grabmann identified as the
central issue of Scholasticism], and
thereby situate Scholastic
tradition in the intellectual history
of the West" (48). Unfortunately, Rosemann does no such
thing;
he drops the discussion of
auctoritas/ratio, starting up a
discussion of how Greek
philosophical language developed as the
marginalization of
<i>mythos</i> for the sake of <i>logos</i>.
Could the binary
mythos/logos be related to the binary
auctoritas/ratio? Sure. But no such historicization is
offered.
We find, rather, another
binary in an extended quotation from 1
Corinthians: Christian folly
(<i>moria</i>) vs. Greek wisdom
(<i>sophia</i>).
We might expect Study 3
("Scholastic Intellectual Practices") to
continue the discussion of
moria/sophia, but Rosemann turns his
attentions to Gothic script,
Gothic architecture, manuscript
transmission, and the
methods/genres of instruction in
13th-century
universities. His general
orientation, here, is
that an intellectual
practice is not simply a vehicle for
thought; an intellectual
practice enables people to think and act
as they do -- "exercising,"
in the case of Gothic script for
example, "a formative
influence upon the thought to which it
gives expression" (63).
Yet, how is it possible to support
such
an assertion given that what
we might observe of these practices
is limited to how these
intellectual practices "seem to reflect
and reinforce a certain
confidence in the powers of human reason"
(63)? The proposed solution to this problem is
the
identification of a
sea-change, a break in tradition that can be
supported only by the
invention of those new practices and
materials:
we can see a clear evolution in
which medieval thought
gradually detaches itself from its
immediate textual bases,
emancipating itself as it were and
assuming an increasingly
independent character, and finally
culminating in the
'elaboration of systematic
disciplines'.
(87)
But one more evidentiary
move is required in order to avoid a
circular argument: the
sea-change ("the elaboration of systematic
disciplines") cannot itself
be rendered wholly as these
intellectual practices. Study 4 ("The Prose of the World --
The
Greek Circle and the
Christian Line") and Study 5 ("Aquinas: the
Open Circle") serve this
argumentative function.
By avoiding circularity in
argument, Studies 4 & 5 run the risk
of losing sight of the
distinctive identity of the medieval
enterprise. I say "risk" here, only because, in
Study 2,
Rosemann identifies this
loss of a distinctive medieval identity
as a problem with "formal"
approaches to scholastic philosophy.
Rosemann cites Foucault on
the "sixteenth-century episteme"
("resemblance played a
constructive role in the knowledge of
Western culture"); then
Rosemann adds that "much of what is said
in 'The Prose of the World'
can indeed be taken as commentary,
extremely insightful
commentary even, on medieval culture" (105).
Rosemann proceeds to chart a
doctrine of resemblance from
Parmenides through Plato,
Aristotle, and Plotinus, concluding
this study with a discussion
of the shape of Christian time.
We
might very well ask what
holds all of these discussions together
-- certainly not a
serialization/narrativization of affect
through individuals, social
conditions, political intentions.
No, Rosemann finds his model
of transmission in the difference
between a circle and a line:
showing us how the "texts" and
"textualization" of the
Hellenic world could not have given birth
to the Christ (Greek time is
circular; Christian time is linear).
Study 4 ends with a
quotation from Bonaventure: "How the center
of a circle can be found by
means of a cross becomes clear
through a geometrical
example." And Study 5 finds that
Greek
circularity is synthesized
with Christian linearity in the
following sentence from
Aquinas' Libri Sententiarum:
In the issuing forth of the
creatures from their first
principle, a certain circling or
wheeling around is to be
considered, due to the fact that
all things turn back, as to
their end, to that from which they
have come forth as from
their
principle.
(In IV libros Sententiarum 1.14.2.2.c
Opera omnia, ed. Busa, 1, p. 36.)
Rosemann's discussions in
Studies 4 & 5 are interesting inasmuch
as they encourage us to find
the circle and the line in a good
deal of philosophical
material. But I am not certain how
a
Foucauldian methodology
allows Rosemann to talk about circles and
lines without also
discussing the role geometrical figures and
the "impossibility of the
void" played in medieval natural
philosophy.
Foucault's "method" assumes
a movement between two poles: (1)
that which comes to function
as the Other because it is presumed
to be in place of the Other
and (2) that which can come to the
place of the Other.
That-which-comes-to-the-place-of-the-Other
causes the Other as such to
disappear or go into hiding, but this
fading/disappearing of the
Other is also necessary insofar as it
allows us to recognize that
the Other-function is not the Other
itself. From a Foucauldian standpoint,
torture/discipline
becomes a way of translating
the presence and absence of the
Other into knowledge so that
even when the Other is absent we
know it's there. Likewise, the fact that the
Other-function is
not the Other allows for
anything other than the Other to take
the place of the
Other-function (culture as fetish).
Readers
might at least consider the
possibility of reading Foucault this
way and then reexamine
Rosemann's claims about the relationship
of the modern
("post-Scholastics"?) and the medieval in "Study 6"
as well as his discussion of
the Inquisition and "witch-hunts" as
the closing of the
Scholastic episteme/circle.
Foucault, I
suspect, would lead us in
other directions. But, to give
the
author his due, these other
directions may well be more carefully
considered because of
Rosemann's efforts.