"In this habitually unary space, occasionally (but alas all too rarely) a 'detail' attracts me. I feel that its mere presence changes my reading, that I am looking at a new photograph, marked in my eyes with a higher value. The detail is the punctum...
We have already considered how non-metrical image writing evolved, as a form of material production associated with the making of tools; and that this defines such a form of image writing as truly distinct from phonetically-based writing systems. We have seen how non-metrical differences between kinds of things are distinguished from metrical variances in degree or measure; and how the non-metrical is characteristically temporal in nature. We have looked at how durations can be thought of in ways quite distinct from measurements based upon a linear system of past, present, and future. We have also considered the nature of images in general, and have seen how graphemically-based writing systems should be understood in grammatological terms, rather than in terms proper to the phonetically-based systems covered by semiology. Finally, we have considered how the selectivity proper to patterns of non-metrical grouping presents to us systemizations indicative of how memory functions within its own associative grasp; and, how images of tools, animals, and facial expressions define distinct associative functions and contexts within image writing. But, all of this is just an introduction to non-metrical image writing. As far as these considerations can take us toward an understanding of non-metrical image writing, they are not sufficient for us to grasp the essential nature of this form of writing. To truly approach non-metrical image writing in its own right, as a distinct form of writing, we must first understand how concepts are presented within this form of writing. We must understand how this form of image writing unified the world that it presents with the thoughts of those who used this kind of writing. If we stop our analysis before we reach this point, we will achieve nothing more than a simple transference of this form of writing into the conceptual world that we have brought with us to our reading of non-metrical image writing. That is not good enough, because we can do so much more here. We have an opportunity to think the world that non-metrical image writing presents to us in the same way that those who produced this form of writing did. We must not allow ourselves to be satisfied with our habitual familiarity toward our own world views, or to trick ourselves into thinking that our view of the world is consistent with the world views of those who produced non-metrical image writing. It is all too easy to limit ourselves to a purely scientific approach that simply selects out relevant objects and assigns to them modern names: for, we don't really learn very much by doing this. And, we don't truly understand anything about non-metrical image writing, or the people who produced it, through this approach. Rather than simply taking a transcendental approach that lifts images from non-metrical image writing and then places them in a scientifically definitional context which is separate from the connectivities of their original occurrence, I will try to bring you toward an understanding of how non-metrical image writing unifies a reader with the world that this form of image writing presents. For, herein lies the true beauty of this form of writing: how it still presents the conceptual grasp which long-ago people had of their world; and, how non-metrical image writing still maintains the conceptual understanding which came from the lived experiences of the people who produced and used it.
"Thinking provokes general indifference. It is a dangerous exercise nevertheless. Indeed, it is only when the dangers become obvious that the indifference ceases, but they often remain hidden and barely perceptible, inherent in the exercise. Precisely because the plane of immanence is prephilosophical and does not immediately take effect with concepts, it implies a sort of groping experimentation and its layout resorts to measures that are not very respectable, rational, or reasonable. These measures belong to the order of dreams, of pathological processes, esoteric experiences, drunkenness, and excess. We head for the horizon, on the plane of immanence, and we return with bloodshot eyes, yet these are the eyes of the mind...But then "danger" takes on another meaning: it becomes a case of obvious consequences when pure immanence provokes a strong, instinctive disapproval in public opinion, and the nature of the created concepts strengthens this disapproval. This is because one does not think without becoming something else, something that does not think - an animal, a molecule, a particle - and that comes back to thought and revives it." There are many different ways to approach non-metrical image writing: as many different ways as there are ways in which one can think about the world. As something produced so very long ago, this form of writing naturally gravitates toward a reading which is predicated by "once upon a time". And although this is the most natural interpretive approach which suggests itself, this is also the first interpretive tendency that we will try to avoid in our attempts at reading non-metrical image writing. We do not wish here to experience the "once upon a time" of mythology but, instead, to immerse ourselves in the immediacy which this form of writing holds open to us, and holds open toward the world from which it originated. Instead of beginning with the "once upon a time" of myth, we must try to find the specific instances of "in each and every case" that characterizes every field of science; and in this case, we will be seeking the "in each and every case" that characterizes the science of linguistics. We already know that this will be found within an understanding of non-metrical image writing as it is defined through grammatology; but again, this is just a starting point. Nonetheless, such a starting point will enable us to at least begin our attempt at understanding non-metrical image writing, without our necessarily falling back into the other pre-established habits for reading that we have developed through our experiences with phonetic forms of writing. But it will not yet allow us to adequately experience non-metrical image writing as it is in its own right, or in ways distinctly proper to what this form of writing is in itself. For that, we must proceed to the point where we can grasp how the concepts presented within this form of writing shape an understanding of the world that non-metrical image writing presents. We must embrace here the very immanences which characterized that world, in the way that such immanences were experienced by the people who lived within that world: we must find the concepts that these people produced from their lived experience of that immanence, before we can understand the existential connectivities holding between them and their world. Then, and only then, will we have reached an essential understanding of non-metrical image writing. I will try to bring you toward the point where the essential nature of non-metrical image writing asserts itself within its own right, as that which is proper to this form of writing within the ways of thinking that produced it. This may prove difficult but, please be patient: it is not an easy task to clearly define a threshold of understanding where this form of writing begins to present its authentic nature; and, it is all too simple a thing to cause this threshold to collapse, by making the wrong interpretive choices, before the necessary consistencies proper to it are reached. (This section, which introduces the concepts used in my interpretive methodology, is a bit technical; however, the following page (which presents an actual grammatological analysis of an example of non-metrical image writing), is more pragmatic and practical: so, if you find yourself not getting very much out of this first section, try reading through the following page and then, referring back to this section in order to clarify any questions you might have).
"The plane of immanence is like a section of chaos and acts like a sieve. In fact, chaos is characterized less by the absence of determinations than by the infinite speed with which they take shape and vanish. This is not a movement from one determination to the other but, on the contrary, the impossibility of a connection between them, since one does not appear without the other having already disappeared, and one appears as disappearance when the other disappears as outline. Chaos is not an inert or stationary state, nor is it a chance mixture. Chaos makes chaotic and undoes every consistency in the infinite. The problem of philosophy is to acquire a consistency without losing the infinite into which thought plunges (in this respect chaos has as much a mental as a physical existence). To give consistency without losing anything of the infinite is very different from the problem of science, which seeks to provide chaos with reference points, on condition of renouncing infinite movements and speeds and of carrying out a limitation of speed first of all. Light, or the relative horizon, is primary in science. Philosophy, on the other hand, proceeds by presupposing or by instituting the plane of immanence: it is the plane's variable curves that retain the infinite movements that turn back on themselves in incessant exchange, but which also continually free other movements which are retained. The concepts can then mark out the intensive ordinates of these infinite movements, as movements which are themselves finite which form, at infinite speed, variable contours inscribed on the plane. By making a section of chaos, the plane of immanence requires a creation of concepts." The above quote is from one of my favorite books; a truly great book that one can read cover-to-cover or, by opening at any point or, by flipping both forward and backward through the pages...a book that will still be read and enjoyed a hundred years from now.
"What Is Philosophy?" is also a very dense book; it's not actually all that thick but, when you 'unpack' the ideas it contains, they increase in content voluminously.
"chaos": not a 'good thing' or a 'bad thing', but a 'real thing'; in fact, the very being of reality from which things form. Before thinking asserts itself and imposes the permanence of memory upon events; before the functional parameters of perception give shape and body to the variances they can discern; and before the thermodynamic slope of the molecular reactions which animate our bodies defines our sensitivity to time and to events, there is only the change, variance, and differential flux proper to the gravity wells of our solar system's section of space. Of and within this, enframed through our existential reality, consistencies persist where simple proximity exceeds the threshold of immanence and produces discernable temporal becomings. However, what we can discern does not determine what there is; that which is, reality inclusive of us, determines what we can discern. And how we discern things, through contrasts produced in and of sensory or instrumental deformations, provides us with the differential information from which we selectively determine the persistence of consistencies. As you can see, a lot happens before we ever reach a point where 'identities' can be referentially stabilized; and as we shift our interpretive analysis away from identity and toward more basic processes of differentiation, we also move closer to chaos. Here, philosophy is the process of maintaining consistency as close to chaos as possible...so close that the becomings of immanence can be approximated through our production of concepts. Since non-metrical image writing is produced from the randomly variable metrical substrates of grain patterns in stone, re-marking these random 'patterns' into the consistencies characteristic of a form of writing is an interpretive act that occurs upon the very edge of (more or less utter) chaos. This is where the interpretive activity of producing such writing occurs, until it is stabilized as composition. In reading such a form of writing, we will always be at the edge of interpretive chaos...a position which will be expressed through the concepts produced within this form of writing.
(August 7, 2003: A friend asked me recently if I felt that the universe had messages for people. I thought about that, and replied: "The universe is always saying everything, all at once and all the time." That's what I consider to be the state refered to here as "chaos" - the natural state of reality.) "characterized less by the absence of determinations" : if our characterization of chaos is only presented in part by the absence of determinations, then perhaps we can say that this characterization is always a partial indeterminacy. This is an important point for our interpretive analysis, because we can try to note the occurrence of such indeterminacy, and we can further try to characterize its partiality. This in itself will provide some information as to the proximity of our interpretive analysis in relation to chaos; and from this we can extract some of the elements of consistency which are inherent within the process of approximation. This will at least allow us to define somewhat the interactions that hold between the concepts we use in presenting the becomings of immanence; and this is indeed something, since:
"Philosophical concepts are fragmentary wholes that are not aligned with one another so that they fit together, because their edges do not match up. They are not pieces of a jigsaw puzzle but rather the outcome of throws of the dice. They resonate nonetheless..." We noted earlier (in an analysis of Henri Bergson's 'selectivist' theory of memory) the apparent occurance of resonance in the selectivity of memory:
"In general the idea is that the item chosen/selected (say a Hebbean-type assembly of neurons) is stabilized while all other items/possibilities are allowed to relax back into formlessness or low levels of activation or are actively inhibited...Several theorists (See Changeux and Dehaene, 1989; Shepard, 1984; and Ratcliff, 1978) endorse the notion of resonance as the principle underlying activation of stored representations - what we are calling here "selection". A memory is stabilized if it resonates (roughly: matches) with an item from either the environment or from another part of the cognitive system...For Bergson the selection process also entailed a kind of matching or resonance procedure but we will see that what counted as a match for Bergson depended on the "ability" of the memory to act as a guide for useful action." So, we can perhaps say that indeterminacy is partial to (forms as a part of) approximation in the selective resonance of concepts. This is also to say that the singularity of a concept is its partiality to that which it approximates in this resonant selectivity: so here, we can see that indeterminacy can be used to characterize some of the consistencies of immanence. In particular, we should note that indeterminacy, approximation, and partiality are characteristic of the interactive spaces between concepts, where concepts resonate with each other. That makes a lot of sense, since indeterminacies are often found at the thresholds of sensory contrasts; so, an indeterminacy in sensory contrast will produce resonating singularities. The partiality of any indeterminacy will characterize the resonance of any associated singularities. In grammatological terms, this will result in the functional, anasemantic (a-semiotic, a-signifying) production of meta-stabilities and meta-narratives...which are fundamental grammatic structures in non-metrical image writing. Of course, although we are interested in the generalized singularity of concepts, and what such singularity tells us about the structure of non-metrical image writing, we are particularly interested in the concepts themselves. So, in order to proceed toward a post-structural interpretation which concerns itself with concepts and their formation, we must shift from a characterization of chaos as partial indeterminacy toward... "infinite speed": infinite speed has nothing to do with how quickly a space can be crossed; it has instead everything to do with the fact that in thought, conceptual spaces are always already crossed, with no necessary physical connection across those spaces and no necessary temporal connectivity between that which such spaces separate. We have acquired some suggestion as to what this means through our brief consideration of partial indeterminacy's effect upon sensory contrasts: consider how quickly such a functional indeterminacy would trigger shifts in any associated meta-narrative. That is infinite speed, as it is encountered on the interpretive edge of chaos.
"Movement of the infinite does not refer to spatiotemporal coordinates that define the successive positions of a moving object and the fixed reference points in relation to which these positions vary. "To orient oneself in thought" implies neither objective reference point nor moving object that experiences itself as a subject and that, as such, strives for or needs the infinite. Movement takes in everything, and there is no place for a subject and an object that can only be concepts. It is the horizon itself that is in movement: the relative horizon recedes when the subject advances, but on the plane of immanence we are always and already on the absolute horizon. Infinite movement is defined by a coming and going, because it does not advance toward a destination without already turning back on itself, the needle also being the pole. If "turning toward" is the movement of thought toward truth, how could truth not also turn toward thought? And how could truth itself not turn away from thought when thought turns away from it? However, this is not a fusion but a reversibility, an immediate, perpetual, instantaneous exchange - a lightning flash. Infinite movement is double, and there is only a fold from one to the other. It is in this sense that thinking and being are said to be one and the same. Or rather, movement is not the image of thought without being also the substance of being." We can call this "absolute horizon", with its characteristic indeterminacy, an event horizon. Event horizons are "absolute" in that we are always upon one, in so far as we are existing as living, temporal beings. In that our lives are an expression of reality's temporal immanence, event horizons are aspects of an absolute horizon of immanence. So, we can move conceptually from chaos, to partial indeterminacy, and then to infinite speed; and this brings us to event horizons which, as it turns out, are characteristic of meta-narratives. That is a handy thing to know, because it tells us that anything which we can determine about event horizons will be of use to us in our interpretation of non-metrical image writing. We now can say that meta-narratives are composed of interpretive event horizons, which shift at infinite speed. These shifts can be further defined as being contingent upon the singularities which express the content of sensory contrasts; and which in turn vary due to partial indeterminacies. Again, the importance of infinite speed here is that shifts between event horizons are absolute: when they occur, there are no intermediary stages or steps. Instead, such transitions are total: they come into being all at once, and nothing of the previous event horizon remains in that which replaces it. Anything that does remain, any consistency, is not of the transitional event horizons left behind but, rather, is of the order of immanence itself and therefore essentially characteristic of temporality in and of itself. This observation will be particularly useful to us in that it will allow us to determine when we are dealing with separate event horizons, and when concepts are part of the same event horizon. It will also help us to define those grammatological structures which precede event horizons: meta-stabilities (in which partial transitions are presented). In short, this will aid us in any analysis we may make of meta-narratives, for it will help us to differentiate between narrative composites. Later, we will also see that the above distinction can also be expressed as the difference between truths of existence and truths of essence. "impossibility of connection between determinations" : this consideration is a different one than that which was called "an absence of determinations", which we considered earlier. Our analysis of the absence of determinations suggested a way in which we might at least establish a resonance between the singularity of concepts; but here, we find that this was indeed the lesser part of what chaos is. More important to us here is the inherent and essential impossibility for determinations within chaos to establish any connections. This is important because, as with the shifts between event horizons in meta-narratives, it is absolutely necessary for concepts to remain singular in their essential nature. Thus, although we can establish a resonance between the singularity of concepts, in order for concepts to remain distinct and to function differentially, part of the consistency which concepts derive from the immanent reality of chaos must be this impossibility of connection. This is why philosophy must retain something of the infinite speed of chaos in the consistency of its concepts: this is what makes concepts distinct from each other. Without such a consistency with the impossibility of connection between determinations (which chaos presents within immanence), all concepts would merge and blend together, rendering them completely useless for distinguishing any distinctions within our thoughts about the nature of reality. In our attempt to move from: a structural understanding of the grammatological principles of non-metrical image writing; to, a post-structural understanding of how concepts occur in non-metrical image writing, we must now consider what the shifts between event horizons within meta-narratives can tell us about the impossibility of connection between determinations within chaos. And it is simply this: whatever forms upon any event horizon as an element of any meta-narrative must be truly distinct and separable in each and every instance of its formation. This specifically means that durations, as elemental to events, can not be thought of in a metrical fashion. To define durations in terms of simple measurement, which can vary only by degree or amount, would make durations inherently connectable...as easily so as for any two numbers, which can be connected through the simplest mathematical operations. Here, we must have a way of defining durations which can not be connected so: we must present durations as differing in kind, as distinguishing between kinds of 'things' (events). Otherwise, we would never be able to distinguish concepts upon an event horizon, or to separate conceptual elements out of any event. The very act of composition would prove impossible; for, it is only through an 'impossibility of connection between determinations' that determinations such as durations can share the common position of an event, yet still remain distinguishable. "To give consistency without losing anything of the infinite is very different from the problem of science, which seeks to provide chaos with reference points...": We now have some idea of how to proceed in our attempt to access the conceptual essences of non-metrical image writing. We know that we should begin by defining the anasemantic functions which this form of writing presents within the linguistic science of grammatology; and that from this point, we should proceed on to an analysis of the conceptual formulations within non-metrical image writing. Having already gained some general ideas about what we will be looking for in such a conceptual analysis, we should consider for a moment the differences between such anasemantic, grammatological functions and, concepts...which are what we are particularly interested in finding.
"The object of science is not concepts but rather functions that are presented as propositions in discursive systems. The elements of functions are called functives. A scientific notion is defined not by concepts but by functions or propositions...it is the idea of the function which enables the sciences to reflect and communicate. Science does not need philosophy for these tasks. On the other hand, when an object - a geometrical space, for example - is scientifically constructed by functions, its philosophical concept, which is by no means given in the function, must still be discovered. Furthermore, a concept may take as its components the functives of any possible function without thereby having the least scientific value, but with the aim of marking the differences in kind between concepts and functions.Thus, as we define the grammatological functions of non-metrical image writing, we will be placing ourselves in a position from which we can also determine what concepts are being presented through this form of writing. Determining what concepts this form of writing presents in any of its instances will allow us to gain a sense of the existential reality from which those concepts were produced...which in turn will help to define for us the conceptual personae through which such concepts are grounded within the world.
Since we already have a viable idea of how to define the grammatological functions presented through non-metrical image writing, we should take a moment to consider how the concepts we will be looking for might be defined.
"First, every concept relates back to other concepts, not only in its history but in its becoming or its present connections. Every concept has components that may, in turn, be grasped as concepts (so that the Other Person has the face among its components, but the Face will be considered as a concept with its own components). Concepts, therefore, extend to infinity and, being created, are never created from nothing. Second, what is distinctive about the concept is that it renders components inseparable within itself. Components, or what defines the consistency of the concept, its endoconsistency, are distinct, heterogeneous, and yet not separable. The point is that each partially overlaps, has a neighborhood, or threshold of indiscernability, with one another...Components remain distinct, but something passes from one to the other, something that is undecidable between them. There is an area ab that belongs to both a and b, where a and b "become" indiscernable. These zones, thresholds, or becomings, this inseparability define the internal consistency of the concept. But the concept also has exoconsistency with other concepts, when their respective creation implies the construction of a bridge on the same plane. Zones and bridges are the joints of the concept. Of all the attributes and characteristics that we can list pertaining to concepts, the description of concepts as intensive ordinates may be the most important for us here. To be able to define concepts as intensive ordinates allows us to gain some insight into the nature of concepts as distinct and discrete durations; and this, in turn, allows us to better define exactly how we might identify concepts as they occur within events and upon event horizons. Given the importance of our definition of concepts as intensive ordinates, it would be of some benefit to our analysis to examine just what this implies. Franz Brentano once made a very important observation concerning human thought. He was trying to find a way to distinguish between physical objects, and thoughts about such objects: how are these two things different, and how can we tell they are different when our only experience of physical things is through thoughts and perceptions? He realized that, while physical objects are quite capable of existing on their own without people having to think about them, all thoughts have one thing in common: they are INTENDED by the person thinking them (in the sense that what we can call 'desire' is 'intentional'). From this starting point, Edmund Husserl developed a school of thought known as "Phenomenology". 'Phenomena' simply refers to the perceptions we have of things (as opposed to "noumena", the things as they are in and to themselves, without people thinking them). He said that all conscious phenomena are intentional, and developed a way of describing thought that demands one simply describe one's perceptions, without using metaphors or ideas that are not in the actual perceptions being described. His idea was to try to capture the actual 'intentional' essence of thought; and as it turns out, this approach is exactly what is needed in order to understand non-metrical image writing. In that 'objects' of consciousness are intensional, as compared to physical objects which are extensional, they can be said to be intended; and as intended, such 'objects' of consciousness are said to be produced by acts of consciousness: this makes them the products of those processes of consciousness which we call by the term 'desire'. Taken in this sense, desire is a very mechanical function; not quite as mechanical as sensory perception but, certainly, the neuro-mechanical nature of the senses functionally structures the productive nature of the conscious processes that we call desire. Thus, the production of non-metrical image writing was always an intentional act; and as such, it will display throughout its various instances the sort of intentional attributes which anyone can easily grasp. So, in interpreting non-metrical image writing, we will be dealing with intentionalities of consciousness, rather than with phonetically defined meaning. This will make the task of interpreting this form of writing much easier than it might otherwise be, since we will be able to base our interpretations upon how desire expresses memory, instead of how memories of phonetically based linguistic references shape expressions of meaning. Although Husserl's conceptualization of phenomenology stresses the study of strictly intentional acts of consciousness - as expressed in isolation from either objective or subjective circumstances - many philosophers of an empiricist outlook tend to emphasize Husserl's concept of material ontology (the 'being of the physically real') and his cardinal principle that evidence, the experience of a something that is itself presented, is the only ultimate source of knowledge. Psychology tends to emphasize the application of phenomenology as it relates to 'subjective' conscious processes; post-structural philosophy, as developed by Deleuze and Guattari into a material psychology, tends to emphasize the 'objective' application of Husserl's principles. (Here, however, we will not be thinking in terms of 'subject' and 'object', but in terms of earth and territory). So, when we say that all concepts are intensive ordinates, this is what we mean: all concepts are intended by consciousness (and they 'are never created from nothing'); they are produced by consciousness, and their production will determine their internal structure, the "order without distance" of their internal components. It might seem that these considerations have taken us quite far from any understanding of non-metrical image writing but, in fact, we are pretty much right on top of that here. Once we grasp that every object and event can be a distinct intentional occurrence for consciousness, then we can begin to see how non-metrical image writing can function as a grammatological systemization of experience. Some might object that such intentionalities are subjective; but consider: we have already seen how mental imagery, as the simulation of vision, is exceptionally accurate in maintaining proportions of distance; and we can also make the observation that there is a similar intersubjective quality (or 'equality') of experience to be found in the physical properties of material objects. So, even if we suppose such intentionalities to be subjective, we must then at least consider the possibility of their also being intersubjective...and that is all we need here. For instance: the ancient Taoists used a systemization of knowledge based upon the intersubjective, experiential stability of the physical properties of objects. They used it to preserve their knowledge of the world and of themselves in ways that anyone could understand, forever. They linked their ideas about 'experiential intentionalities' with the observation that any physical, material thing will have distinct phenomenological (perceptual) characteristics for everyone. And, even if there is some slight interpersonal variance as to the precise 'existential intentionality' of any given object, this variance can be mitigated by composing the 'existential intentionality' of material objects into composites of differential occurrence...producing, as it were, "intensive ordinates" with which to define the conceptual essence of thoughts. So, for example, when they wanted to convey what they observed about the nature of, say, 'wisdom' as an attribute of consciousness, they would describe wisdom as "lead in the water of home". What does that mean? Were they saying that putting lead in your water would make you wise? NO! Quite the opposite is true (and this is why both philosophers AND scientists become upset at 'New Age "thinkers"' who confuse scientific functions with philosophic concepts...and why philosophers and scientists do not always see eye-to-eye)! But, if you hold a piece of lead in your hand, you can feel its weight: and you will notice that it is in fact heavier than almost anything else of the same size that you have ever held. If you then lower your hand into water, the weight of the lead is buoyed up a bit. And when you are at home, you feel comfortable. So, the 'intentionality' of wisdom is the same as that of a heavy thing buoyed up by one's feeling comfortable with it: this is 'wisdom' as an intensive ordinate. It isn't the only possible intensive ordinate for wisdom; it is just one which the Taoists used to express how they were thinking (the direction in which one of their thoughts was 'turned toward truth'), and to express this in a way that others could directly grasp. This description of wisdom, as the conceptual presentation of an intensive ordinate, makes perfect sense; and anyone can experience and understand exactly what the Taoists were referring to...even if they don't speak Chinese, or study Taoism. Non-metrical image writing functions to present concepts in much the same way: it doesn't 'translate' ideas into words, it captures intentionalities in the ways that they are related to the actual phenomena physical things are experienced as. This makes non-metrical image writing particularly useful in presenting events, as durations, through intensive ordinates. Thus, anyone can still understand what non-metrical image writing is presenting, even tens thousands of years after it was produced.
Having now a suitable grasp of what a concept is, and how concepts can be understood as durations (through intensive ordinates), we are but one step from a position at which we can indeed (as we have set out to do) place ourselves within the existential and experiential immanences proper to those who created non-metrical image writing so very long ago. Having so defined concepts, we need now only define that to which the production of concepts is attributable: conceptual personae.
"The conceptual persona and the plane of immanence presuppose each other. Sometimes the persona seems to precede the plane, sometimes to come after it - that is, it appears twice; it intervenes twice. On the one hand, it plunges into the chaos from which it extracts the determinations with which it produces the diagrammatic features of a plane of immanence: it is as if it seizes a handful of dice from chance-chaos so as to throw them on a table. On the other hand, the persona establishes a correspondence between each throw of the dice and the intensive features of a concept that will occupy this or that region of the table, as if the table were split according to combinations. Thus, the conceptual persona with its personalized features intervenes between chaos and the diagrammatic features of the plane of immanence and also between the plane and the intensive features of the concepts that happen to populate it : Igitur. Conceptual personae constitute points of view according to which each plane finds itself filled with concepts of the same group. Every thought is a Fiat, expressing a throw of the dice: constructivism. But this is a very complex game, because throwing involves infinite movements that are reversible and folded within each other, so that the consequences can only be produced at infinite speed by creating finite forms corresponding to the intensive ordinates of these movements: every concept is a combination that did not exist before. Concepts are not deduced from the plane. The conceptual persona is needed to create concepts on the plane, just as the plane itself needs to be laid out. But these two operations do not merge in the persona, which itself appears as a distinct operator. In defining the grammatological functions of non-metrical image writing, we noted (with reference to Felix Guattari's "The Role of the Signifier in the Institution", from MOLECULAR REVOLUTION) that a-signifying semiotics and a-semiotic encodings form (anasemantic) functional connections between the matter of content and expression, and the form of content and expression. By so focusing upon function, and thus bypassing any problematic concerns related to questions of meaning, we have also bypassed the intermediary semiological category of content and expression, substance.
|
When we last encountered this category of SUBSTANCE, it was when considering "movement of the infinite" as the truth holding between thinking and being: "...movement is not the image of thought without being also the substance of being." So, perhaps we should begin defining the nature of conceptual personae through an analysis of the linguistic category of SUBSTANCE. In our first derivation based upon these linguistic categories, we identified the SUBSTANCE OF CONTENT as PROXIMITY; and the SUBSTANCE OF EXPRESSION as IMMANENCE.
As important as these considerations are to our definition of conceptual personae, of even more use to us will be the observation noted from the second derivation - that the category of substance is bracketed by VIRTUAL POINTS and PARTIAL OBJECTS.
Meta-stabilities, as a formalization of re-markings (intensive ordinates), can occur as partial objects: and this can range from the territorial, camouflage patterns of animals, to any form of referentially indicative marking.
Thus, whenever we can find any virtual points directly associated with partial objects, we will have found a position which brackets the linguistic category of substance - and which is thus characteristic of 'substance of being', and of conceptual personae.
But, what exactly do we mean by 'points of view constituted by conceptual personae'? It is tempting to say that conceptual personae create points of view; that is the obvious answer. But, it is not necessarily the answer that we need:
"Each one, each subject, for each individual notion, each notion of subject has to encompass this totality of the world, express this total world, but from a certain point of view. And there begins a perspectivist philosophy. And it's not inconsiderable. You will tell me: what is more banal than the expression "a point of view"? If philosophy means creating concepts, what does create concepts mean? Generally speaking, these are banal formulae. Great philosophers each have banal formulae that they wink at. A wink from a philosopher is, at the outside limit, taking a banal formula and having a ball, you have no idea what I'm going to put inside it. To create a theory of point of view, what does that imply? Could that be done at any time at all? Is it by chance that it's Leibniz who created the first great theory at a particular moment? At the moment in which the same Leibniz created a particularly fruitful chapter in geometry, called projective geometry. Is it by chance that it's out of an era in which are elaborated, in architecture as in painting, all sorts of techniques of perspective? We retain simply these two domains that symbolize that: architecture-painting and perspective in painting on one hand, and on the other hand, projective geometry. Understand what Leibniz wants to develop from them. He is going to say that each individual notion expresses the totality of the world, yes, but from a certain point of view. The translation of this series can be found at: GILLES DELEUZES' LECTURE SERIES ON LEIBNIZ; Gilles Deleuze. "Sur Leibniz. April 15, 1980." Gilles Deleuze. "Sur Leibniz. April 22, 1980." Gilles Deleuze. "Sur Leibniz. April 29, 1980." Gilles Deleuze. "Sur Leibniz. May 6, 1980." Gilles Deleuze. "Sur Leibniz. May 20, 1980." (I recommend this entire series to anyone interested in non-metrical image writing; there are many useful concepts here, and they are brilliantly explained). So for Leibniz, points of view define the observer. Can we use this definition? Certainly. To say that a conceptual persona constitutes a point of view does not preclude what Leibniz wants to say; we are simply saying here that planes of immanence are defined by points of view, and that this act of definition takes place through conceptual personae. “Planes of immanence and conceptual personae presuppose each other”…a presupposition which implies point of view. To be precise: planes of immanence are co-extensive with conceptual personae; and such co-extension can be characterized through points of view. One can object that Leibniz is describing an idealist philosophy, which does not include a real, objective world. However, that isn't much of a drawback for us here because, non-metrical image writing presents a world that no longer exists; and, in some cases, a world that hasn't existed for tens of thousands of years. So, in this respect, Leibniz's description of a perspectivalist philosophy works perfectly well for what we want to use it for. Again, we will not be thinking here in terms of ‘subject’ and ‘object’, but in terms of territory and earth. In other words, we will be considering territory and earth as co-extensive, with territory being intended and the earth being extended. For our purposes here, it makes a lot of sense to say that perspectivalistic points of view create positions in which we can localize conceptual personae. Specifically, points of view allow us to define the intensive ordinates through which concepts are defined. Using intensive ordinates to define concepts then allows us to move from durations to event horizons, which are territorial aspects co-extensive with the earth. Certainly, it isn't difficult to see how the perspectivalism of a point of view would first be implicit in the production of diagrammatic features. Or, that every perspective utilizes a virtual point, the vanishing point of its relativizing horizon. This isn't the event horizon where we define concepts; but then, we are not yet working with concepts when we are dealing with diagrammatic features. That comes later. Virtual points are essential to relativizing horizons, and so the points of view that constitute the truths of essence which characterize the earth are always relativizing. Event horizons can be considered to be absolute in that, as with points of view, they are implicit in and define all truths of existence. From this point of view, we might say that conceptual personae are absolutely free relative to the earth (but we would be making a philosophic joke).
It should be noted that we can find many different positions and characteristics for virtual points besides that of perspectival vanishing points. When we move from perceiving singular points (singularities), to perceiving collective (diagrammatic) features that are co-relativized by their proximity to each other, we find that every point which is encompassed by the diagrammatic features of an image, but which is not in itself a singularity, is a virtual point. Here, points of view can be seen to be implicitly presented by the very real nature of extension, by the truths of essence which are characteristic of the earth. Such virtual points, relativized through extension, also tend to shift inclusively at infinite speed when non-metrical grouping patterns are altered (differentially co-relativized).(In that human consciousness is co-extensive with itself, people can be said to be self-conscious. It is self-consciousness which distinguishes that separation found between humans and the rest of the animals; but it is human intersubjectivity that truly defines that which distinguishes humans from all other animals. Such virtual points aren't actually there, as distinct and distinguishable points of sensory contrast; but we are free to think of them as if they were. Similarly, we can also find great variance in points of view as they are related to truths of existence. Here, this variance is most adequately expressed in terms of partiality: in terms of the relativized existence which characterizes absolute differences in kind (between kinds of things, beings, and events). In so thinking such virtual points and partial objects, we are fulfilling one function of a conceptual personae as a 'distinct operator'...as did those people who produced the non-metrical images we are considering. What we are doing here is no less than defining the co-extensive nature of thought itself; and in doing so we are seeking to reconstruct the resonant consistencies that formed of the co-extensions between existential territoriality, and an earth which is essential to any concept of territory. A "distinct operator", as a conceptual persona, is precisely localized in those conceptual functions which associate the virtual points of diagrammatic features with the partial objects that define intensive ordinates.
Thus, whenever we can find any virtual points functionally linked (in a grammatological sense, within non-metrical image writing) with partial objects, we will have found a position characteristic of conceptual personae. (This would, of course, work PARTICULARLY well if one were able to define the virtual points associated with the diagrammatic features presented through a system used in the [First Nations' traditional] mapping of territory; and if one were then to correlate such virtual points with the partial objects associated with the intensive ordinates that are co-presented through an event-language such as non-metrical image writing. Then, we would not only be able to define relevant conceptual personae; we would also be able to construct the geophilosophy which these conceptual personae held in relation to the territories in which they lived. And that, for a post-structural philosopher, would be quite a bit of fun! I think that this would also be of interest to the First Nations, as it would help to explain to non-Aboriginals the traditional role of Hereditary Chiefs). We should also note that for Leibniz, there are two types of truth: truths of essence, which can only be so (as they are); and truths of existence, which might always be otherwise (than how they actually occur). Leibniz is primarily concerned with truths of essence, as they apply to mathematical determinations: and to invariate rules of logical definition as they apply to identity (A=A). Truths of existence, as they apply to contingent situations which are not necessarily as they came to become, are another case altogether. This distinction by Leibniz corresponds to a distinction that we noted earlier, in relation to shifts between event horizons. So, we can say that the inherent nature of temporality, which is common to different event horizons, is of the nature of a truth of essence. Truths of existence, on the other hand, can indeed be contradictory; and this is what (in part) distinguishes between different event horizons. In order for occurrences to be common to an event horizon, Leibniz would say that as truths of existence, they must be compossible. It is not enough for an event to be possible, it must also be possible with other occurrences upon the same event horizon. Thus, with the constructs we have termed meta-stabilities, we often find that the concepts which are co-expressed within a non-metrical assemblage are non-compossible. One pattern of grouping might present a smiling face; another, a frowning face. This demonstrates to us how shifts between event horizons can produce meta-narratives in ways that are more easily determinable than (but subject to the same grammatological rules as) those produced by partial indeterminacies within sensory contrasts. Shifts in event horizons caused by the partial indeterminacies of sensory contrasts are essential, and so relativize conceptual personae by way of points of view; and points of view can be common to absolutely differing event horizons. An indeterminacy of sensory contrasts produces essentially meta-stable assemblages which relativize event horizons; but the absolute differences of separable event horizons express the existential truths of temporal existence. Meta-stabilities present endoconsistencies characteristic to variances in kind, as truths of essence. Event horizons present exoconsistencies characteristic to variances of kind, as truths of existence. Meta-stabilities are assemblages which present the variant structures of event horizons; meta-narratives are differential compositions. Meta-narratives, as compositional, are inclusive of all possible linkages and disjunctions. Thus, the functional effects of partiality are also evident within event horizon shifts localized to meta-stabilities; here, the partiality of objects defines such shifts. It is this partiality which, when expressed as variance of (within) kind, provides the differential shifts found within specifically identifiable event horizons. Partial indeterminacy, however, tends to provide the essential differentiation between event horizons within meta-narratives. Event horizons are the differential variance of transitional phase found in shifts between meta-stabilities and meta-narratives.
As a quick review of what we are referring to when talking about partial objects, let's return for a moment to the section entitled "About Schizo-Analysis", which is appended to the second section entitled "What Is Non-Metrical Image Writing?"...
"So, there is no desire, says Deleuze, that does not flow into an assemblage, and for him, desire has always been a constructivism, constructing an assemblage (agencement), an aggregate: the aggregate of the skirt, of a sun ray, of a street, of a woman, of a vista, of a color... constructing an assemblage, constructing a region, assembling. Deleuze emphasizes that desire is constructivism. Parnet asks if it's because desire is an assemblage that Deleuze needed to be two, with Guattari, in order to create. Deleuze agrees that with Felix, they created an assemblage, but that there can be assemblages all alone as well as with two, or something passing between two. All of this, he continues, concerns physical phenomena, and for an event to occur, some differences of potential must arise, like a flash or a stream, so that the domain of desire is constructed. So every time someone says, I desire this or that, that person is in the process of constructing an assemblage, nothing else, desire is nothing else... Since desire is always an assemblage, its components are always partial. This is to say that any 'object' (or 'conceptualization') of desire is in fact a composite, formed of partial objects. This partiality of objects is an integral aspect of the functional nature of meta-stabilities, and helps to define the compossibility of the event horizons which might shift between various stable compositions within a meta-narrative. And, since partial objects are also characteristic of desire, they can be defined in terms of their inherent intentionalities. This means that partial objects are indeed indicative of intensive ordinates; and this is why they can be used, along with diagrammatic features, in the co-definition of conceptual personae. We can further define shifts in the event horizons found within a meta-narrative, when such shifts are the effect of the partiality of objects, as characteristic of truths of existence. This means that such shifts can be differentiated through the principle of compossibility; and that this principle can be used to define the nature of distinct compositions within the meta-narratives which are produced from meta-stabilities in the formation of differential textures. Shifts in event horizons that are the result of partial indeterminacies within sensory contrasts are characterized by truths of essence. This means that such shifts are defined by logical (necessary) consequence; and as necessary truths, the expressive effects of such shifts are not limited to any particular event horizon. Thus, the differentiations within both meta-stabilities and meta-narratives that are a result of partial indeterminacy within sensory contrasts are held in common throughout meta-stabilities and meta-narratives. They are consistent aspects associated with singularity itself, and structurally apparent through the virtuality of any point which expresses a differentiation within meta-stability or meta-narrative (and thus can be seen to be relativizing).
Such a structurally essential virtuality can occur in many ways: Instead, I will again refer to Deleuze's lecture series on Leibniz, and a very instructive description of the relationship between singularities and sensory contrasts found therein:
We noted briefly in our passing considerations of Husserl and intentionality that the neuro-mechanical parameters of sensory perception functionally structure our conscious expression of desire, as intentionality. So too, truths of essence are structurally implicated in the expression given to truths of existence. Thus virtual points, although distinct from partial objects, co-define conceptual personae; with the virtuality of points being associated with truths of essence, and partial objects with truths of existence. This relationship can further be defined, by expressing matters pertaining to the earth as truths of essence; and matters pertaining to any territory defined upon the earth, as truths of existence. Transitions of territoriality (deterritorialization, as well as reterritorialization) can be either relative, or absolute. Simply put, then, conceptual personae functionally operate within non-metrical image writing as geophilosophers who link the virtual points of diagrammatic features (as truths of essence) with the partial objects of intensive ordinates (as truths of existence). Through this function, they think the linkages that form within their lives between the earth they live upon (as truth of essence), and the territory they define by living within (as truth of existence). As it so happens, this could also serve as a functional description of the traditional role played by the Hereditary Chiefs within First Nations culture. It is not the role played by archaeologists and anthropologists. I should also add here that, by conceptual personae, we are not referring to anything like a Jungian "archetype" or a "Tarot card": conceptual personae are all about DIFFERENCE, not identity; there are no limits to the number of conceptual personae, for they are as infinite as the concepts they are associated with. TO SUMMARIZE: in reading non-metrical image writing, we will be experiencing how the co-extensive nature of consciousness (as expressed through the conceptual personae of those who produced this form of writing) grasped, from the chaos of the real, resonant consistencies holding as co-extensive between the earth on which they lived, and the territorializations through which they lived.
"Subject and object give a poor approximation of thought. Thinking is neither a line drawn between subject and object nor a revolving of one around the other. Rather, thinking takes place in the relationship of territory and earth..."
An Interpretation
An Interpretive Application of Post Structural, Grammatological Analysis, With Reference to an Actual Example of Non-Metrical Image Writing.
|