Artists,
poets and other thinkers an
essay by Jacques
Delaruelle
Originally
delivered as the keynote address of the Double Dialogue conference
in Melbourne, November 1997.
A
few years ago, I was involved in the Art History/Theory Foundation
program that was run at the College of Fine Arts of the University
of New South Wales. There was a very large intake of first-year
students and no adequate lecture hall. So every week, the Foundation
lecture took place in a near-by cinema. It soon became apparent
that there was, among students and staff, a sense of occasion
and excitement about the event. I too enjoyed it, even if my feelings
were ambivalent. For there was something wrong about the circus-like
ambience of these mass-lectures. I remember standing as I now
stand, on the edge of a stage, hoping to disappear behind what
I had to say. My unease, not a matter of stage fright, came rather
from the fact that it was both show time and time for thought:
thought which (in the words of Hannah Arendt) is invisible
and never comes into being except through a deliberate withdrawal
from appearances. (1)
As
one tries to think aloud before a small audience, it is easy to
vanish in such a manner and let the ideas or the work speak for
themselves. But as one faces a larger number of people, it is
more difficult to concentrate on the internal consonance between
ones words and ones thought. Though I do not wish
to ground my argument on the traditional antagonism between thinking
and being, or thinking and doing, I believe that we must remain
aware of their separate history, especially if we wish to posit
a common ground between them. So even if, at long last, the hostility
towards the body that runs through the history of thought is coming
to an end, we still need to make the distinction between theory
and practice. The confusion between them is not equivalent to
their synthesis and does not, as far as I can tell, imply a liberation
from old taboos and fears concerning 'the body.'
There
is no denying that most thinkers who are worth their salt are
also performers. To embody ones thoughts is a necessary
aspect of both research and teaching. We need to live our ideas
and nothing could be less indifferent than the telling of certain
stories by means of which we try to transmit our values, our knowledge
and whatever insight we may have. It is indeed unadvisable to
establish strict boundaries between theoretical and artistic disciplines,
yet it is necessary to distinguish between their respective method
and vocation. I would, however, be most grateful if you did not
hasten to interpret this last proposition as some kind of hang-up
from my French (and therefore assumedly Cartesian) education.
My ambition is not to isolate a pure subject and a pure object
in order to define precise, measurable and immutable truths. And
my insistence at setting theory and practice apart has nothing
to do with the inevitable duality between what people are actually
doing and what people believe they are doing either. A first reason
why the line between theory and practice must be drawn is that
the mutation of thinkers into performers, or its opposite, implies
a loss of concern for the invisibility of thought, which is symptomatic
of a society having reduced the whole communicative process to
a kind of visual happening.
Another
reason why theory and practice ought to be, if not disassociated,
at least understood in their complex relationship is that if both
the artist and the theorist think at work, their thinking is not
of the same kind. In Harold Rosenbergs words: art
is a different way of thinking and the assimilation of the
artists performance to the demonstrable logic of an academic
thesis is bound to debase them both. Creative artists do not follow
theoretical formulae. And when they put a drop of theory into
their practice, or the opposite, they only produce what the chemist
calls an unstable emulsion. Think of an unsuccessful mayonnaise,
or try to put oil in water: the atoms do not mix. It is more or
less the same with theory and art. Why then, is such a mixture
still forced down everybodys throat? For reasons which have
nothing to do with art and everything to do with the superstition
of the dominant tribe. Namely: Economic Rationalism and the principles
of management that have come to define the functioning of our
cultural life. My advocacy today is merely that we, performers,
artists or intellectuals of whatever kind, recognise what is currently
happening to our field and cease to pretend about the reasons
that have forced the migration of the Visual and Performing Arts
into the fold of bureaucratic institutions.
As
the Public Sphere shrinks, so does arts horizon of possibility,
and only a few places are left where it is still possible to base
ones artistic (or intellectual) practice on the basis of
its tradition and history. We know that the academic scholar too
has to justify his or her existence as a public servant and waste
a lot of time playing tedious political games in order
to remain in employment. Most of us have had to compromise and
accommodate procedures or rules that had been defined without
the slightest regard for the specific nature of our métier.
Most of us have had to hide in the different niches that pretend
to shelter the arts against the constructed indifference of our
times. But does the university system still possess the required
independence to be a genuine haven for artists (or intellectuals)?
Having lost its former privileges, it too has to justify its existence
in ways that do not always allow for the kind of hospitality it
claims to be giving!
The
problem is that to judge a work of art or a performance is not
a matter of measurement, but of participation in its movement
or of experiencing of its presence with a feeling of pleasure.
The specific value of this feeling is the outcome. Pleasure is
the outcome, and by 'pleasure', all I mean is 'that which increases
activity'. A 'good' work of art or a 'good' performance is above
all one which defeats our indifference and rekindles our curiosity
for the particular, for the actually-lived experience not just
of art, but of being alive at a given moment. There undoubtedly
is an aesthetic element in the work of certain scientists, but
it is not on it that the judgement of their peers is based. It
is on the manner in which proof is established that certain phenomena
can be repeated (in the laboratory) or understood as being identical
with themselves (i.e. have a conceptual existence). The trend
of the Hybrid created by the exodus of the arts into a mutating
Academe obfuscates the distinction between two manners of thinking
that tend to be mutually exclusive. The fact that the gap between
them ought to be transcended is not in doubt here, only the manner
in which theory-driven art purports to 'subvert' this incompatibility.
In
my field, the visual arts, a number of reasons make practitioners
suspicious of theorists. The most common of them is that a central
function of ideas in art is to place artists under the authority
of non-artists. Beside plumbing the depths of aesthetic phenomena,
ideas in art have a normative function. They implicitly suggest
what artists should or should not do. More dramatically still,
they imply what they should or should not be. It is this overseeing
of the artistic task that practitioners oppose with a feeling
of urgency that increases in proportion to the number of agencies
involved. And as one witnesses this often speechless reticence
towards Academe in the studio, one is reminded of the effort by
Modernist artists to emancipate themselves from more ancient patronages.
For it is not so much the signified content of ideas about art
which is thus rejected by the most independent makers or performers,
but the social relationship implied by them. Though infrequently
argued in the academic manner, this rejection amounts to a critical
response by practitioners who, in the quietest hour of their night,
must realise their metamorphosis into ancillary workers merely
illustrating other peoples beliefs or ideas.
There
is an even more basic cause for the hostility felt by practicing
artists towards theory: a basic conflict of interest between the
few who benefit from the hegemony of Academe in the field and
the many who, on the contrary, must labour under it. Such a social
division of labour makes the proposition that theory-driven practice
is of itself subversive or, on the side of the oppressed, self-contradictory
in the most obvious sense that it reproduces the old hierarchy
at the bottom of which lies manual labour. Historical memories
may obscure the issue, especially since at the origin of this
hypertrophy of the theoretical in the creative arts, one finds
the redefinition of the artist as a member of the intelligentsia.
From the time of its first metamorphosis from crafts person to
para-scientific experimenter, from trusted servant of the Church
or the State to their most conspicuous enemy, the figure of the
artist acquired its intellectual dimension by adhering to the
programme of thought known as the Enlightenment. I am not implying
that the ongoing re-definition (or de-definition) of the artistic
task has gone too far. Yet it is painfully clear that after a
whole century of innovation and crisis, the artistic activity
has lost a great deal of its affirmative powers and become virtually
incapable of reasserting the prerogatives of its tradition.
Naturally
the aversion of practicing artists to the condition of government
employees has led a good many of them to compensate for the loss
of freedom typical of their new working condition with a dream
of return to the terra firma of the studio. The 'back to the studio'
campaign must be understood as a response to a lasting offensive
against traditional values and the politics of de-skilling implemented
in the name of dubious ideologies. But the propensity amongst
practitioners to immerse themselves in the practical difficulty
of their work does not constitute a sufficient response to the
impasse of their cultural situation. As a kind of knee-jerk reaction
to the conspicuous triumph of both Technism and Conceptualism,
such a retreat from the world also suggests that practitioners
are prone to forget the obligation of integrating critical self-awareness
in their activity. Because artists tend to view our technocratic
society as hostile, their work often concentrates on formal relationships
whilst showing definite preference for sentimental (i.e. ideological)
generalities. No matter how different their genre may be, a great
many art practices thus conjure up a picture of life based on
general ideas. It matters little what those ideas are, what matters
is that they are nothing but ideas, emanations from a realm where
no-one ever works, plays, sleeps or wakes up for that matter.
Again,
we must insist that art is a different form of thinking, and one
in which conception cannot precede execution. Its executory
understanding (O. Mandelstam) is neither outcome based,
nor a matter of theoretical knowledge only. It will never be quite
at home in the Academic system, or in the world for that matter.
What is signified by works of art cannot be the translation of
a clear thought without becoming an illustration of that thought
and consequently a non-thought. I do not mean to suggest that
communicable thoughts about art are devoid of referential value,
or more radically still that, art is an incommunicable experience.
On the contrary, art is communicative action par excellence. As
Merleau-Ponty explains:
If a new theory of physics can be proven, it is because
calculations connect the idea or meaning of it with standards
of measurement already common to all men. (But) it is not enough
for a painter like Cézanne, an artist or a philosopher,
to create and express an idea; they must also awaken the experiences
which will make their idea take root in the consciousness of others.
A successful work has the strange power to teach its own lesson.
It
is rare that theoretical knowledge makes us view things for what
they are, but often the experience of seeing things generates
knowledge. In a fascinating passage of The Twilight of the Idols,
Nietzsche takes the above thought a little further: One
has to learn to see, habituating the eye to repose, to patience,
to letting things come to it; learning to defer judgement (
)
this is the first preliminary schooling in spirituality, not to
react immediately to a stimulus
. Such an apprenticeship
is, in its nascent state, a process of attunement and a realisation
of belonging to a kind of natura naturans, the creative process
that defines both being and doing. To say anything worthwhile
about this realisation is difficult and one of the most depressing
features of art writing is precisely the silence it maintains
about it. It is as if art could not exist as an actually lived
experience, but only as a social construct begging to be dismantled
in the name of higher rationality.
The
poets give us a better sense of the reality of art. The words
of Keats, Baudelaire, Rilke, Apollinaire, Char, Paz, Stephens
et tutti quanti, bear witness to this reality and have long since
convinced me that the best art theory is actually art itself.
Poetry lets us touch the impalpable and hear the tide of silence
that covers a landscape devastated by insomnia. Poetic testimony
reveals to us another world within this world, the other world
that is this world. Inasmuch as it is a matter of formulation,
the task of the poet consists in finding the verbal equivalent
for that realisation of presence, for that which has no name because
it is not yet known as such, since no word yet exists for it.
The task of the art theorist is also to allow with words for the
establishment of a contact with art that will trigger the double
experience of feeling and understanding. Only then does it become
possible to speak about the integration of theory and practice.
Initially, only one person is beholding the new 'thing', is alone
in understanding it, or more exactly, as Ortega Y Gasset put it,
alone in understanding it in its new poetic name.
The
poetic name is the one we employ when inwardly referring to something,
when talking to ourselves in secret endophasia (inner speech).
Ordinarily, however, we do not have the ability to create those
secret inner names whereby we would understand ourselves with
respect to things, and we would say what they authentically are
to us. We suffer in our soliloquies from muteness. (2)
The
poets role hinges upon his ability to create that inner
tongue, that wondrous slang comprised only of authentic names.
Such a unique parlance gives poets the means to tell us something
about art that is actually connected with the experience of it.
It permits them to approach the mode of thinking in which the
body provides the vital information that emerges in doing. But
for this to happen, Octavio Paz tells us, language (must)
cease to crawl and rise to its feet and teeters above empty spaces.
(3) What do poets say about the artistic experience? We can not
tell unless we ourselves desert the field where meaning is produced
along the lines of ordinary speech. A leap of faith is required
to believe that in its present state the University system can
house such forms of communication and thinking. Thus my conviction
is that the Creative Arts need their own place to be themselves
again and re-establish the vital contact with their tradition
of practice and thinking. After all, no bird has the heart
to sing in a thicket of questions (René Char).
Notes
1. Hannah Arendt, The Life of the Mind, Invisibility and
withdrawal, a Harvest Book, NY, 1971, pp 76-77.
2. Jose Ortega Y Gasset, The Origins of Philosophy, Norton, NY
,1967, pp 62-63.
3. Octavio Paz, The Double Flame, Essays on Love and Eroticism,
trans. Helen Lane, Harvill Press, London, 1995, p 3.
back
to top