The Politics of Knowing
Shame
Agency in Jiang Jieshi’s
Leadership (1927-1936)
Grace Huang
October 2003
Dissertation Précis
Although
intuitively we know that political leaders can alter the
course of history, we often cannot clearly characterize
how they do so. In part, we are uneasy about actions
that are idiosyncratic and contingent because they chafe
against our desire as social scientists to search
for a more determinate world. We have thus tended
either to ignore the idiosyncratic actions of political
leaders, or to highlight such actions as exceptions to the
rule. In doing so, we often mischaracterize a leader’s
unique contribution to a brilliant or catastrophic decision.
The goal of this dissertation is to develop a more robust
theory of agency (using the case of Jiang Jieshi’s uses
of ‘shame’ in his leadership) to gain a more faithful measure
of individual leadership efforts.
The
case of Jiang Jieshi proves intriguing on a comparative
and methodological basis. Comparatively, because Jiang
drew from both revolutionary and Confucian ideologies for
his leadership, he inhabited structural situations similar
to that of the revolutionary leaders, Sun Zhongshan and
Mao Zedong, and to that of the ‘reactionary’ leader, Yuan
Shikai. Methodologically, I have relied on the ‘diaries’
of Jiang that the Taiwanese government recently opened to
the public in 1997. In painstaking brushwork calligraphy,
Jiang’s secretaries had copied quotations from Jiang’s diaries
and portions of his speeches and telegrams, among other
writings by Jiang. The presentation and content of
this source, properly called the shilue manuscripts,
give us a unique window to understand agency in the Chinese
context.
Chapter
One: Theoretical Framework
First, the chapter focuses on how patterns in the leadership
context enable and constrain the agency of leaders.
To do so, it integrates approaches to structure developed
by Stephen Skowronek (1998) and William H. Sewell, Jr. (1994,
1992) thereby reformulating Theda Skocpol’s (1979) approach
to structure in analyzing Chinese political leadership.
Second,
the chapter examines how we can conceptually separate agency
from structures. Refining and critiquing Emirbayer’s
and Mische’s (1998) work on agency, it first demonstrates
that a leader cannot easily revise his or her agentic orientation.
One who consistently draws on suppressors of rebellions
cannot easily switch to drawing on the rebels. In
addition, unlike practical evaluation (the day to
day decision-making), iteration (selectively reactivating
past experiences, patterns of behavior to condition present
actions) and projection (imagining future goals,
projects, and fantasies that may also condition present
actions) can be situated ‘outside’ of time. An individual,
for example, might cognitively decide that she wants to
quit smoking, but her goal is not reached within temporal
time. This disjunction suggests that a particular
action can be described as being more or less ‘agentic’
depending upon how an individual aligns the cognitively
projected agency ‘outside’ of time and the actively projected
agency within temporal time.
Third,
the chapter theoretically links question of subjectivity
to agency in the Chinese context. The intriguing nature
of the archival materials motivated this inquiry.
Jiang’s ‘self’ rarely appeared. When it did, it appeared
detached in the third person. The chapter therefore
investigates the credibility and authorship of Jiang’s
shilue manuscripts, delineating the manuscript’s
limits and possibilities for understanding Jiang’s agency.
Chapter
Two: ‘Shame’ as Ideological Warrant
Because it is not clear why Jiang drew so persistently on
‘shame’ for his leadership, this chapter outlines the method
by which what one might call the “Confucian self” makes
decisions. Within this Confucian framework, this chapter
argues that ‘shame’ occurs at certain moments, when propriety
[li] has degenerated to where one side of the hierarchical
relationship (i.e. ruler to ruled or father to son) has
lost its standing (and usually it is the inferior side).
‘Shame’ serves a dual purpose of reinforcing or transforming
the script of propriety (i.e. the rules of proper behavior
between superior and inferior). Each side may exert
great effort to reinforce or transform the script to prevent
the relationship from degenerating. But, for various
reasons, ‘shame’ might still occur. This chapter demonstrates
that the standards of ‘propriety’ might not follow the changing
of times; the superior might be overbearing; the inferior
operates with another standard. Because ‘shame’ often
occurs on the inferior’s side, ‘shame’ becomes an important
ideological resource and weapon of the weak to recover standing,
and in the process, further reinforce or transform the script
of propriety. Given the dire circumstances of the
Chinese army and of society, Jiang’s uses of ‘shame’ become
intelligible. Because China was always in the ‘inferior’
position in relation to the ‘superior’ imperial powers that
had transgressed propriety, Jiang appealed to ‘shame’ to
exhort his soldiers and citizens to overcome their dire
situation and to recover their standing in the international
community.<
Chapter
Three: The Jinan Incident of 1928
In Jiang’s first serious confrontation with the Japanese,
where he ultimately abandoned Jinan to the Japanese, Jiang
appealed to Gojian, a historical king during the Spring
and Autumn Period [722-481 B.C.]. In doing so, Jiang
signaled to himself and to his country to be patient, to
endure the humiliation, so that in the meantime they could
self-strengthen, and eventually, avenge humiliation.
The cleverness of drawing on this historical figure was
that Gojian took twenty-three years to avenge humiliation
against the King of Wu. Therefore, Jiang could afford
to avoid the Japanese, and when necessary, concede to them,
in the name of avenging China’s ‘shame’ at a later date.
This chapter explores how Jiang employed the Gojian story
as a template for China’s eventual success. First,
Jiang used Gojian’s ‘lying on brushwood and tasting gall”
to call on the soldiers and citizens to endure the
humiliation and to not strike back or to protest against
the Japanese. By avoiding the Japanese, Jiang aimed
to minimize the humiliation at the hands of the Japanese,
and at the same time, impute strength in actions that otherwise
might be interpreted as passive or weak. Second, Jiang
used Gojian’s ‘pooling the population for ten years and
training the population for ten years,’ to imagine blueprints
for systematically strengthening China. While Jiang
could not actively implement these goals (because he was
busy preventing China’s collapse), Jiang’s plans served
as possible blueprints for when China would be ready to
take positive self-strengthening measures.
Chapter
Four: The Manchurian Railway Incident of 1931
Methodologically, the goal of this chapter is to gage Jiang’s
education as a leader in his second major confrontation
with the Japanese. This chapter demonstrates that
Jiang became more adept at pursuing his negative approach
towards avenging humiliation. In the name of enduring
humiliation, Jiang took the position of nonresistance, noncompromise,
and nondirect negotiation with the Japanese, which allowed
the Japanese to occupy the whole of Manchuria within five
months. In addition, he became more reliant upon the
international situation to solve the Japanese problem.
This chapter argues that Jiang’s continued negative approach,
while understandable given his goals of preventing China’s
collapse, nevertheless further undermined positive outlets
in which the people and the soldiers could self strengthen
to avenge humiliation.
Chapter
Five: The New Life Movement of 1934
This chapter studies Jiang’s second important use of ‘shame,’
as one of the four cords that uphold a moral society.
Jiang’s exhortative speeches, New Life Movement speeches,
telegrams, and daily reflections reveal that Jiang consistently
confronted a profound gap between material resources and
the realization of the ethics of ‘shame’: how were the soldiers
to fight the Japanese effectively if they lacked bullets
for battle, let alone for target practice, and, how were
the citizens to conduct themselves as befitting a strong
moral society when they lacked food, clothing, housing,
and basic transportation? Drawing on the pre-Confucian
philosopher and statesman Guanzhong (ca. 645 B.C.), Jiang
argued that the ethical value of ‘shame’ was more important
than material resources (i.e. the soldier’s moral spirit
was more important than the bullets). To instill ‘shame,’
Jiang started with small changes (i.e. straighten one’s
posture, refrain from spitting), believing that this would
eventually lead to larger changes (i.e. a fearless spirit
to confront the Japanese). This chapter attempts to
explain why Jiang was unable to advance beyond the small
changes.
Chapter
Six: Jiang vs. Yuan on ‘Shame’
This chapter demonstrates that revolutionary leaders such
as Sun Zhongshan and Mao Zedong appeared larger than life
because they based their claims of authority on opposing
a vulnerable ideological regime. By contrast,
Yuan Shikai and Jiang appeared reactionary and weak because
they based their authority on a vulnerable ideological
regime (respectively, Yuan Shikai’s basic continuation of
the Qing Reformist policies and Jiang’s Guomindang ideologies).
In demonstrating that Yuan and Jiang inhabited similar structural
situations that constrained their agency, I then compare
the agency of Jiang and Yuan on their uses of avenging humiliation
(in Yuan’s case, his response to the Japanese Twenty-One
Demands toward China in 1915) to further delineate Jiang’s
unique and creative uses of ‘shame.’