Navigation
Papers by Melberg
Elster Page
Ph.D work

About this web
Why?
Who am I?
Recommended
Statistics
Mail me
Subscribe
Search papers
List of titles only
Categorised titles

General Themes
Ph.D. in progress
Economics
Russia
Political Theory
Statistics/Econometrics
Various papers

The Questions
Ph.D Work
Introduction
Cost-Benefit
Statistical Problems
Social Interaction
Centralization vs. Decentralization

Economics
Define economics!
Models, Formalism
Fluctuations, Crisis
Psychology

Statistics
Econometrics

Review of textbooks

Belief formation
Inifinite regress
Rationality

Russia
Collapse of Communism
Political Culture
Reviews

Political Science
State Intervention
Justice/Rights/Paternalism
Nationalism/Ethnic Violence

Various
Yearly reviews

Philosophy
Explanation=?
Methodology

 

[Note for bibliographic reference: Melberg, Hans O. (1997), What is economics? A method or a topic?, www.oocities.org/hmelberg/papers/971018.htm]

 

What is economics?
A method or a topic?

by Hans O. Melberg


Is it proper to publish a paper on suicide in an economic journal? Should economists avoid explanations (e.g. of unemployment and growth) based on norms and culture? Should economists do empirical work on the mechanisms affecting the formation of beliefs and preferences?

The answer to these questions depend on our conception of economics. If the essence of economics is the analysis of behaviour on the assumption that it is inspired by rational cost/benefit considerations, then even suicide might be within the realm of economics (suicide occurs when the perceived cost of living is lower than the perceived benefits). However, on this view of economics, it would be wrong to bring in norms when explaining economic phenomena. All economic explanations have to be based on the assumption that behaviour is rational. On the other hand, if economics is considered to be the analysis of a set of issues - unemployment, economic growth, inflation, consumption, investment and so on - then norms could well turn out to be an important explanatory variable.

So, we have at least two rival concepts of economics. The first is economics as an approach - a methodology. An current example of an economist in this tradition, is Gary Becker. Building on "the economic approach to human behaviour" he has used cost/benefit analysis to explain crime, the decision to have children, the choice of marriage partner, divorce, and many other non-standard topics for mainstream economists. The second approach, economics as a set of topics - is implicit in R. Solow's 1980 Presidential Address about unemployment, in which norms about fairness was emphasized as a major cause of wage rigidities and hence unemployment. An explicit proponent of the same approach, is R. Coase who writes about "my belief that in the long run it is the subject matter, the kind of question which the practitioners are trying to answer, which tends to be the dominant factor producing the cohesive force that makes a group of scholars a recognisable profession with its own university departments, journals and libraries" (Coase, 1994, p. 38).

I could go on giving examples of economists who belong to one of the two traditions. Steven E. Landsburg, for instance, belongs very strongly to the "economics-as-an-approach-camp." When faced with apparently irrational phenomena like $2.99 pricing (why not $3?), long queues to get tickets to a concert (why not rise the price?), and voting (seldom worth the trouble on a pure cost/benefit consideration) he "insists on finding rational explanation, no matter how outlandish, for all of this apparently irrational behaviour" (1993, p. 11-12). Douglas C. North, on the other hand, belongs to the camp who wants to incorporate norms, culture and institutions into economics, as is evident from his writings about the causes of economic growth.

So, who is right? To answer this, I shall examine two reasons for the somewhat dogmatic adherence to the assumption of rationality.

First, some might claim that irrational and non-rational behaviour (behaviour guided by norms and passions) are not very important. Hence, there is little point in spending a lot of time on a topic which is not likely to explain many phenomena. And, even if the explanatory capacity of our theories could be improved by incorporating non-rational behaviour, we might argue that the gains are illusory. Bringing in new variables always increase our explanatory capacity, as we know from statistical theory (R2 always goes down when we introduce more variables). What we want is parsimonious explanations: to explain as much as possible using as little as possible (Occam's razor). The only way to convince these economists, would be to give concrete empirical evidence demonstrating that norms and passions are important causes of behaviour.

Second, even if one admits that irrationality is not of marginal importance, one could argue that the marginal payoff from spending time on the topic is low. The payoff has two dimensions. First, the increase in the amount of phenomena we can claim to explain. Second, the change in the reliability of our explanations. Now, the traditional economist would argue that bringing in norms might increase the scope of economics, but it might also reduce the reliability of our theories. It reduces the reliability since the causes of irrational phenomena are difficult to quantify. This makes it hard to test the truth of explanations based on norms, and thus it reduces the reliability of our theories. Hence, to show that norms and passions have a place in economics, we must demonstrate that it is possible to quantify and test these theories.

These are valid and good reasons to insist on the assumption of rationality, and to resist the sociologization of economics. It is, however, also falsifiable since its force will be reduced if people can come up with concrete empirical studies demonstrating the importance and reliability of explanations based on norms and passions.

There is, however, also a third option: To retain the supremacy of the assumption of rationality (and the variables of beliefs and preferences), but to extend it to the formation of belief and preferences. For instance, the assumption of rationality should not only apply to the choice of means to achieve a given end (Elster's "thin" concept of rationality). We might also examine whether the beliefs are formed rationally, and - more controversially - whether preferences are formed rationally (Elster's "broad" concept of rationality). Rational beliefs require optimal collection of information and optimal processing of the information (no bias resulting from hot or cold mechanisms such as wishful thinking and cognitive illusions). Rational preferences can be defined as preferences that are not subverted by mechanisms which we, if we were aware of the mechanisms, would not accept. For instance, if I do not want something simply because I cannot get it (the mechanism of sour grapes), then one might question whether my preference has been formed rationally. Using the broad theory of rationality, we end up with what might be called "psychological economics"; a close focus on the psychological mechanisms that actually shape our beliefs and preferences.

Of course, the traditional economists can object to this psychologization of economics. For instance, he might claim that it is perfectly acceptable to take preferences and (less likely) beliefs as given. In short, scarcity of time and space prevents economists from discussing the causes of the variables they are using to explain. There is always a deeper cause of the cause; behaviour can be explained by preferences and beliefs, preferences and beliefs can be explained by psychology, psychology might be reduced to biology (genetics), biology can be reduced to chemistry and so on [The regression might stop here (with chemistry) - unless we include God. As the well known chemist P. Atkins writes: "Because our brains are made up of elements, even our opinions are, in a sense, properties of the elements and inhabitant of the [periodic] kingdom" (Atkins (1995), p. 6)). Hence, to complain that economists do not explain preferences, is not a critique with great force: it is perfectly valid to focus on one step in the causal chain; nobody can discuss everything all the time!

Once again, the argument has some force. At least it presents a division of labour: Economists deal with the consequences of choices given preferences and beliefs, psychologists focus on the formation of preferences and beliefs etc.,. However, there are also good arguments for at least going one step back in the causal chain. As Houthakker writes: "There is much to be said for regarding the explanation of the content of preferences ... as outside the economist's competence. Nevertheless, there is also a danger in such delimitations of responsibility, namely that the problems thus excluded may not be studied at all. It is easy to say they belong to psychology but this does not mean that psychology will find them sufficiently interesting to look into them." (p. 156, in Mason (1988)).

The danger of beliefs and preferences being left unexplained might be exaggerated, but there are some beliefs and preferences that psychologist seldom focus on. Take, for instance, the case of why people believe what they do about free trade. Economists are probably more likely to wonder about this question since they hold opinions that differ greatly from the general public.

As a side-note, one might note that "imperial economists" do not restrict their explanatory claims to behaviour. Also beliefs and preferences can be explained by cost/benefit calculations they claim. As for beliefs, this is a well established branch (rational expectations), but preferences have so far been kept outside (De gustibus non est disputandem). However, lately the economist Gary S. Becker has also tried to explain preferences as the outcome of rational choice (see Accounting for Tastes). [Note: It is perfectly possible to explain preferences rationally, at the same time that you do not make a claim on the rationality of the preference. Whether the cause of a preference is a rational choice is conceptually distinct (but related?) from whether the preferences actually is rational (if such a question can be asked]. So, instead of talking about the psychologization of economics, one might choose a fourth approach: the economization of psychology!

A frame
My discussion so far can be summed up in a diagram:

What is economics?

						Topic
		Economic Behaviour	Beliefs & Preferences	Behaviour in general
..Rationality	Traditional economics	Economic psychology	Imperial economics
Method	
..Norms		Sociological economics	Psychological economics	Traditional sociology

In short, traditional economics tries to answer what is considered to be standard economic questions using the assumption of rationality. The assumption of rationality has also been used to explain beliefs, and lately some economists have taken an even more controversial step and used rational choice theory to explain preferences. I have labelled this approach "Economic psychology". Another development has been the invasion of economists into questions previously though to be outside the realm of economics (interaction in the family, suicide, crime) to produce what is sometimes called "imperial economics", or less pejorative, economic sociology (also: economic political science, such as Public Choice). Some economists, however, complain that the assumption of rationality is not an adequate description of behaviour even on topics considered to be traditional economics (growth, unemployment). To give good answer to economic questions, they argue, we have to bring in norms, culture, passions and institutions. In short, we need more "sociological economics." A related complaint, is that economic phenomena cannot be adequately explained as long as we do not study more closely exactly how people form their beliefs and preferences (not just assume it is done rationally). The study of how non-rational beliefs and preferences are formed and affect the answer to economic question, are labelled "Psychological economics." Finally, there is traditional sociology which tries to explain non-economic topics using norms and other non-rational motivational factors as their main explanatory device.

Now, to ask who is right and where economists should be in my grid, only gives meaning in those cases in which there is a conflict and we have a neutral criteria. There is sometimes a conflict between rational and non-rational explanations of behaviour; but it is not mutually exclusive in the sense that all behaviour either is rational or norm guided. One criteria for judging between the approaches, could be explanatory power (scope multiplied by reliability). If it can be showed empirically that explanations of unemployment based on norms are better than explanations based on the assumption of rational behaviour, then "sociological economics" would be the right approach. Or, conversely, it might turn out that people in general behave rationally, and form rational beliefs and preferences, thus making economics the king of the social sciences. I do not know the answer, and I prefer to hedge my bets by examining both rational and non-rational explanations of the specific phenomenon that I am studying before judging which I think is most plausible.

As for how to judge plausibility, I agree with Friedman that the ability to predict is important, but I do not think this is the sole source of plausibility. I also believe logical considerations should influence my belief in a theory (is it consistent, are the deductive/inductive inferences correct?. Also information, from experiments and/or history, can also give some guidance on the plausibility of theories (e.g. testing the assumption of rational beliefs).


An draft note on sources:
Atkins, Peter (1995), The Periodic Kingdom: A Journey into the Land of Chemical Elements, London: Phoenix
Becker, Gary S. (199?), The Economic Approach to Human Behaviour, Journal of Political Economy (?),
Coase, R. H. (1994), Essays on Economics and Economists, Chicago/London: The University of Chicago Press (Especially ch. 3: Economics and contageous disciplines and ch. 2 How should economist choose? (arguing against Friedman's methodology))
Elster, Jon. (Most of his papers and books!, Especially: Sour Grapes, "Explaining Technical Change and Ulysses and the Sirens. See the Jon Elster Page at www.oocities.org/hmelberg/elster.htm)
Friedman, M. (1953) The methodology of positive economics. In Friedman, M. (ed.), Essays in Positive Economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Hausman, Daniel M. (1992), The Inexact and Separate Science of Economics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

Landsburg, Steven E. (1993), The Armchair Economist, New York: The Free Press
Mason, Roger S. (1988), The Psychological Economics of Conspicuos Consumption (ch. 10) in Peter E. Earl (ed.), Psychological Economics, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Boston, pp. 147-162.
Sen, A. K. (1982), Rational Fools: a critique of the behavioural foundations of economic theory, in Sen A. K. (ed.), Choice, Welfare and Measurement, Ocford: Blackwell
Solow, Robert M. (1980), On theories of unemployment, American Economic Review, vol. 70, pp. 1-11.

Further sources (unread so far)
Blaug, M. (1980), The methodology of economics: or How Economists Explain,
Boland, L. A. (1981) On the futility of criticizing the neoclassical maximization hypothesis. American Economic Review, vol. 71, pp. 1031-6
Dow, A.and Dow, S. C. (1985) Animal Spirits and Rationality. In Lawson, T. and Pesaran, H. (eds) Keynes' Economics: methodological Issues. Armonk: NY: M. E. Sharpe Inc.
Hamermesh, Daniel S. and Soos, Neal M (1974) An economic theory of suicide, Journal of Political Economy (January-February)
Hirschman, A. O. (1984), Against Parsimony: three ways of complicating some categories of economic discourse, American Economic Review, vol. 74 (papers and proceedings), pp. 89-96
Hirschleifer, J. (1985), The expanding domain of economics, American Economic Review, vol. 75, pp. 53-68
Hounthakker, H. S. (1961), The present state of consumption theory, Econometrica, vol. 29, pp. 704-40
Marr, W. and Raj, B. (eds.) (1983) How Economists Explain. Lanham: University Press of America
Rosenberg, A. (1979), Can economics explain everything?, Philosophy of the Social Sciences, vol. 9, pp. 509-529
Stigler, G. J. (1984), Economics: the imperial science?, Scandinavian Journal of Economics, vol. 86, pp. 301-313


[Note for bibliographic reference: Melberg, Hans O. (1997), What is economics? A method or a topic?, www.oocities.org/hmelberg/papers/971018.htm]