Navigation
Papers by Melberg
Elster Page
Ph.D work

About this web
Why?
Who am I?
Recommended
Statistics
Mail me
Subscribe
Search papers
List of titles only
Categorised titles

General Themes
Ph.D. in progress
Economics
Russia
Political Theory
Statistics/Econometrics
Various papers

The Questions
Ph.D Work
Introduction
Cost-Benefit
Statistical Problems
Social Interaction
Centralization vs. Decentralization

Economics
Define economics!
Models, Formalism
Fluctuations, Crisis
Psychology

Statistics
Econometrics

Review of textbooks

Belief formation
Inifinite regress
Rationality

Russia
Collapse of Communism
Political Culture
Reviews

Political Science
State Intervention
Justice/Rights/Paternalism
Nationalism/Ethnic Violence

Various
Yearly reviews

Philosophy
Explanation=?
Methodology

 

[Note for bibliographic reference: Melberg, Hans O. (1999): Consumer theory - As evaluated by three economists: Blaug, Sugden and Hausman, www.oocities.org/hmelberg/papers/990611.htm]



Consumer theory - As evaluated by three economists
Blaug, Sugden and Hausman

by Hans O. Melberg


Blaug: Does the theory yield testable predictions?
The main purpose of the theory of consumer behaviour is, according to M. Blaug, to "justify the notion of a negatively inclined demand curve from fundamental and compelling axioms of individual behavior" (Blaug 1992, p. 140). Unfortunately it turns out that the axioms (see appendix below) are not enough to exclude the theoretical possibility of so called Giffen goods, that is a good for which demand increases when the price increases. The problem is that in theory there is nothing within the axioms that prevent the income effect from a price change to outweigh the substitution effect. One could always argue that at least the substitution effect is always negative after a price change, but this is to loose focus of the real question: how can we justify downward sloping (uncompensated, Marshallian) demand curves theoretically (not just empirically).

Given the fact that consumer theory cannot derive the downward sloping demand curve from individually rational behaviour, one is entitled to ask why we should spend so much time studying the theory. Why can't we just start from the empirical generalization that usually demand falls when price increases without spending a lot of effort learning about the unsuccessful effort to justify the downward sloping curve? This was the position of the economist Gustav Cassell long time ago, and it seems to be close to Blaug's position today. As he writes:

"The Slutsky-Allen-Hicks decomposition of price responses into income and substitution effects, and the invariably negative sign of the substitution effect, are the only substantive achievements of the immense intellectual efforts of literally hundreds of economists applied for a century or more to the pure theory of consumer behavior" (Blaug 1992, p. 141)

Sugden: Three (testable?) implications and was it worth the effort?
Robert Sugden (1992) believes that consumer theory has a wider scope than Blaug. His definition is that "consumer theory is the branch of economics that explains the demand for goods, and in particular, how demands are influenced by changes in prices and income" (Sugden 1992, p. 26). In addition to the usual assumptions, Sugden notes that those trying to establish downward sloping demand curves from assumptions about individual demand, need to use some kind of aggregating assumption. That is, there is no "law" that makes sure that the market demand functions have the same properties as the individual demand functions. A simple example should be enough to convince the reader. A person standing up in a room full of people sitting down gets a better view of whatever is happening on the stage. The same is not true in the aggregate: if everybody stands up they do not all improve their ability to view the events on the stage.

Do the usual assumptions about consumer behaviour lead to any surprising and testable implications? Sugden lists three implications of the axioms. First, if price and income increase by the same percentage there should be no change in demand. Technically this is known as the property of homogeneity. Second, there is the law of demand which states that unless we have an inferior good we can be certain then demand will increase if price decreases. (An inferior good is a good which we want less of as our income grows). Third, there is the property of symmetry. Once again we have to assume away the income effect of a price change. As long as we do this, the assumptions of consumer theory says that the cross-substitution effect between good x and y must be the same as the cross-substitution effect between y and x. Here is an example. Assume the price of cheese increases by $1 pr. kilo. The increased price of cheese may affect the demand of wine, say the demand of wine pr. week falls by 2 liters. This implies that the cross-substitution effect between a change in price of cheese and a change in the demand for wine is: 2 kg. / 1 liter = 2 kg/liter. The property of symmetry then implies that we can use this to predict the change in the demand for cheese if the price of wine increases (as opposed to the demand for wine when the price of cheese increased). In short, if the price of wine increases by $1 pr. liter, then the demand of cheese will fall by 2 kg. Thus, the axioms of consumer theory have at least three implications: homothetic demand functions, the law of demand and the property of symmetry.

The three implications raise two issues. First, Sugden echoes Blaug in "wondering whether all the initial assumptions about the rational consumer were really necessary" since the theory yields so disappointingly few results. In fact, Samuelson has showed that it is possible to justify downward sloping demand curves (and the first two properties listed above) using only the weak axiom of revealed preference (without using the concepts of indifference and metaphysical preferences). Blaug also notes this, but he is very critical of Samuelson's claim that revealed preference theory represents a new and better approach to consumer theory. The theory is no better than the old theory in establishing the downward sloping demand curve.

Second, we could ask whether the implications really are testable. Blaug notes that we never observe only the substitution effect. A change in price always has an income effect and as such the prediction that isolated the substitution effect is always negative is not testable (as implied by what Sugden the law of demand). Rødseth (1992) argues that we also need to assume that preferences are stable in order to test the theory since choices are made at different times. it is not irrational to change your opinions, so preferring x to y at one point in time and y to x at another point in time is only irrational if we also assume that preferences are stable. In short, consumer theory is associated with much work, few implications, even fewer testable implications (unless further assumptions are added), and the same implications are also derivable from alternative theories (even random behaviour produces downward sloping demand curves as Becker has showed).

Hausman: A partially successful effort to provide microfoundations
D. Hausman is less critical than Blaug of the force of the conclusions above. "It would be nice" he admits "to have a quantitative account of market demand, and it would be nice to make use of a less idealized model than that of a simple consumption system …" Still, we have enough, he believes, to argue that "the descent from the level of market generalization to supposed theoretical underpinnings appears to be a success" (Hausman 1992, p. 39). Although it does not produce testable predictions of novel facts (as the Popperian Blaug wants), it does provide a plausible but incomplete microfoundations for aggregate behaviour (which Husman wants).

Conclusion
What does the contrast between these three economists tell us about consumer theory? In three previous essays I have tried to discuss the value of formal modeling in economics. I then claimed that formal modeling was justified if it gave us "surprising" results that were difficult to find using verbal reasoning. Although this criterion is very much in agreement with Blaug, I am more reluctant to accept his conclusions. For instance, I think the discovery of the possibility of a Giffen good is a valuable achievement that was made easier by formalization. One might argue that the theoretical discovery of the possibility of a Giffen good may not be that important if it does not correspond to a real phenomena (and economists have to my knowledge so far not been able to prove the empirical existence of a single Giffen good). This is true. However, one might try to save the theory, as hausman does, by arguing that the point of a theory is not only to produce surprising, true and important predictions, but also to improve the reliability of an explanation by providing the microfoundations on which the macro-theory is build. That is, if an emphasis on individual rational behaviour makes us more aware of the causal machinery that creates downward sloping demand curves. This is valuable in itself. It may not be surprising, but it provides a better justification for the already existing belief that when price increases demand will usually go down.


Appendix
* There are two sets of standards assumptions. First, about the space of feasible price and good combinations - no negative prices or quantities are allowed, perfect divisibility (continuity). Second, we have a set of assumptions about behaviour and preferences - that people act as if they are rational maximizers of utility and that their utility functions have certain properties - always increasing with more goods, diminishing marginal rate of substitutions, independence and so on. If we introduce uncertainty we need to include additional assumptions, such as the rational formation of beliefs.


References
Blaug, Mark (1992): The methodology of economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (esp. ch. 6, The theory of consumer demand, pp. 137-149)

Hausman, Daniel M. (1992): The inexact and separate science of economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Ch. 1 and 2 on rationality and consumer choice)

Rødseth, Asbjørn (1992): Konsumentteori. Oslo: Universitetsforlaget.

Sugden, Roger (1992): "Consumer Theory" in Shaun Hargreaves Heap et al. : The theory of choice: A critical guide. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 26-35.

For a more empirically and macro oriented study, see: Angus Deaton (1992): Understanding Consumption. Oxford: Oxford University Press.


[Note for bibliographic reference: Melberg, Hans O. (1999): Consumer theory - As evaluated by three economists: Blaug, Sugden and Hausman, www.oocities.org/hmelberg/papers/990611.htm]