A Public of Individuals
free art magazine

__________________________________________________________________________________________________________

vol.1no.3 Nov/Dec 2002


Art Is What It Always Was; Art History Is Bunk

byDonald Brook,© 2002

Some of the ideas outlined here, more guardedly qualified and referenced, have already appeared in print as ‘The Undoing of Art History (Parts I and 2)’ in Artlink 21 (No.4, 2001): 66-69 and in Artlink 22 (No.1, 2002): 70-73. Also, as ‘Art and History,’ in Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 60 (No.4, 2002): 331-340, further developed as ‘Art History?’ (forthcoming).
This is an outline of a rather intricate argument. It is a sketch, not an ordnance survey map.

Cultural kinds

The conclusions that are summarised as the title of this essay can not be argued for independently; they hang together on an intricate skein of ideas. Pivotal among them is the notion of a cultural kind, and of the historically shaping power of a generative principle of kindedness.

Kinds are collections. They are not abstract or ‘philosophical’ non-particulars like types or classes. They are more like herds or tribes, enjoying a relatively concrete and precarious temporal existence, buffeted by fate. To invoke the word that distinguishes them most sharply from classes: kinds have histories. A great deal of nonsense is attributable to theorists who have explicitly asserted, or who have implicitly condoned, the proposition that the word art is correctly used when it is used as the name of a kind, of which conventionally so called works of art are (allegedly) the items.

Cultural kinds such as the condom, the piano accordion and the Archibald portrait, are not biological kinds like the broad bean and the fruit bat; although, like biological kinds, they each have a history. Every work of conventionally so called art is an item of some cultural kind. It would be merely truistic to say that each still life with fruit is an item of the still life with fruit kind, if it were it not for the profound implication that the still life with fruit kind has a history. But, as I shall argue, the history that the still life with fruit kind has is a cultural history; it is not an art history. With cultural kinds (just as it is with biological kinds) it does not follow from the fact that each so called work of art is an item of some cultural kind that all so called works of art are items of the same cultural kind, and that this kind is distinguishable from other kinds in such a way that all of the items of all of the cultural kinds have a role to play in a single history.

Biological kinds such as the broad bean and the fruit bat have histories. Nevertheless, they are different biological kinds, and they have different histories. What their histories have in common—what sustains their histories as histories and not as mere stories standing autonomously upon independent foundations—is a common intelligibility given by appeal to a set of common or transcending explanatory principles.

For biological kinds the basis of the common intelligibility of their different histories is located in evolutionary theory. To qualify as a relevant consideration in the history of a biological kind a candidate event must be compatible with a set of generative assumptions: notably, that the history of each biological kind has been shaped by the imperfect replication of parental DNA and by the exposure of items of the kind to environmental contexts within which faithful and variant copies differentially survive to replicate themselves in their turn. The history of the bean is not the history of the bat, but the intellectual constraints upon the teller of their histories are constant. For the biological kinds these constraints are generally Darwinian and are handily collected together under the rubric of evolutionary theory. It is the generative principle of biological kindedness—the chemically coded replication of DNA and the constraints of the environment—that shapes the history of each kind; with different results, case by case.

If we are to speculate as coherently about the histories of cultural kinds—the screwdriver, the wedding ceremony and the Hellenistic terracotta—as we speculate about the histories of the cauliflower and the redback spider we shall need to draw upon a generative principle of cultural kindedness that is fairly comparable to the biological generative principle of kindedness, both in its explanatory power and in the restriction of its range to the appropriate domain of application.

Of course, the generative principle that shapes the histories of cultural kinds can not be the same Darwinian principle as that which shapes the biological kinds. We can not draw upon the imperfect replication of DNA—the genetic story—to account for the shaping of cultural kinds without collapsing together our distinct ideas of biological nature and of culture. Moreover—and more pragmatically—items of the refrigerator kind manifestly have no genes. We are quite sure that this is not a kind that perpetuates itself in the whitegoods factory by sexual congress, or by spontaneous division.

The differential adaptive responses of cultural items to their environments is another matter. The shaping power of context is as influential in the cultural domain as it is in the biological. In a propitious environment such items of a cultural kind as a greeting (for example) can easily be generated. One of the varieties of the greeting kind is constituted by occurrent items in each of which noses are rubbed together. There are unresponsive cultural contexts in which this greeting kind is either unknown or else it is so indignantly discouraged that it finds no foothold. One, at least, of the factors determining the history of a cultural kind—the projection of its items into a propitious context—is in direct analogy with the workings of the generative principle of biological kindedness. Despite this analogy, however, we need an answer to the parallel question of replication. How are relevantly similar items of a cultural kind perpetuated in such a way that new items, replete with onward-transmissible imperfections and variations, come to be reproduced generation after generation?

Imitation

The answer to this question is in one way obvious; in another way it is obscure. Plainly, the persistence of cultural kinds is somehow attributable to imitation. Something is imitated by those cultural participants who are the users of items of cultural kinds. Imitation is the key, but what lock does it turn? It is far from obvious what it is, precisely, that is imitated by cultural participants. Theorists in this domain—the domain that is now fashionably called memetics—are inclined to make one or the other of two disastrous mistakes. They are likely to say that cultural kinds are imitated by cultural participants, and that cultural kinds are the imitable and imitated memes—let us take advantage of Dawkins’ felicitous term—whose onward transmission perpetuates the kinds and gives them their histories. Or else these theorists—and sometimes, inconsistently, they are the very same theorists—say that items of the various cultural kinds are imitated by cultural participants and that these things—the items themselves—are the imitable and imitated memes whose replication perpetuates the kinds.

Both of these claims are incoherent. Kinds, conceived as memes, can not possibly be held responsible for their own perpetuation. In spite of this, such cultural kinds as the screwdriver and the calendar feature prominently among the examples given by respondents when they are called upon to exemplify a meme. The suggestion that the screwdriver is a meme is an inchoate category error, comparable to the claim that the fruit bat is the very gene whose replication perpetuates the fruit bat kind. Nor can memes be identified with items of cultural kinds. To make short work of the argument we need only substitute demonstrative terms in an otherwise identical reductio. The suggestion that this (holding a screwdriver aloft for inspection) is a screwdriver meme is precisely analogous to the absurd suggestion that this (holding a fruit bat aloft) is a fruit bat gene.

Memes

I propose, quite differently, that the meme is a behaviour-in-context such that an item of an identifiable cultural kind is, as matter fact, normally generated by performing it. For example: there is a context (a very complicated context, certainly, and difficult to specify in detail) such that, as I know, if I raise my hand in just this context I shall more often than not succeed in generating an item of the cultural kind that we call a greeting. There is a quite different sort of context such that, as I know, if I raise my hand in this (other) context I shall more often than not generate an item of the cultural kind that we call a vote. There may not be any differences, obvious to a spectator, in the way I seem to be raising my hand in the two cases; and the unwary may even be tempted to say that my behaviour is the same. But this temptation should be resisted. Behaviours-in-context are by no means mere behaviours. The internal and generally unseen bodily components of the progress of such different performances as greeting by, and voting by, hand-raising, as the progress of each is internally monitored by the performer, are radically different.

It is my contention that memes are intimately related behaviours-in-context, performed in such a way as to sustain a justifiable expectation among cultural co-participants that an item of an identifiable and predictable cultural kind will thereby be generated. For a clear case: the handraising-in-context that is regularly generative of a greeting is a meme that we might call (if we insist upon having a name for it) the greeting-by-handraising meme. The different behaviour of handraising that is, in its own context, generative of a vote is another meme entirely, that we might characterise as the voting-by-handraising meme. Both memes are learnt by imitation. As participants we are tireless watchers and copiers of our co-participants in the shared culture. The successful teaching of children is massively achieved by displaying memes and by encouraging their imitation. ‘Look! This is how we make a sandwich. This is how we make a primed canvas. This (raising an eyebrow) is how we make an ironic face’. And so on.

A competently participating child will imitatively acquire many thousands, perhaps millions, of memes. By adulthood she will have acquired the knack of combining sequences and combinations of memes so seamlesslessly that she is able to generate, intentionally, not only an item of an elementary cultural kind such as a greeting by handraising. She may well have the sophistication to generate an item of such a rare cultural kind as an altarpiece in three panels in the manner of Pietro Lorenzetti, dedicated to the virgin in parody of the cult of Kylie Minogue. Similarly—to reinforce the analogy with biological kinds—do a myriad of genetic bases on strings of DNA combine and sequence themselves to generate a cabbage.

Skill, intention and accident

Memes are behaviours-in-context that are regularly, reliably (and hence predictably) generative of items of established cultural kinds. A purposeful command of the common stock of memes is learnt by imitation, and the cultural kinds are perpetuated by competent cultural participants. A cultural kind may be rigid to the extent that its memes are simple and lend themselves to quasi-mechanical copying with little variation. The assimilation of memes may, indeed, be so regular and widespread that in relation to a few of them—for example, in the generation of such cross-cultural kinds such as the eyebrow-flash of recognition—there may well be a case for conceiving of their acquisition as a genetically hard-wired disposition, rather than as a purely memetic acquisition.

But let us try to keep the question simple; first distinguishing biology from culture before seeking to re-join them. Cultural history would be a less interesting topic than biological history were it not that the perpetuation of cultural kinds is at no less subject to variation. Indeed, because of an element of arbitrariness in the adoption or rejection of new memes (shall we or shall we not decide to make a fashion statement by preferring pastel colours this year?) culture might be regarded as more radically plastic than nature. For a variety of reasons and in a variety of ways memes can be inexactly imitated, and cultural kinds can be perpetuated with such florid variations that emergent kinds may speciate more profusely even than plants and animals. Cultural histories are probably more— and certainly more rapidly—marked by innovation than are biological histories.

It is a corollary of this conception of the meme that the intentional use of memes (in the commonsense meaning of the term ‘intentional,’ equivalent to deliberate) is possible. We can make an omelette intentionally just because, and only because, we know that we are very likely to generate an item of the omelette kind if we begin by breaking eggs.

Simple skills, using elementary memes, are combined into more broadly based and elevated skills. At the tops of memetic pyramids there are the superlative skills of virtuoso pianists, portrait painters and microsurgeons. Products of skill are recognised, and they are widely admired, as evidence of their performers’ ability to marshal imitatively acquired memes toward the generation of items of the most sophisticated cultural kinds. In spite of this we are well aware that a great blessing of life—its creative unpredictability—is attributable not so much to the exercise of skilful deliberation as to the accident of discovery. To borrow the sense of the title of a painting by Joseph Wright of Derby: it is the alchemist in search of the philosophers’ stone who discovers phosphorus, not the mediaeval phosphorus-seeker (who knows of no such element).

In the mode of intentional action we use those memes that we expect will yield an item of the X-kind and we occasionally discover, to our gratified astonishment, that some accidental variation of behaviour has occurred, or there has been some anomaly of context, such that an unintended, unexpected, item of the Y-kind has instead been generated. And very occasionally the Y-kind may qualify not as a mere variant of the intended X-kind but as a new kind entirely. Nobody—or anyhow, none of our co-participants in the local culture—knew that things of this kind could be made. But now they know how. A new meme has emerged.

New memes

Discoveries are not made memetically, although once they are made the productive new memes are freely available for exploitation. Discoveries are not, as is sometimes claimed on their behalf, the products of skills so high and fine that their authors deserve adulation as the possessors of an inimitable genius. Discoveries are necessarily accidental. The secret of creativity is not after all so very mysterious. We stumble upon the possibility of new behaviours-in-context with unexpected but regular consequences. We do this incidentally to the purposeful doing of something else. Important discoverers no doubt deserve to be celebrated, but not for their display of inimitable skill. There are no inimitable skills.

What is it, then, that makes intentional, memetic, action possible? Standing behind every meme we must suppose that there are universal regularities without which repetitive behaviours-in-context would not have predictable consequences. Part of the delight that attaches to the discovery of a new meme is surely attributable to the contribution that each one makes to our practical and intellectual grasp of the mysterious regularities of the universe. It is essentially a metaphysical delight, and it is no wonder that creativity—when it is understood in this way—is much appreciated. We should rather wonder why it is that theorists have tried to associate creativity distinctively with conventionally so called art, when it is so clearly manifest in every domain of human interest.

Entertainments

A possible explanation comes to mind. It is a plausible thought that memetic innovation is most likely to occur when the standard use of memes to generate familiar cultural items is observed by spectators who are free—as the performers are relatively unfree—to ‘misread’ what is being intentionally made and done. Such ‘misreadings’ may well be repudiated by the performers, but in spite of this they may be no less viable accounts of what might have been done, and of what might therefore be done again, than are the performers’ own readings upon which their claims to have acted deliberately rest.

Those activities and products of action around which bystanders are assembled with an assumption of personal detachment have a general name. They are called entertainments. Classic entertainments make provision for a non-participatory audience, quarantined in the auditorium of a stadium, a theatre, a concert hall, a gallery or circus tent. Entertainments are prime sites of memetic innovation precisely because the bystanders’ productive readings—or, as one might prefer to say, their felicitous mis-readings—of what has been made or done and of how it might be made or done again is significantly out of collusion with the entertainers’ intentions.

A story of this kind about the potency of entertainments is to some extent consistent with the familiar post-Kantian art-theoretical dogma of disinterestedness; but it parts company with such teachings in that it does not pretend to offer a criterion by which the artistic domain is to be distinguished from the scientific or the economic or the political or any other domain. Why, indeed, should we expect to find such a criterion? Why should we not instead abandon the use of the term ‘art’ that is currently conventional and revert to an older and more general use, in which its application is indifferent as between domains? Demotic speech still encourages us to speak of the surgeons, chefs and criminals who stumble upon powerful new memes as artists; and there is no reason why this usage should not be restored to its earlier, still vestigial, status as the literal and not the metaphorical use of the word.

Art is what it always was

In short, current linguistic practice had much better be modified in the following ways. First: the word ‘art’ should not be used as the name of a kind for the absolutely knock-down reason that there is no such kind. It should be used instead as the name of the category of memetic innovation.

I offer the word ‘category’ here because, although its meaning is contested among philosophers, it is at least clear that a category is not a kind and that, unlike kinds, categories do not have histories. Memetic innovation—the discovery of new ways in which the regularities of the universe can be consistently and predictably exploited—is what it always was. Memetic innovation is, was and always will be, memetic innovation. Without memetic innovation we should live in a culturally frozen universe, just as without genetic innovation we should live in a biologically frozen universe. Hence, in my proposed use of the term: art is what it always was. It has no history. Art history is bunk. When she ruminates upon the history of the archaic Kouros or of American-type abstract expressionism the so called ‘art historian’ is functioning as a cultural historian, elucidating the histories of cultural kinds all shaped by a common generative principle of cultural kindedness. She should be free to do this without the impossible burden of elucidating concurrently the history of something else that has no history, popularly mis-called the history of art.

This adjustment to our use of the term ‘art’ forces upon us the need for a better way of dealing with the cognate expression ‘work of art’. Currently we try, incoherently, to speak of works of art as if they were items of an art kind despite the fact that because there is no such kind there are no such items. I suggest instead that we should understand ‘work of art’ in the following way:

Works of art are those things to which attention is paid in the hope that reflection upon them may deliver up to a disengaged contemplator the prospect of some memetic innovation.

The conventionally so called works of art that are collected for many different reasons in the art galleries and the art museums are not, of course, disqualified absolutely by their status as works of art conventionally so called from counting as works of art properly so called. In the same way, objects of innumerable cultural kinds bundled together in various ways beyond the domain of conventionally so called art are not disqualified by their exclusion from counting as works of art properly so called.

This was Duchamp’s point, I imagine; although he did not spell it out explicitly. Or if after all this was not his point, then it should have been.

 

back to top

vol.1no.3 Nov/Dec 2002

__________________________________________________________________________________________________________

Copyright 'A Public of Individuals' © 2002-Copyright and Disclaimer Statement