A Public of Individuals
free art magazine

__________________________________________________________________________________________________________

vol.1no.3 Nov/Dec 2002

Return to the real world: a reply to Richard Larter

In our last issue Richard Larter offered some thoughts on the art world, politics and thought itself. Here, Chris Jones responds.

“We guess by analogy” (1).

To answer the question “Is the real world real?" Richard Larter created his own and termed it the “art world”. In a muddled flip of writerly irony, he sought to expose the benefit of perception active within the practices of art by gleaning authority from the abstract world of “scientific facts”; a rigid domain of static perception functioning antithetically to lively acts of artistic perception. In a manner reflecting the argument structures used by economic and political bureaucracies so rightly raising his ire, Larter engineered an “art world” by manufacturing an argument filled with abstract “societies” and fictitious “theys”. To do so, he first poured into the argument’s mould the great unwashed “ours”, “us” and “we” of conventional analytic research, (characters who only befriend fictive analysts tenured high within ivory towers: see Jean Baudrillard et al). When full, he then sculpted each new resident into neat and trimmed points arranged carefully within the growing body of his text. When ready, he rounded the finished piece to form an article finally representing the shiny sphere of an “art world”. But Richard, to whom were you referring when describing the ”we”, “suffering from being considered unimportant”? Who were the “we” of the “art world” that “stupidly imagine” democracy for instance? (To stupidly imagine is perhaps the first step in any worthwhile artistic project, and an effective technique whilst engaging seriously un-stupid, un-imaginative, political practices). And who were the “our” whose collective “mental activity” you claim to know the “truth” about? Finally, who were the “us” you perceived continually lied to by “fourth rate Presidents, Prime Ministers, Ministers and Government officials”? When was the last time Bush, Howard, Kemp or Keating lied to you; when was the last time they even spoke to you? The “art world” you created to succeed as an argument certainly doesn’t include me and I consider myself one of the many gallery ghosts who’d expect a swift invite to its opening. By couching your claims within rhetoric floating high upon clouds of assumption, you raise serious, challenging and I hope popular issues, surrounding the vital topic of perception within the practices of contemporary art. To point out just a few of these issues, and hopefully generate discussion around this topic, I will refer to your article that raised them, (published in vol.1, no.2 of A Public of Individuals), as case study for mine.

Throughout your argument you privileged the elitist mode of perception sustained by Cartesian dualism, an inherently authoritarian structure raising intellectual minds above the ambiguities of their supposedly unthinking, untrustworthy bodies. For example, from the fixed locality of your writing station you perceived “our extremely ignorant and imperfect world”. How did you do this from the fixity of a seat? Only with a detached mind’s eye perceiving information through a telescope, forged by the hand of Galileo perhaps, could you survey with such a broad vision. Extending this privilege to dualism you added, “We do not know how we think – this is a scientific fact”. Scientific fact is thought, what else could it be? Scientific facts are thoughts written as words into books and computers. They present as terms demarcating abstract themes and authoritative explanations; they are concepts and ideas interpreting, and wholly distorting, the sensational world of things and objects. To argue “we do not know how we think” because this is what science thinks is to extend self-reflexive, circular arguments spun by rationalists installed high inside towers of academe, set fast to their seats in long forgotten postures, warmed through by the romantic glow of a two-bar heater and pumped full with the rarefied oxygen of idealism. What these and other examples from your article expose is a lack of subjective awareness in the process of analytic perception; in other words, you disregard the I in your eye. This disregard, all too common within analytic research and writing, forms a gap between the perceiver and the perceived creatively filled by abstract thought and concepts; concepts which are wholly divorced from the details of life in order to sustain bold discussions about manufactured “worlds” dis-located far from their actions therein. These actions, full of blood, shit, sweat and moments of real reality manifest paintings, installations, interactive environments, photographs, textiles and performances. These are the responsible marks from the grounds of the living earth; embodied interactions of subjective dialogue presented within the moving acts of artistic practices, not practice concretised within the fixity of an abstract “art world”.

My want to expose your body from the process of thoughtful perception may seem a rather odd intention. But it is only by admitting the multi-sensorial function of the body into the process of perception that one can responsibly and accurately analyse phenomena perceived: it is also the only way to fully embrace perception within the processes of art. By admitting the body to the process of perception you, as analyser of objects perceived, are compelled to a direct and lively relation with the “facticity” of the object as Maurice Merleau-Ponty would write. Consequently, during perception, you become bound to an awareness of all the influences effecting that facticity as they correspondingly interact with your nearby perceiving body; influences affecting the process of remembering as it brings to mind thoughts of childhood sight for instance. These influences might involve the colour, speed and proximity of the locality in which you’re remembering; the shape, line and contour of your body whilst in the posture of remembering; perhaps the temperature surrounding and interacting with you as each memory arises; or even the mood in which you’re in whilst remembering. By admitting your wide and lively body to the process of perception - your I to your eye - you are bound within a fascinating and responsible interaction within the variegated life of the object’s perception. If, on the other hand, recourse to the fiction of rational authority is relied upon to attain meaning from the thing, all you will perceive, as layers added to the thing, will be hackneyed dusty themes; concepts regurgitated from a tome or google searched web-site destined to “excite the mind” of your reader, as Descartes would write. This application to the thing with abstract interpretation is the antithesis of artistic perception, sensing momentary freshly essences within the lively living “thingness of the thing” as Heidegger would write. Instead, like fetish applied to an old wooden cross, it is the essential project of power.

Power’s project is the control of the perceived thing through authoring its explanation and interpretation. It relies upon talking loud and effectively to others about things unperceived, in the way I’m writing here and now with this buzzing screen through words about intimate thoughts and feelings that, as marks on the distant page you now perceive, control your attention whilst reading. Power is inserted between perceiver-thing relations by an author controlling explanation and interpretation of the thing perceived. This control, usually inserted as the filter of language, allows an author with intent to authorise the process of explanation and interpretation and thereby argue that what is perceived is actually an example of something else or, in certain cases, is something completely different. An example of this process is evident when a “salesman” explains an assemblage of metal and paint as interpreting a dream machine fuelled by freedom. Similarly, it was evident when “The Australian Government”, (abstraction par excellence), explained images of what appeared as people, motionless in a small area of water, as interpreting illegal acts involving a particular racial group of men “throwing children overboard”. These images, in their thingness, were simply photographs that, if perceived as such and without the filter of authority; that is, in an aesthetic manner, would have read as such. Consequently, the “readers” of the images would not have been engulfed by a redneck tide, interpreting them as proof of murder, and thereby voting accordingly. By explaining the “children overboard” images as interpreting murderous activity, the government displayed a clear act of attempting to authorise perception, thereby exposing a desperate attempt to claim the reins of power. But, if the readers had perceived them in an embodied manner as signs laden with significant and immediate meaning triggering a direct personal response; not an indirect impersonal response controlled by government, destined perhaps for presentation on a canvas, on a textile, on a video-wall or through action at the gates of Woomera, the mind-games of control exercised by the government would not have gained control of any personal, embodied perception and actions that follow.

But it’s these mind-games that sustain your argument Richard. By claiming a meaning exists out there somewhere in an “arts world” is to repeat an idealistic, intellectual and therefore dis-embodied analytic process of perception, authorised on high from the vestige of some crumbling ivory tower. When the presence of an ideal is presented as replacement for an absence in meaning at the object perceived, in the form of an image of “child murderers” or a group of “us” and “we” termed an “art world”, it suggests the presenter of that ideal perceives the bodily-perception-of-individual-subjectivities under analysis; people that is, as unnecessary to that process. Consequently, the people under analysis need not exist to be written about. This wholly unethical and arrogant process of creating meaning for the purpose of argument, dis-located completely from the field of people’s experience, enables authoring systems to control the explanation and interpretation of non-existent things within that field, indefinitely. Consequently, if the systems of idealistic manufacture are maintained by the language machines of religion, economics, politics and conventional academe, they will argue perpetually, with heightened power as their target, there’s always more to life than meets with the body; it’s just that you can’t see it. And to this convenient equation they will perpetually add, as they already do, if there is more to meaning than perceived by the body then it’s controlled by an unperceivable entity on high; a god, a profit margin, a truth or ideal; all meta-authors of unperceivable contexts installed within the dwelling of some meta-unperceived. But how can there be more than is perceived? How can there be more to a perceivable world than meets with a perceiving body?

1. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, Routledge, 2002, p.481.

back to top

vol.1no.3 Nov/Dec 2002

__________________________________________________________________________________________________________

Copyright 'A Public of Individuals' © 2002-Copyright and Disclaimer Statement