A cost-benefit analysis
of different treatment programs for drug addicts: Theory and application
Project
description by Hans O. Melberg
1
Introduction: The general problem
Every year
billions of dollars are spent on different programs for addicts. In the US, for instance,
$1.3 billion (1987 dollars) was spent on treating drug addicts in the US (French, 1995:
113) and in Norway it has been estimated that about 1 billion NOK a year was spent on
treatment of alcohol addicts in the late 1980's (Waal,
1996: 10). At the same time very little empirical research has been conducted on the
relative efficiency of the many different treatment programs (cost-benefit analyses).
Moreover, after a review of some of the few studies available, a leading researcher in the
field concludes that "no study" has followed the recommended set of important
methodological guidelines - such as tracking patients over time to avoid biased measures
of effectiveness due to readmission or examined the possibility that doing program A after
program B produces different results than the reverse option (French, 1995: 131, 120). In
short, there is a gap between our current knowledge and the knowledge we should have to
justify the allocation of large sums of money. The purpose of the dissertation is to make
a contribution towards closing this gap.
The starting
point of the dissertation is the following simple question: "From a cost-benefit
perspective, which treatment for treating drug addicts is the best?" This main
question, in turn, leads to a large number of sub-questions: Is cost-benefit analysis the
correct way of deciding the matter? How do you define addiction? What should count as
costs and benefits, in what units, and are these units interpersonally comparable (so they
can be aggregated)? Is it enough to collect data about the different treatment programs
and do the appropriate statistical calculations (the black-box approach), or is it
necessary to discuss theories about drug-addiction (theory-approach)? Indeed, what is
meant by "best?"
It is not the
purpose of the dissertation to discuss all the questions above in detail. The dissertation
is part of a larger project at the National Institute for Alcohol and Drug Research (SIFA)
financed in part by the Norwegian Research Council and different questions are allocated
to different researchers in the team. In the proposal below I have therefore indicated
which themes which I want to emphasise as opposed to those questions on which I will be
strongly guided (although not uncritically) by the research of others.
2 Preliminary
questions
Some of the
questions on the list above can be labelled "conceptual preliminaries". It is,
for instance, not obvious that all questions of public policy money should be guided by
cost-benefit analysis. As an illustration ask yourself which group of victims you should
help after a plane-crash (The example is inspired by Elster, 1992: 92). Should you help
those who are most wounded (but likely to die anyway), those who have moderate injuries
(who have a greater change of surviving if given treatment) or those with non-lethal but
painful injuries which are easily curable? The
utilitarian answer is simply to focus on those patients that will maximize social welfare
(people in the second category?). Against this a pure "rights" or norm based
ethic might tell us to first attend to those who are worst off. It is not obvious that the
pure utilitarian solution is the "best." The same kind of logic also applies to
drug treatment. Even if cost-benefit considerations tell us that it would be
"best" to leave the heavy users to themselves without trying to help, this need
not be the policy that is "best" if we include ethical considerations.
A second
conceptual preliminary concerns definitions and classifications. The problem of defining
addiction may be more acute when it comes to gambling and other forms of claimed
addictions (for an overview of possible addictions, see Ainslie, 1992: 3-4), but even with
drug addiction there are ambiguities. Is a person who occasionally has used
"mild" drugs during the past four months a drug addict? The second problem -
that of classifying different treatments - is one of those areas in which I will rely on
previous research. Based on this research the project has identified five major different
treatments that need to be distinguished: a) traditional inpatient treatment (24 hours);
b) hierarchical therapeutic units; c) collectives; d) psychiatric youth teams; e)
methadone treatment. This can be collapsed to a distinction between inpatient treatment
(a, b, c) and outpatient treatment (d, e) and one of the aims of the research is to
examine whether the rather expensive inpatient treatment is better than the less expensive
outpatient treatment. Some previous research - for instance on alcohol abuse - suggests
that the net benefit from inpatient care is not large enough to justify the heavy emphasis
this type of treatment has received compared to outpatient treatment (French, 1995: 121).
Whether this is the case in Norway and in the context of drug addicts is an important
research question to be answered.
The third,
and perhaps most crucial conceptual preliminary, is an identification of the costs and
benefits. This depends among other things on the type of analysis one wants to conduct:
Cost-benefit, cost effectiveness and cost-utility analysis (see Nygaard, 1996). This is an
area in which much theoretical work has been done, but fewer studies actually follow up to
do applied work. Regardless of the type of analysis, there are some obvious costs and
benefits associated with the different treatments (and non-treatment). The direct costs
include the salaries to the staff involved and the fixed cost of buildings and so on. The
benefits of treatment (to the extent it works) include improved ability to participate in
work, reduced health expenses, and reduced outlays to prison incarceration (for a full
list of possible costs and benefits, see French, 1992: 115)
Even if we
ignore the practical problems of identifying and estimating the size of the costs and
benefits, there are many difficulties at this stage. One example is the problem of
including non-monetary costs and benefits. For instance, how should we include the utility
of a cured addict as a benefit? This is difficult to measure in monetary terms
(willingness to pay?) and as economists we might even believe that removing drug from an
addict reduces her utility; Since she used it
voluntarily her utility must be higher with drugs than without (revealed preference
theory). Alternatively one might invoke some theory of a multiple self or hyperbolic
time-discounting to explain why a person does something he "really" does not
want.
Another
problem related to the measurement of costs is that we should use opportunity costs, not
monetary outlays. Thus, the true cost of the staff is not their salary, but the best use
we could make of the staff if they were not occupied treating drug addicts. Usually it is
much more difficult to find the true opportunity cost than the monetary outlays.
A third
problem is the tendency to ignore the difference between marginal costs/benefits and
overall costs/benefits. When faced with an institution that simply cannot be closed for a
few years, then it is irrelevant in the short run that the overall net benefits in this
program is lower than in an alternative treatment program. The relevant variable in the
short run is marginal net benefit: Can we get a better result by moving some resources
from one program to another. To give an example: Institution A might have unavoidable high fixed cost due to a
housing-contract. This implies that A has a low
overall net benefit compared to another institution (B). It does not, however, imply, that it is
better to give an additional 100 000 to B rather
than A. It is perfectly possible that
institution A has a higher marginal net benefit
at the same time it has a lower overall net benefit compared to institution B. Although this reasoning is rather obvious to
economists who have a rich appreciation of the different cost concepts (fixed, variable,
opportunity, accounting), it has not been obvious to the professions that have dominated
research on addiction so far (medics, psychologists, sociologists). In sum, more applied
research on the relevant marginal net benefits in contrast to the more common overall net
benefits, can produce valuable knowledge for policy makers.
Important as
they may be, the conceptual preliminaries mentioned above will not be the main focus of
the thesis. Some of the questions are well covered by other research (different
cost-benefit frameworks and variables), some are fixed parameters outside my control (like
the fivefold division of treatments in the larger project) and some are simply too
peripheral to be the main focus, although they do need to be discussed. Instead the main
focus will be on the following two issues: A critical analysis of original survey data and
a discussion of how to model addiction.
3 Analysing
survey data
As mentioned
the dissertation is part of a larger project that has already started. One of the main
elements of this project is a large survey of 400 drug addicts in different treatment
programs. The participant will be interviewed every year for four or five years. The
respondents are asked questions about the treatment they receive, the severity of the
addiction (measured by the Europ-ASI - Addiction Severity Index), psychopathological
profile (using standardised indexes such as such as MIO, MCMI, BCI and BDI) and important
life events like marriage, religious conversion, pregnancy and childbirth.
One of the
main dangers when working with surveys of this kind, is that of drawing policy conclusions
based on spurious correlation. For instance researchers in the 1940s found a strong
correlation between cirrhosis of the liver and vitamin deficiency (the example is from
Skog, 1992: 49). Based on this they claimed that liver cirrhosis was not caused by alcohol
(since after controlling for vitamin deficiency alcohol intake explained very little). The
conclusion also implied that taking vitamins (without reducing alcohol intake) would
prevent cirrhosis. Today we know that their conclusion was wrong and based on spurious
correlation. Because of the importance of this phenomenon, I propose to make the problem
of how correlation can lead to wrong conclusions a major focus in this section. This
necessitates, first, a conceptual discussion about the difference between causation and
correlation. Second, for every important correlation found in the survey it is necessary
to test and examine whether it is spurious. Third, the reasons for spurious correlation
found in the second part should be systematised with the aim of creating a more general
theory of the reasons why reliance on correlation leads to wrong results (and how it can
be avoided).
On the
conceptual issue, the starting point is Hume's theory of causation as "constant
conjunction" (The following discussion draws upon Beauchamp & Rosenberg [1981],
Elster [1989, ch. 1] and Skog [1992]). Hume knew, however, that this was not enough since
a third variable can make two variables appear together without being causally related.
This led Hume to propose two criteria for separating correlation and causation. The first
is inductive support; that is whether the relationship holds under a great variety of
circumstances. Second there is predictive confidence, which includes the degree of
theoretical support behind the correlation (knowing why
there is a correlation as opposed to simply knowing that
there is a correlation makes us more confident that the correlation is not spurious).
One problem
for Hume could be the following (based on
information in Dawkins 1995): In 1973 Karl von Frish's won a Nobel prize for his discovery
that the complex bee-dance communicated where the bees could find food. Against this
Adrian Wenner argued that it was a mistake to believe that the dance was a form of
communication. He did not deny than the dance showed both the direction and the distance
to the food source, but he denied that the other bees were able to understand this. The
last - and final - participant in this debate was James L. Gould who designed an
experiment that proved that the dance in fact transmitted information to the other bees
(by blinding the dancing bee and using a light bulb to fake the sun's position). To make a
long story short (for more, see Melberg, 1997), the flight path of the bees after these
experiments showed that the dance transmitted information. How many examples of this do we
need to generalise? Although we do not have enough examples to claim that there is a
"reliable constant conjunction" a few (even only one?) experiment of this type
is enough to convince working scientist of the "communication hypothesis" as
opposed to the "no communication hypothesis." (Melberg, 1999a and Skog, 1992:
39-40, provides additional examples of "generalisations based on one example")
Where does
this leave us when it comes to distinguishing between causation and correlation? The main
conclusion is simply that more research is needed. The bee-dance example may lead us to a
Bayesian theory of belief formation, in which the "degree of surprise" is given
importance when new information makes us update our beliefs. Whether it is possible (and
desirable) to use Bayesian theory to form beliefs about causation remains to be proved,
but it is one of the issues I intend to explore.
Consider the
second and third point mentioned above - using the survey to develop a list if possible
causes of spurious correlation and then using this to create a more systematic theory. As
a preliminary categorisation, I have listed 18 reasons why an emphasis on correlation may
lead to wrong conclusions (see Melberg, 1996a). These causes, in turn, can be categorised
in the following four groups:
a) Strong
correlation but no causation
(1.
accidental, 2. common cause, 3. intervening variable, 4. pre-emption)
b) No
correlation but strong causation
(5.
third variable effects, 6. lags, 7. non-linear relationships)
c)
Correlation and causation but of unknown direction and type
(8. wrong
direction inferred, 9. ignored joint relationship, 10. wrong kind of causation, 11.
self-confirming correlation, 12. confusion between short run and long run effects)
d) Data
problems leading to wrong conclusions
(13. few
observations, 14. not enough variation, 15. too much noise, 16. flawed assumptions about
underlying distribution, 17. measurement errors, 18. ignored non-quantifiable variables)
This is very
much a draft and further work may well demonstrate more useful categorisations and
different examples. It would require more space than I have to list examples of all 18
problems, but some of those which are most relevant to the current project are listed
below (see the already mentioned paper - Melberg 1996a - for examples of all).
Imagine that
the survey shows that outpatient treatment is generally associated with better result than
inpatient care. It could be very wrong to conclude from this that inpatient treatment
should be closed and all addicts assigned to outpatient care. The reason the conclusion is
most likely wrong is that the "heavy" addicts may be assigned to inpatient care,
while the "light" addicts are assigned to outpatient treatment. Given this
sorting mechanism there is no wonder why outpatient treatment performs better; they
receive the easiest cases to treat. In this case the reason behind "strong
correlation no causation" is obvious, but in other cases it is much less obvious and
it is an important task to try to sort the spurious from the more reliable correlation.
Even less
obvious are the mistakes we make by assuming that no correlation means no causation. Take
the following example (from Dawes, 1994: 59): Research has shown (weakly) that the
compatibility of the therapist's and the client's views on the causes of alcoholism is
important for the effect of therapeutic treatment. If both the client and the therapist
believe alcoholism is caused by genetic disposition (the disease model) or if they both
believe it is a "bad habit" (no genetic disposition), there is a greater chance
of success than if they have different views. Schematically we have the following (Diagram
1):
Diagram
1: Compatibility of therapists and clients views and outcome of treatment
|
|
Therapists' view on the causes of alcoholism |
Clients' view
|
|
Genetic |
Not genetic |
Genetic |
Successful treatment |
Not |
Not genetic |
Not |
Successful treatment |
If we assigning
a random sample of clients to a random set of therapists, we might end up with no
correlation between treatment and successful outcome. Still, it would be wrong to conclude
from this that treatment is a waste with no effect. In fact, there are strong but opposing
causal forces at work. The positive effect of treatment when the views are compatible is
balanced by a negative causal effect when the views are incompatible. Ignoring this
produces the wrong conclusion, while taking it into account can lead to a dramatically
improved result - that we begin to assign clients to the therapist that is most likely to
produce success with that particular client. When it comes to drug addiction, Edle Ravndal
(1986) has described some potential reasons why the same treatment may have different
effects on different clients - such as the age and gender of the client, whether there is
a record of criminal activity, the degree of personality disorders and other
characteristics. In the dissertation I intend to follow up on these suggestions and test
empirically whether the aggregate "no correlation" really hides "strong
causation" at a lower level of aggregation. One simple way of doing this is to
perform multiple regression analysis of the characteristics against an index that measures
success in treatment, but more complex analysis is also necessary (by subdividing the
sample based on the variables we believe are important).
One of the
aims of the survey, as stated in the original project description, is to reveal whether
the different combinations of treatment produce significantly different results. This aim
may run into the last problem mentioned on my list - data problems. Briefly, when we have
five different treatments there are at least 120 different possible combinations.
With a set of 400 respondents and 120 possible combinations there is not enough data to
tell whether the different combinations produce significantly different results. In
practice, however, one might expect that not all combinations are equally likely, and this
may make it possible to test at least some different combinations. On the other hand (as
explained in the footnote) 120 is really a minimum of theoretical possibilities and if we
include "no treatment" as a possible option at all times, then the number of
possible combinations increase to 720. This leads to two conclusions - one challenge and
one warning. The challenge is to devise statistical methods to reduce the problem - for
instance, if we can assume that the "BC" in "ABC" can be compared to
"BC" in DBC" we will increase the number of observations. The warning (both
to the politicians and academics that want these results) is not to expect too many strong
results to emerge from this kind of analysis.
It is well
known that a focus on correlation can lead to wrong conclusions. Indeed, it is about 75
years since Yule published the first article dealing with spurious correlation. The topic
was then "lost" for a period of time, but recent development in econometrics
have renewed the interest in the topic of how we should proceed to avoid spurious
correlation. For instance, David Hendry's strong criticism of Milton Friedmans theory of
inflation - which Hendry claims is based on a
spurious correlation - has led to the development of a set of systematic methodological
recommendations to avoid spurious correlation (for more on Hendry's specific
recommendations, see Gilbert, 1986). Another examples of the renewed interest, is
McCloskey and Ziliak (1996) article in which they warn against confusing statistically
significant correlation with practically significant correlation. Yet, although it has
long been known that correlation and causation are different, this general knowledge is
often not matched by specific effort at the applied level of testing whether the
correlation is spurious or not. Moreover, this failure is likely to lead to bad policy
recommendations. That is why I will make it a major focus in the dissertation, both when
it comes to applied and theoretical work. Hopefully this can lead to some novel techniques
to reveal spurious correlation as well as improved knowledge about the problem of spurious
correlation in drug research (For an overview of existing techniques to reveal spurious
correlation in research on addiction, see Skog, 1988).
4 Modelling
addiction
As mentioned
above, there are two approaches to cost-benefit analysis. The first was labelled "the
black box" approach i.e. one simply tries to measure the costs and benefits without
discussing the theory of addiction. The section above then described some of the
weaknesses of this approach and this leads to the second alternative - that of basing your
cost-benefit analysis and policy recommendations on a model of addiction and treatment
(the "theory approach"). The reason for focusing on this approach is not that
the first approach "fails" and that this leaves us with the second (as if
theoretical and empirical work is incompatible). Rather the argument is that knowing why a correlation exists reduces the risk of
accepting a spurious correlation (see Melberg, 1996b). This was already emphasised by Hume
(in his criterion of confidence to distinguish between correlation and causation), and it
was emphasised by Hendry who, as one of his methodological demands, require that variables
we included in the model must be "theory consistent" i.e. we do not add
variables when we have no theoretical reason to believe they are relevant. Thus, one
reason why we want to model addiction is to make sure that our correlations are not
spurious.
Given that we
want to model drug addiction, how should we do so? There are several models available (see
Godfrey [1989] for a review of economic models of addiction), but it is possible to
categorise these models along two key dimensions. The first is whether they model
addiction as the outcome of rational choice or not. This, in turn, has important policy
consequences - if addiction is viewed as rational then the "treatment" is simply
to change the incentive system facing the agent. The second distinction is whether the
model emphasises interaction as opposed to assuming a "representative agent."
There are, of course, other relevant distinctions (such as models based on brain chemistry
vs. those who view addiction as a "psychological problem"), but this is outside
my competence.
4.1 Should
addiction be modelled as the outcome of rational choice or not?
The classic
argument in favour of the rational addict model, is presented by Gary Becker and Kevin
Murphy (1988). In short, people decide to use drugs when the expected utility of doing so
is larger than the expected utility of not doing so (the possibility of addiction is
included in the calculation). The original project description presents a model of
addiction that comes close to this view (SIFA, 1997). In that paper addicts are viewed as
acting on a Lancaster-type consumption function with preferences for two types of
characteristics: basic needs (food, housing) and experiences (whatever produces
self-esteem, feeling of community). The "experiences" can be produced by taking
drugs, but it can also be produced by friends, family and important life events. In this
perspective the demand for treatment need not be motivated by a desire to really quit, but
rather to satisfy basic needs for a period of time (since they receive free housing and
food).
Becker's
theory of rational addiction is useful as a starting point, but there are also important
weaknesses in his theory. One could, for instance, attack his definition of rationality.
As I have discussed elsewhere (Melberg 1998, 1999b, ch. 2) rationality demands not only
that the action be optimal for a given set of beliefs. It also demands that the beliefs
must be optimal for the given set of information AND that the amount of information must
be optimal. Hence, although one might agree with Becker that taking drugs may be rational
for some people given their beliefs (e.g. if she believes she is strong enough to quit
whenever she wants), but one might question whether these beliefs are optimal given the
evidence and even if this is the case one could ask whether the amount of information used
to form the belief was optimal. Unless all three conditions are satisfied it is not
correct to label addiction "rational" in any substantive sense.
Even if we
ignore the conceptual problems related to Becker's definition of rationality, Elster has
presented one key criticism that goes to the heart of the model (see Elster 1997 and 1999:
160-164). Becker argues that non-monetary sources of utility, such as guilt and shame,
should be included when agents calculate the expected utility of various actions. This is
fairly standard reasoning for those who include "psychic" utilities. In the
words of Elster (1999: 160): "Among economists, the most common way of modelling the
interaction between emotions and interests is to view the former as psychic costs or
benefits that enter into the utility function on par with satisfactions derived from
material rewards." Elster believes this is fundamentally wrong and presents the
following example to support his argument: "If guilt were nothing but an anticipated
or experienced cost, an agent whose guilt deters him from stealing or retaining the book
should be willing to buy a guilt-erasing pill if it were sufficiently cheap. I submit that no person capable of being deterred by
guilt would buy the pill.
For him, taking the pill in order to escape guilt and
be able to steal the book would be as morally bad as just stealing it
A person
willing to take the guilt-erasing pill does not need it." (Elster, 1999: 161,
emphasis in the original).
Where does
this argument lead us with respect to how we should model addiction? According to Elster
(1999: 161) we "need a model that can account for the trade-off between guilt and
interest and yet does not imply that a reluctant agent would buy the guilt-erasing pill. I
conjecture that the model would involve some kind of nonintentional psychic causality
rather than deliberate choice." As an example of such causality, Elster mentions how
the psychic mechanism of cognitive dissonance can be introduced to explain asymmetries
that rational choice theory cannot deal with.
I do not want
to conclude at this early stage that Elster is correct and Becker is wrong. I simply want
to indicate that this is one of the issues where more research is needed. Elster's
argument must be scrutinised closer and in any case his model can be viewed as an
extension rather than a radical new approach. Both Becker's and Elster's starting point is
that agents are mainly rational. The difference is that Elster also wants to include
non-intentional causal forces in the model to capture psychic costs/benefits, while Becker
wants to model this in the usual cost-benefit framework. And, even if Elster's approach is
best, there is still the challenge of formalising his verbal arguments.
4.2
Modelling: Interaction vs. representative agent
Since the
assumption of a representative agent usually makes it much easier to handle models
mathematically, this has traditionally been preferred above explicit modelling of
interaction (see Kirman [1992] for more on this and a harsh attach on the representative
agent assumption). Although this may work fine in some situations, there are some
phenomena which seems to require the incorporation of interaction. An early example of
this recognition is Schelling's (1978: 147-155) model of the housing market. Another
example is S. Bikhchandani, D. Hirschleifer
and I. Welch's (1998) theory of fashion, fads and customs. Until
recently, however, addiction had not been modelled using this approach, although important
aspects of addiction clearly depend on social interaction. An agent's decision to use
drugs may be heavily influenced by whether his friends use drugs (if there is a desire to
conform) and the social stigma attached to the drug (which in turn may depend on how many
people use the drug).
The first
formal model that captured some of the social interaction effects in research on
addiction, was created by Karl Ove Moene (1999) who explicitly says that he "focuses
on long-range equilibria of social interaction within a group of persons and neglects
additive dynamics within each person separately" (Moene, 1999: 30). The key feature
of the model is that one person's utility depends on what the other people do; all other
things constant an agent has higher utility if she does what the others do (drink when
they drink; abstain when they abstain) i.e. there is a desire to conform. The agent's
utility also depends on his pain or pleasure from the drug itself and the size of this
pleasure/pain differs from agent to agent. Based on this Moene shows that the model most
likely has multiple self-enforcing equilibria, that there is hysterese (the history of
drug addiction matters to explain the current number of addicts) and that there may be a
tendency for drug addiction to go easier up than down.
What are the
implications of including interaction effects in our models for conclusions about
treatment? One conclusion is that the aggregate effects of small changes may be difficult
to predict. If the system is non-linear (exhibits hysterese) and there are thresholds
beyond which the system switches to a new equilibrium, then small changes can have large
effects (and large changes may not have any effect - depending on the staring point). It
becomes almost impossible to estimate and predict the aggregate costs and benefits of
treatment based on (linear) correlation alone (see Skog, 1992: 54). There is, however, a
large step from a pure theoretic and stylised model to a policy conclusion like this. The
model has not been tested or quantified (although it is compatible with some basic facts -
such as changes in consumption patterns for no apparent reason except "fads").
This implies that more work should be done on the formal modelling of these systems and
whether they are compatible with the central historical facts about addiction.
Exactly how
should one go about modelling systems in which agents interact? As mentioned it is often
difficult to model complex interaction in a mathematical model. One alternative that could
be explored in a dissertation is computer simulations (see Skog, 1980, for a review of
computer simulations in the field of addiction). This, in turn may provide valuable
lessons for modelling beyond the field of addiction. By using computer programs we can
specify the characteristics of the agent, the nature of the environment, rules for
interaction and watch as different scenarios unfold. This approach allows for a richer
characterisation of the agent (e.g. allowing agents to be influenced by mechanisms like
wishful thinking or cognitive dissonance). In short, computer modelling allows the agent
in our models to be more like real individuals and it enables us to capture more realistic
aggregation procedures than merely assuming that one agent is representative for all. One
area in which this approach could be useful (beyond addiction), is to explain economic
fluctuations which seems to involve important interaction effects as well as not perfectly
rational agents. This does not imply that I believe computer modelling necessarily will
succeed or that it will "solve all our problems." It does mean, however, that I
believe the approach deserves to be investigated further in a dissertation dealing with
addiction.
5 Practical
issues
To create the
dissertation I intend to write several articles that can be published separately, but at
the same time be united in a coherent thesis. The planned list of articles is: 1. The
limitations of cost-benefit analysis; 2. Reasons for spurious correlation and how to avoid
them; 3. Modelling drug addiction using computer simulations; 4. Addiction - rational or
not, and is that the question? This is, of course, a preliminary plan and if future
research throws up more interesting questions or reveals that some of the topics are not
very fruitful (this applies particularly to article 3) the plans will be changed.
The work on the dissertation will start in January, year 2000. Whether the
dissertation will take three or four years depends on the workload imposed by SIFA. I
intend to spend at least one term abroad - more specifically at York University which has
a department that is engaged with a project very similar to that at SIFA. During my stay
there I also intend to take a course in health economics. Finally, I intend to continue my
education is statistics by taking courses at the University of Oslo.
6 Conclusion
Research on
addiction poses important questions. From a policy perspective it is important to know
more in order to determine what kind of treatments the state should provide. From an
academic perspective it poses important statistical challenges - such as how to avoid conclusions based on spurious correlation. Finally
it raises important questions of modelling - about how we can capture complex social
interaction and less than perfectly rational agents and still retain the discipline and
precision of rigorous modelling. I am aware that to some extent there is a conflict
between the need for policy recommendations and a focus on the problem of spurious
correlation conflict (Why focus on the problems, we want answers!). When faced with this
conflict it is important to be willing to admit that "I do not know" is
sometimes the scientifically correct answer. The main purpose is not to produce policy
relevant conclusion, but to produce conclusions that are scientifically valid.
References
Ainslie,
George (1992) Pioeconomics. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Beauchamp,
T.L. and A. Rosenberg (1981) Hume and the problem of
causation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Becker,
Gary and Kevin Murphy (1988) "A theory of rational addiction", Journal of Political Economy, 96: 675-700.
Bikhchandani,
Sushil and David Hirschleifer and Ivo Welch (1998) "Learning from the behaviour of
others: Conformity, fads, and informational cascades", Journal of Economic Perspectives, 12 (3): 151-170.
Dawes,
Robyn M. (1994) House of Cards: Psychology and
Psychoterapy Build on Myth. New York: The Free Press.
Dawkins,
Richard (1995) River Out of Eden: A Darwinian View
of Life. New York: Basic Books, New York.
Elster,
Jon (1989) Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Elster,
Jon (1997) "More Than Enough: Accounting for Tastes" (review of Becker), The University of Chicago Law Review, 64: 749-764.
Elster,
Jon (1999) Strong Feelings: Emotion, Addiction, and
Human Behavior. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.
Gilbert,
Christopher L. (1986) "Professor Hendry's Econometric Methodology", Oxford Bulletin of Economics and Statistics, 48:
283-307.
Godfrey,
Christine (1989) "Factors Influencing the Consumption of Alcohol and Tobacco: The use
and abuse of economic models", British Journal
of Addiction, 84: 1123-1138.
Kirman,
Alan P. (1992): Whom or what does the representative agent represent?, Journal of Economic Perspectives, 6, 117-136.
McCloskey,
Deirdre and Stephen T. Ziliak (1996) "The Standard Error of Regressions", Journal of Economic Literature, 34: 97-114.
Melberg,
Hans O. (1996a) "Against correlation: 18 ways of confusing correlation and
causation", www.oocities.org/hmelberg/papers/960415.htm
Melberg, Hans O. (1996b) "Tre
årsaker til urettferdigheter", Lov og Rett,
no. 8: 471-499
Melberg, Hans
O. (1997) "Bees, marbles and generalizations based on one example: A reflection on
the concept of statistical significance", www.oocities.org/hmelberg/papers/970117.htm
Melberg, Hans O. (1998) "Et
forsvar for antagelsen om rasjonalitet", Impuls,
52: 27-37.
Melberg, Hans O. (1999a) "Kommer
russerne fra Mars? Om bruken av kultur som forklaringsvariabel i russisk politikk", Norsk Statsvitenskapelig Tidsskrift, no. 4:
313-337.
Melberg,
Hans O. (1999b) "A critical discussion of Jon Elster's arguments about rational
choice, infinite regress and the collection of information", unpublished thesis,
University of Oslo.
Moene,
Karl Ove (1999) "Addiction and Social Interaction" in J. Elster and O-J. Skog
(eds.) Getting Hooked: Rationality and Addiction.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 30-46.
Nygaard, Elizabeth (1986)
"Samfunnsøkonomiske problemstillinger ved rusmiddelbehandling" in H. Waal and
F. Duckert (eds.) Behandling av rusproblemer -
nytter det og hva koster det? Oslo: Rusmiddeldirektoratet og SIFA, pp. 15-28.
Ravndal, Edle (1986)
"Klientforskjeller - betydning for behandling og evaluering" in H. Waal and F.
Duckert (eds.) Behandling av rusproblemer - nytter
det og hva koster det? Oslo: Rusmiddeldirektoratet og SIFA, pp. 67-78.
Schelling,
Thomas C. (1978): Micromotives and Macrobehaviour.
New York, N.Y.: W. W. Norton & Company.
SIFA (1997) Hvilken nytte? - for hvem?- og til hvilken kostnad?: En
prospektiv multisenter studie (Prosjektbeskrivelse), Oslo: SIFA.
Skog,
Ole-Jørgen (1980) "Social interaction and the distribution of alcohol
consumption", Journal of Drug Issues, 10: 71-92.
Skog,
Ole-Jørgen (1988) "Testing causal hypotheses about correlated trends: pitfalls and
remedies", Contemporary Drug Problems, 15:
565-606.
Skog,
Ole-Jørgen (1992) "Correlation and causality: notes on epistemological problems in
substance abuse research" in M. Lader, G. Edwards and D.C. Drummond (eds.) The Nature of Alcohol and Drug Related Problems.
Oxford, Oxford University Press, pp. 37-59.
Waal, Helge (1986) "Hva koster
nytten og hva er nyttig kostnad?" in H. Waal and F. Duckert (eds.) Behandling av rusproblemer - nytter det og hva koster
det? Oslo: Rusmiddeldirektoratet og SIFA, pp. 9-14.
Yule
George U. (1926) "Why do we sometimes get nonsense correlations between
time-series?", Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, 89: 1-64.